Skip to main content

Full text of "The Open Philosophy And The Open Society. A Reply To Dr. Karl Popper's Refutations of Marxism"

See other formats




THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY 
AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


By the same Author: 

DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM AND SCIENCE 
READERS* GUIDE TO THE MARXIST CLASSICS 
SCIENCE VERSUS IDEALISM 

DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM, AN INTRODUCTION! 

Vol. I. Materialism and the Dialectical Method 
Vol. 2. Historical Materialism 
Vol. 3. The Theory of Knowledge 

MARXISM AND THE LINGUISTIC PHILOSOPHY 

With J. D. Bernal, 

SCIENCE FOR PEACE AND SOCIALISM 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY 
AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 

a Reply to Dr. Karl Popper’s Refutations of Marxism 


By MAURICE CORNFORTH 



INTERNATIONAL PUBLISHERS 


NEW YORK 


Copyright © Maurice Cornforth 1968 


Library of Congress Catalogue Card Number: 68-27395 
Printed in the United States of America 


FOREWORD 


The object of this book is to discuss fundamental ideas of Marxist 
philosophy and their implications for social theory and socialist policy. 
My premise is to accept Marxism as essentially a scientific outlook 
which seeks to work out and test ideas and policies, in all spheres, in 
accordance with the canons of rational scientific discussion and in no 
other way. 

I have chosen the method of constructing this book as a reasoned 
reply to criticisms of Marxism. And of all the critics, I have picked on 
a single one, Dr. Karl Popper, as the one to answer. I have done this 
because Dr. Popper's whole case against Marxism rests on his con- 
tention that it is nothing but a system of dogmas, so that his arguments 
against Marxism provide a ready-made and accommodating peg on 
which to hang the argument that Marxism is, on the contrary, a 
rational scientific discipline. 

There is the more reason for a Marxist to tackle the case put against 
Marxism by Dr. Popper because not only is he perhaps the most 
eminent of our contemporary critics, and not only does he present 
his case with great ability and force, but because, so far as I can judge, 
the points he makes against Marxism include practically all the main 
points against it which carry most weight in contemporary debate. 
Of course, some of his arguments (for example, those he directs against 
Marx’s Capital , or again, against the theory and practice of socialist 
economic planning) are borrowed from arguments originally put 
forward in greater detail by other critics. However, I have preferred 
to stick throughout to tackling the case as put by Dr. Popper rather 
than encumber the discussion with references to the writings of others 
who have put the same case before or since. Dr. Popper’s arguments 
against Marxism are extremely comprehensive, and it is high time 
someone tried to answer him in detail. 

Dr. Popper himself occupies an unchallengeable position in modem 
letters as an exponent of principles of scientific method. His contribu- 
tions in this sphere, first in his famous book Logik der Forschung 
(published in English under the title Logic of Scientific Discovery) and 
then in numerous articles in English and American journals, have had 
and continue to have a great and beneficial influence on modern 
thought. I would like to emphasise that I do not seek to attack or refute 
all that Dr. Popper has to say about science or about society. On the 
contrary, I accept and agree with a good deal of it. This book is not a 


6 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


polemic against Dr. Popper, but an answer to his polemic against 
Marxism. I am seeking only to answer his charges and (as the sequel 
will show, this is often the right word) smears against Marxism, so as 
to make as clear as I can what Marxism really stands for, and to show 
that a rational and scientific approach to social problems (which 
Dr. Popper professes to demand) lends support to Marxism. 

Dr. Popper has popularised in sociology and politics the use of the 
word “open”. In the title of this book, and in the discussions it contains, 
I have ventured to borrow it from him. A society is “open” when 
there is nothing to stop individuals, if they choose, from developing 
their abilities and personalities to the fullest extent, and when social 
institutions are so ordered that they can be changed and developed, by 
decision of the members of society, in any way that will assist indi- 
viduals to live more fully and more freely. On the other hand, it is 
“closed” when the members of society are bound by rules and regula- 
tions, conventions and prejudices, strictly enforced, which restrict 
their choices and impose on them a pattern of life rigidly limited by 
institutions which may not be changed. 

The open society and progress towards the open society demand 
(so Dr. Popper declares, and I agree with him) an open way of think- 
ing, characterised by rationality as opposed to blind belief in dogmas. 
For the open society we need an outlook which rejects dogmas and 
judges things only on the basis of evidence, always ready to think 
again when experience falsifies earlier conclusions. This I have ventured 
to call an “open philosophy”. 

Dr. Popper’s objection to Marxism is that he imagines it to be a 
closed philosophy, a system of dogmas, what he calls “a reinforced 
dogmatism”. And inevitably, so he maintains, the Marxist dogmas 
enjoin a corresponding closed attitude in social life — the imposition on 
society of rules, regulations, tyrannies of custom, enforced by political 
tyranny, which effectively close for individuals, and for society as a 
whole, all the avenues of free development. 

But, one may ask, is a society really “open” when social production 
is tied to ensuring the accumulation of capital from surplus value, and 
the enjoyment of benefits and privileges by some depends on exploiting 
the labour of others? And can one’s mind be really “open” so long as 
one is unable to see that such is the case with contemporary capitalist 
society, or to see the possibilities of advance which could be opened 
up for mankind if only the exploitation of man by man were done 
away with? So far from Marxism being a system of dogmas to close 


FOREWORD 


7 


our minds and discourage the unfettered exercise of reason to work 
out how best to promote freedom and the brotherhood of men, it 
systematises a way of thinking to open our minds to the appreciation 
of things as they are and the practical possibilities of changing them 
for the better. 

The open way of thinking is the way of thinking which bases itself 
on demonstrable rules for finding out how things are, and which 
strives to appreciate, therefore, the actual conditions of our material 
existence and the necessary conditions for changing them — which 
therefore closes the mind to misrepresentations and dogmas, and opens 
the mind to the real possibilities of human life. That is why I have 
called the philosophy of Marxism “the open philosophy” and the 
communist society towards which Marxism directs our sights “the 
open society”. 

A good deal of this book is controversial — not only because I engage 
in a controversy with opponents of Marxism but because there is 
controversy within Marxism itself. Inevitably, to answer the objections 
of opponents, especially the kind of objections Dr. Popper makes 
about Marxism being a dogma and the policies it advocates policies 
of dictatorship and tyranny, involves discussions which are contro- 
versial as among friends. In this connection I cannot but conclude this 
Foreword by acknowledging a particular debt of gratitude to R. Palme 
Dutt, who read through most of this book in the form in which I first 
drafted it. I alone am responsible for the point of view I express and 
for such unclarities and fallacies as may be found in it. But by his 
critical observations he helped me on several points to make it more 
clear and, I hope, more cogent than it would otherwise have been. 


London, October 1967 


M. C. 


Digitized by the Internet Archive 
in 2010 


http://www.archive.org/details/openphilosophyopOOcorn 


NOTE 


Dr. Popper's anti-Marxist writings are contained in three of his books, 
from which I have quoted extensively. For this purpose I have adopted 
the following abbreviations in references to them: 


The Open Society and its Enemies , Vol. i i-OS 

Vol. 2 2-OS 

The Poverty of Historicism PH 

Conjectures and Refutations CR 


Page references refer to the fourth (revised) paperback edition of 
The Open Society and its Enemies, 1962; to the paperback edition of 
The Poverty of Historicism, 1961; and to the original edition of 
Conjectures and Refutations, 19 63. 






















. 





































CONTENTS 


PART ONE: TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 

Chapter i: THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF page 17 

MARXISM 

1. Marxism in Wonderland 17 

2. Is Marxism Falsifiable? 18 

3. Fundamentals of Marxist Social Theory 23 

4. Does Marxism Allow Logical Contradictions? 31 

5. Dialectical Materialism and Scientific Method 36 

Chapter 2: THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 42 

1. Materialism versus Idealism 42 

2. The Case against Idealism 47 

3. The Case for Materialism 51 

Chapter 3: THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 60 

1. Dialectics versus Metaphysics 60 

2. Materialist Dialectics 67 

3. The Concrete Analysis of Concrete Conditions 73 

4. The Dialectical Materialist Theory of Knowledge 8 1 

5. Reinforced Dogmatism Reinforced 88 

Chapter 4: THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 97 

1. The Science of Interconnections 97 

2. The Unity of Opposites 101 

3. The Test of Dialectical Materialism in 

4. The Philosophy of Identity 12 1 

PART TWO: PREMISES FOR POLITICS 

Chapter i: HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL 129 

PREDICTION 

1. The Dogmatism of Historicism 129 

2. Men Make their own History 133 

3. Historical Prediction 137 

4. Prediction, Probability and Intent 143 

5. Necessity and Inevitability 15 1 

6. Science and Utopia 159 


12 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


Chapter 2: SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 164 

1. Problems of Social Science 164 

2. Social Science and Politics 172 

3. Conduct and Aims of Marxist Political Parties 178 

Chapter 3: THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 188 

1. Has Capitalism Disappeared? 188 

2. The Labour Theory of Value 192 

3. Surplus Value and Exploitation of Wage-Labour 198 

4. The General Law of Capitalist Accumulation 204 

Chapter 4: SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL 215 

ENGINEERING 

1. The Socialist Revolution 215 

2. Social Engineering 222 

3. Reform and Revolution 227 

Chapter 5: THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL 232 

POWER 

1. Institutions 232 

2. Institutions and Classes 239 

3. Classes and Political Power 245 

4. The Executive Power of the State 253 

Chapter 6: THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 258 

1 . The Definition of Democracy 258 

2. Public Control and Class Control 265 

3. Political and Economic Power 271 

4. Socialist Democracy 274 

PART THREE: TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 

Chapter i: EQUALITY 281 

1. Equality of Rights 281 

2. Equality and the Abolition of Classes 287 

Chapter 2: FREEDOM 292 

1. Freedom and Restriction of Freedom 292 

2. Freedom, Rights and Security 299 

3. Freedom from Exploitation 304 

4. Freedom and Necessity 312 

5. The Means and Opportunities for Individual Freedom 319 


CONTENTS I3 

Chapter 3: THE OPEN SOCIETY 325 

1. The Closed and the Open Society 325 

2. The Way Into the Open Society 328 

3. Responsibility, Individual and Collective 336 

Chapter 4: COMMUNISM 343 

1. The Rationality and Practicality of Communism 343 

2. Social Implications of Modem Techniques 345 

3. The Communist Programme 352 

Chapter 5: THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 360 

1. Democratic Socialist Planning 360 

2. From Socialism to Communism 368 

Chapter 6: THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 373 

1. Communism and Anti-Communism 373 

2. Against Violence, for Just Laws, for Individual Rights 375 

3. The Rationalist Belief in Reason 383 

Index: 391 





PAST ONE 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 
















































I 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


I. MARXISM IN WONDERLAND 

“You should say what you mean,” die March Hare told Alice at the 
Mad Tea Party* “I do,” Alice replied. “At least, I mean what I say — 
that's the same thing you know.” “Not the same thing a bit!” said the 
Hatter. 

The rather lengthy expositions and refutations of Marxism by 
Dr. K. R. Popper place Marxists in the same predicament as the Hatter 
placed Alice. Regardless of what we may say, he undertakes to say 
what we mean — and then to show that it is both absurd and obnoxious. 

Dr. Popper regards Marxism as a “reinforced dogmatism”. To deal 
with it, he has himself devised a method of reinforced refutation. He 
says what Marxism means, and shows how wrong it is. If any Marxist 
objects, “But that is not what we Marxists say!” he replies, “It is 
what Marxism means.” How can one answer such a refutation? 
As Dr. Popper says in his preface to the second edition of The Open 
Society and its Enemies , “my criticism was devastating”. 

His exposition, explanation and refutation of Marxism is based on 
the assumption that Marxism is essentially unscientific. How unscientific 
it is he shows in The Open Society and its Enemies , where he expounds 
and exposes first Plato and then Hegel, and then warns the reader — 
Marxism is like them ! After such an introduction the reader’s prejudices 
are thoroughly aroused, and he is well prepared to assist at the final 
exposure and dissolution of Marxist dogmas. 

What Marx did, however, was not to follow blindly in the footsteps 
of Plato and Hegel, but to work out the foundations of the scientific 
theory of man and society. That is what he said he tried to do, and 
that is what he did. Marxism is scientific. Marx’s achievement was to 
apply the standard methods of science to the study of society and the 
solution of social problems. By so doing he performed a signal service 
for the working-class movement, for his scientific theory (a) demon- 
strated the character and consequences of the exploitation of labour in 
modern society, (b) formulated a practical aim of ending that exploita- 
tion and its consequences, and (c) supplied principles on which to 
decide the practical policies necessary for realising the aim. Only the 


i8 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


application and continued application of scientific method could 
produce that kind of practical understanding and purpose of which 
Marx and Marxists consider the working-class movement to stand in 
need. 

Marxism stands or falls entirely by whether it can or cannot justify 
its scientific claims. But if it is, as is claimed, scientific, then it must be 
allowed to share the generally recognised character of scientific 
theories and views — namely, that it stakes no claim to finality or 
completeness but keeps on adding to, modifying, reformulating and 
rearranging its generalisations and recommendations as new experiences 
and new problems are presented. A Marxist is, presumably, a follower 
of Marx; and Marxism is the continuation of Marx’s work in developing 
the scientific theory of the working-class movement and of socialism. 
Yet when Marxists try to press forward the scientific development of 
Marxism — and that includes not only expansion and elaboration but 
correction — our critics tell us: Stop ! Marxism is unscientific and is not 
allowed to develop like that. 

Dr. Popper has himself written a good deal about scientific method, 
notably in his book The Logic of Scientific Discovery and in the papers 
collected in the volume Conjectures and Refutations . His contributions 
to the subject are important and enlightening; and if I shall venture 
to suggest that he has not said the last word (and he himself, I suppose, 
would hardly claim that) it is not intended to belittle in the least the 
value, importance and originality of what he has said. While answering 
his refutations of Marxism I am well aware of how much we stand 
in his debt. We are indebted to him in two ways. First, the points 
he has made about “the logic of scientific discovery” are of great 
assistance in formulating and explaining the actual scientific procedures 
of Marxism. Second, his efforts to say what we mean are of great 
assistance at least in making clear what we do not mean. So far as 
we are concerned, we say what we mean and also (which Dr. Popper, 
like the March Hare and the Mad Hatter, seems to find it hard to 
appreciate) we mean what we say. We say that Marxism is based on 
scientific procedures and can only continue on that basis. And we 
mean it ! 


2. IS MARXISM FALSIFIABLE? 

In his writings on scientific method Dr. Popper dealt with the question 
of the criterion of demarcation between scientific theories, on the one 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


19 


hand, and non-scientific (pseudo-scientific or metaphysical) theories 
on the other. It is generally agreed that a theory is scientific only if it 
is capable of being tested by experience. He pointed out that to be y 
capable of being tested is to be capable of being falsified. Thus it is not 
enough to be able to describe types of instances which would confirm 
a theory; it is necessary to be able to describe what sort of instance 
would falsify it. “The criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its 
falsiflability ,, (CR. 37). 

This point, a valid and important one, can be appreciated by 
reflecting that to test anything it is essential to have a criterion of 
failure . If there is only a vague idea of what is required to pass the test, 
but no clear idea of what will bring failure, then it is possible to wangle 
almost anything past the test and the test is as good as worthless. Or if 
the test is so devised that anything will pass it, then it is no test at all. 
This, Dr. Popper insists, goes for , scientific theories. “It is easy to 
obtain confirmations for nearly every theory — if we look for confirma- 
tions. Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify it, or refute 
it. Testability is falsifiability” (CR. 36). 

It is quite possible, as he and others have pointed out, for certain 
ingenious theories to masquerade under the title of science when they 
are in fact non-scientific — since they have been so constructed as to be 
incapable of falsification. They are so constructed that whatever happens 
fits in with the theory, and nothing , therefore, can falsify it. 

It has been suggested that certain Freudian theories may be of this 
sort. Freud said that every man wishes to kill his father and marry his 
mother. If a man objects that he does not in fact wish to do such things, 
Freud replies that of course he is not aware of so wishing because the 
wish has been repressed. And in general, whatever a man consciously 
wishes and does, it can always be made out to be linked with and not 
incompatible with his unconscious oedipus-complex. But this puts the 
Freudian theory outside the bounds of science. It is not a scientific but 
a pseudo-scientific theory. It is a “reinforced dogmatism”, so built up 
or reinforced as to be unfalsifiable or irrefutable. 

These considerations suggested to Dr. Popper the happy idea of 
contriving a final refutation of Marxism. People had long been trying 
in vain to cite facts which would refute Marx’s social theories. No 
wonder they did not succeed, for these theories are so devised as to be 
irrefutable — and that refutes them ! 

If Marxist social theories were irrefutable in this sense, then they 
would indeed be unscientific. But the fact that a theory has not been 


20 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 




falsified does not imply that it is unscientific because unfalsifiable. For 
example, the law of the conservation of energy (the first law of 
thermodynamics) is generally regarded as a genuine and well-tested 
scientific law; but it has not been falsified. We can quite well say what 
sort of things could happen if the law of the conservation of energy 
did not hold; the point is, it does hold and they do not happen. 
Similarly, we can quite well say what sort of things could happen if 
the basic laws formulated by Marx as governing social development 
did not hold; the point is, they do hold, and these things do not 
happen. Unhappily for the refutation, Marxism is not irrefutable. Its 
basic laws, like those of thermodynamics, correspond with how things 
in fact go. What they forbid to happen never does happen. 

Dr. Popper says, with truth, that “every ‘good’ scientific theory is 
a prohibition: it forbids certain things to happen” (CR. 36). Thus a 
“good” or “genuine” scientific law, as distinct from a pseudo-scientific 
one, can always be expressed in the form: “So and so cannot happen.” 
For example, the first law of thermodynamics tells us “You cannot 
build perpetual motion machines”, and the second law tells us “You 
cannot build machines that are one hundred per cent efficient”. This 
way of expressing laws brings out very well their practical value. 
Thus the laws of thermodynamics instruct machine-technologists about 
the limits of practical possibility within which they can operate (indeed, 
it was in connection with the construction of steam engines that these 
laws were first discovered). An engine cannot run without fuel, and 
the task of the designer is to construct an engine in which the energy 
of the fuel will be most efficiently converted into work. That allows 
a very large but not unlimited range of possibility for the construction 
of engines. But, of course, if someone did contrive an engine which 
ran without fuel, or which was one hundred per cent efficient (it 
would be a kind of fairy-tale engine), that would falsify the laws of 
thermodynamics — and technologists would have to undertake some 
new and very fundamental rethinking of their concepts. No one 
expects this to happen, but it is imaginable (i.e. it can be described in 
fairy tales). The laws of thermodynamics are thus falsifiable but not 
falsified. That is, no doubt, why they are considered to be such 
very “good” laws. 

The fundamental laws which Marx formulated as governing social 
development similarly “forbid certain things to happen”. They say 
that there must always be a certain kind of correspondence between 
forces of production and relations of production. This allows all 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


21 


manner of things to be done within the bounds of such correspondence, 
but denies the possibility of going outside those bounds. From the 
point of view, therefore, of social action — or what Dr. Popper calls 
“social engineering” — it says what is possible and what is not possible. 
For example, to use all the resources of modem technology for human 
welfare is possible, but not without reconstituting property relations in 
correspondence with the social character of production — it is not 
possible to combine such use of resources with capitalist ownership 
and capitalist profit. What Marxism “forbids to happen” can be 
imagined as happening — indeed, in many democratic countries the 
principal political parties make a parade of such imaginings at every 
general election; but it never happens. If uninterrupted economic 
development were to be combined with capitalist enterprise and 
capitalist profit, then Marxs theory would be falsified— just as if a 
perpetual motion machine were built the laws of thermodynamics 
would be falsified. 

The “social engineering” which treats Marxism as reinforced 
dogmatism is thus just about on a level with ordinary engineering 
which treats the laws of thermodynamics as reinforced dogmatism. 
Dr. Popper maintains that the true scientist, always eager to test his 
theories in every conceivable way, devotes his main energies to trying 
to contrive falsifications. This view of scientific work overlooks the 
fact that a scientific attitude also demands the guidance of practical 
undertakings in accordance with scientific discovery. Dr. Popper 
seems to think that a scientific attitude towards the social discoveries 
claimed by Marx would enjoin continually trying all manner of means 
to go against the laws which Marx formulated, in the hopes of 
falsifying them. The scientifically-minded person must try to preserve 
capitalism so as to see whether Marx’s laws cannot be falsified. The 
Marxist who, accepting the laws, advises the abolition of capitalism, 
is a mere dogmatist and lacks any conception of the ways of science. 
This is like saying that chemists should practise alchemy, in the hopes 
of falsifying the laws of chemistry; and that engineers should devote 
all their ingenuity to constructing perpetual motion machines. 

But Dr. Popper formulates his objection to Marxism also along the 
following lines. Marxism forbids certain things to happen, but never- 
theless some things which it forbids do happen. In that case the Marxists 
admit to having made a mistake, but say that, all the same, “the 
fundamentals” of the theory have not been falsified. That shows, says 
Dr. Popper, that the theory is nothing but a reinforced dogmatism. 


22 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


It has formulated its 4 ‘ fundamentals* * in such a way that they cannot 
be falsified. It is not a scientific theory, which submits itself to tests, 
but an unscientific theory which evades every test. 

The Russian Revolution has been alleged, by Dr. Popper and 
others, to provide a case in point. Marx certainly said at one time 
that the socialist revolution would begin in the most advanced 
industrial countries. He 4 'forbade* * it to begin anywhere else — but in 
fact it began in Russia. But when this falsification of an earlier predic- 
tion (or prohibition, for every prediction is a prohibition) took place, 
Marxists simply said that certain specific features of social development 
in particular countries had been underestimated; the revolution began 
in Russia because “the chain breaks at its weakest link*’. 

Does a candid examination of this example really support the 
allegation that Marxism is reinforced dogmatism? On the contrary, 
Marxism remains falsifiable. Marxists can, it is true, readily account for 
the socialist revolution starting in Russia. But if it had started, say, 
in the Far East or Central Africa, or if it had never started at all, that 
could not have been accounted for, and really would have falsified 
Marxism. But it did start, and started where Marxism permitted it to 
start. In point of fact Marx himself, in his later correspondence, wrote 
that his observations were leading him to the conclusion that revolution 
was unlikely after all to start in the industrial countries. Things were 
happening in these countries to postpone the revolution he had earlier 
expected, but in Russia to accelerate it. His approach to questions 
was the normal one of a scientific thinker who is continually ready to 
revise former estimates in the light of new evidence, but does not find 
it necessary to scrap the whole fundamental theory of his science every 
time such a revision is indicated. 

Similarly the fact that after the Second World War there was for 
many years full employment in Britain, in contradiction to Marx’s 
statements about capitalism always creating 4 ‘a reserve” of unemploy- 
ment, does not lead British Marxists to conclude that the whole 
Marxist theory of capitalism and socialism has been falsified, but only 
that certain special conditions had temporarily come into existence in 
Britain. 

Scientists generally agree that if predictions made in the light of a 
general theory are falsified, and it is then proposed to “save” the 
theory by adding 4 ‘supplementary hypotheses”, the theory must none 
the less be scrapped if the only evidence offered for the supplementary 
hypotheses is that they save the theory. Thus, for example, the old 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


23 


Ptolemaic theory that the planets move in circular orbits round the 
earth failed to accord with observations, but was “saved” by postu- 
lating irregularities, or epicycles, in the motions of the planets. 
However, because the only evidence offered for these epicycles was 
that they saved the theory, scientists now generally agree that observa- 
tion has falsified the Ptolemaic theory. 

It has been suggested that this is how Marxism is “saved” wherever 
what happens deviates from a prediction. But in fact the Marxist 
procedure has never been to invent supplementary hypotheses. For 
example, to account for full employment in Britain we do not invent 
a supplementary hypothesis — a kind of economic epicycle. We simply 
examine what has actually happened, which has by no means exceeded 
the bounds of possibility allowed by the general theory of Marxism, 
and find that it has led to consequences predictable and accountable 
within the theory. And similarly with the Russian Revolution. 

The rescue of Marxism in such cases is interestingly paralleled by 
a second example from the theory of planetary motions. After the 
Ptolemaic theory had been supplanted by Kepler's laws, certain 
irregularities were observed in the motion of the planet Uranus which 
did not accord with the predictions made by the laws. So it was 
suggested that there was in fact another planet, whose existence had 
previously passed unnoticed, the influence of which would account 
for the irregularities. Sure enough, this other planet (now named 
Neptune) was observed when telescopes were directed in the right 
direction — so Kepler's laws were “saved”, since they did not “forbid” 
there being another planet but allowed for its existence. It is just 
the same with Marxism, when social “irregularities” (such as the 
Russian Revolution or full employment in Britain) take place — we 
look for and find the causes of these “irregularities”. 

3. FUNDAMENTALS OF MARXIST SOCIAL THEORY 

Is there really anything wrong with saying, as Marxists say, that the 
“fundamentals” of Marxist social theory are not refuted even when 
certain particular expectations of events are falsified? Is it really a 
defect of a theory when its fundamentals are so framed that a rather 
wide range of possible happenings can be fitted into it? If so, then 
not only Marxism but a number of other theories too, generally 
regarded as scientific, must be relegated into the category of pseudo- 
science. Scientists are for ever being faced with failures of prediction, 


24 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


which they manage nevertheless to fit into the framework of their 
theories; and that is how the theories generally develop. 

To deal with the question of whether Marxism is science or pseudo- 
science it is advisable to begin by asking what the fundamental 
propositions of Marxist social theory actually say, and how Marx 
arrived at them. 

Before Marx formulated these scientific propositions, social events 
were generally accounted for in terms of people’s intentions and 
motives, and the structure and institutions of society in terms of the 
prevailing ideas. This way of accounting for social phenomena really 
does suffer from the defect of being able to account for anything. 
People always have intentions, and whatever may happen it can 
always be accounted for by saying that certain people acted with 
certain intentions — if what happens is what they intended, well and 
good; if not, then that is because they made a miscalculation, or 
because other people with other intentions interfered with them. 
Moreover, because it is practically impossible ever to discover with 
certainty what people’s intentions really were, it is always possible to 
attribute to them intentions fitting in with what took place, and so 
to account for what took place by the attributed intentions. Similarly, 
whatever the structure and institutions of society, it can always be 
said that they came to exist because certain people thought that was 
the best way of arranging social affairs, or else because some people’s 
good intentions were frustrated by other people. This type of theory 
(described by Marx as “idealist”, because it makes intentions and 
ideas the primary motive force in society) can therefore be judged 
unscientific precisely on the criteria proposed by Dr. Popper for 
distinguishing unscientific from scientific theories. Its obvious short- 
coming is that it leaves one still asking — what accounts for people’s 
different intentions and ideas, and for some being more successfully 
realised than others? 

Marx’s formulation of fundamental propositions for social science 
disposed of such previously unscientific ways of interpreting and 
accounting for events in very much the same way that, in other 
branches of inquiry, previously unscientific theories were disposed of 
when certain fundamental propositions for the respective sciences 
were formulated. For example, the old type of physics, derived from 
Aristotle, accounted for physical motion on the principle that every 
body seeks its natural place and changes according to the potentialities 
of change inherent in it. As Galileo, Newton and others effectively 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


2 5 


showed, such theories accounted for nothing because they could 
account for anything. Again, the theory of the original creation of 
biological species accounted for nothing because it could account for 
anything — whatever forms of life were observed could be accounted 
for by including them in the original plan of the Creator. 

Dr. Popper has pointed out that scientific theories are not arrived 
at by so-called “induction” from numerous observations but rather 
by posing questions and answers to them — answers that can then be 
observationally tested in all manner of ways. He did not, however, 
conclude (as he could have done) that the establishment of funda- 
mental theory, or guiding principles, for any field of inquiry has 
always depended on someone asking the right questions. Yet the 
genius of the great innovators in science has consisted in their formu- 
lating the right questions : once that is done, the answers are generally 
rather obvious. Marx's theory originates from his asking a question 
about society. 

What is the key question from which Marx’s social theory proceeds? 
The theory is not understood unless the question is understood — and 
this is why so many people (Dr. Popper included) fail to understand 
it, and so say it means what it does not mean. 

Faced with all the multitudinous phenomena of social life (both 
contemporary and as recorded by history) and seeking to embrace 
them all within a theory, Marx did not ask “What will account for 
all these phenomena?” Indeed, a question of the form “What accounts 
for all the phenomena?” is never the key question for establishing 
fundamental scientific theory. The phenomena in detail are to be 
accounted for by detailed investigations guided by scientific theory, 
which is quite another thing from the theory laying down in advance 
just what accounts for them all. So far from being a key question for 
science, the question “What accounts for everything?” is the very 
question which commonly leads to pseudo-science — something is 
posited which can so readily account for anything that it accounts 
for nothing. Marx is often alleged to have posed against the pseudo- 
scientific theory that ideas account for everything the rival pseudo- 
scientific theory that economic interest accounts for everything. This 
he did not do, and he and Engels denied it frequently and emphatically. 

The key question Marx asked was the simple and searching one: 
What is the condition for social life of any kind to take place ? Once he 
asked this question the answer was obvious. The condition for any 
kind of social life is that people should associate together to produce 


2 6 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


their material means of life. The proposition that to engage in any form 
of social activity people must first associate to produce their means of sub- 
sistence, was the fundamental proposition on which Marx based the 
science of society. 

Having arrived at this proposition, Marx was then able to formulate 
the fundamental concepts in terms of which the social mode of production 
may be defined. These are the concepts of forces of production and 
relations of production. In order socially to produce their means of 
subsistence men must fashion tools and implements and acquire the 
skill and knowledge for their use — and these are their forces of pro- 
duction. And in using those forces of production they must enter 
into social relations of production. Men “produce only by co-operating 
in a certain way and mutually exchanging their activities’’, wrote 
Marx in Wage-Labour and Capital. “In order to produce they enter 
into relations with one another, and only within these relations does 
production take place.” The relations of production are therefore the 
multiple relations between individual people as “they exchange their 
activities and take part in the whole action of production”. They 
include the property relations which people enter into in owning 
means of production and in appropriating and distributing the pro- 
ducts, and define the economic structure of society and the division 
of society into classes. 

Having thus concluded that the condition for social life is that men 
should engage in a mode of production, consisting of their entering 
into definite relations of production for the utilisation of definite 
forces of production, Marx proceeded to frame a general hypothesis 
about the way social life develops — it may be called the general law 
of all social development. This said that people must always adapt their 
relations of production to their forces of production , and work out ideas and 
organise themselves in institutions to enable them to do so. 

This theory (often known as “historical materialism”, and here 
stated only in its barest and simplest terms) served Marx (as he put 
it in the Preface to The Critique of Political Economy) “as a guiding 
thread for my studies”. That is to say, in the study of any particular 
phase of social development, past or present, he proceeded to consider 
what the forces of production were, what the relations of production 
were, and how people’s arguments about ideas and conduct of institu- 
tions enabled them to adapt their relations of production to their 
forces of production. This procedure served at one and the same time 
to account for the principal currents of social activity and their inter- 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


27 


play, and to define and delimit the actual possibilities and possible 
directions of social change. 

Such study, evidently, has to be empirical, like any scientific study — 
it is always necessary to ascertain the facts, they cannot be deduced 
from general theory. The general theory, like any “good” scientific 
theory, guides the inquirer by telling him what to look for ; it does not 
tell him in advance exactly what he will find. And obviously, on the 
one hand, it is possible for the inquirer to make all sorts of errors 
(for example, to overlook certain things that are happening, or to 
mistake one kind of happening for another) without such errors 
falsifying the general theory. On the contrary, the reapplication of the 
general theory will assist him to rectify such errors. And on the other 
hand, the general theory is sufficiently general, and sufficiently 
“flexible”, to allow a very wide margin of possible variations of 
development to occur without its being thereby falsified. On the 
contrary, in a given situation the theory permits many different 
alternative things to happen and, whichever does happen, is still 
capable of finding out how to account for it and to follow its 
development. 

The general guiding theory of Marxism is tested in its application 
to inquiries about particular events or sequences of events. And so 
far it has not been falsified but confirmed. As I pointed out before, 
this does not make it unfalsifiable. Certain things would assuredly 
falsify it, only they do not happen — for example, a Stone Age com- 
munity managing its affairs by parliamentary government and con- 
ducting controversies about the rights of man, or a successfully 
managed capitalism. 

The methodology by which Marx arrived at his theory of social 
development is exactly the same as that employed by Darwin in 
establishing the theory of evolution of species by natural selection. 
Engels in fact remarked on this in his speech at Marx’s funeral, when 
he said: “Just as Darwin discovered the law of development of organic 
nature, so Marx discovered the law of development of human history.” 
It is remarkable that Marx and Darwin both published their basic 
conclusions within a few years of each other, each having worked 
independently in applying the same scientific methodology in their 
respective spheres of inquiry. 

Darwin’s theory rests on the fundamental premise that every living 
organism lives by adaptation to an environment from which it 
assimilates its requirements of life. This, he realised, is the universal 


28 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


condition for the existence of living species— just as Marx realised that 
social production is the universal condition for the existence of human 
societies. Marx’s point about the human species — that men live in 
society by the social production of their means of life — was in fact a 
special application to men of the more general proposition about all 
living organisms propounded by Darwin. What distinguishes men 
from other animals, Marx explained, is the way they obtain their 
requirements by social production: from this comes the human 
peculiarity of speech, and the whole social and intellectual life by 
which men separate themselves from the rest of living nature. Human 
evolution then becomes not biological but social. Men do not acquire 
and satisfy new needs by any alteration of the organs of their bodies, 
but by acquiring new forces of production; and they change their 
social life and their own individual habits in so doing. 

Having propounded his fundamental proposition, Darwin proceeded 
to formulate the general hypothesis of natural selection. In exactly the 
same way, having propounded his fundamental proposition, Marx 
proceeded to formulate the general hypothesis about adapting relations 
of production to forces of production. Darwin, in his work, collected 
and sifted an enormous mass of data, demonstrating in detail how his 
hypothesis worked out — and he was able to fit all manner of apparent 
anomalies into the general theory. Marx in his work did the same. The 
scientific methodology employed was identical; and if historical 
materialism is to be rejected as pseudo-science, so must the theory of 
the evolution of species by natural selection. 

This account of the parallel in scientific methodology between the 
evolutionary theories of Marx and Darwin does not, incidentally, 
invalidate the criticisms that Marx himself made of certain supple- 
mentary aspects of Darwin’s original theory. To the general hypothesis 
of natural selection Darwin added a supplementary concept — which 
he borrowed from Malthus — about “the struggle for existence” and 
“the survival of the fittest”. Marx criticised these supplementary 
formulations of Darwin. It is now pretty generally agreed that those 
formulations were defective, and so the Darwinian theory does not 
survive in the exact form which Darwin himself originally gave it. 
But the “fundamental” Darwinian theory of evolution by natural 
selection survives. 

Marx’s theory, of course, lacks the “exactness” characteristic of 
those sciences which deal with physical and chemical phenomena. For 
the generalisations and laws stated in the theory are not formulated in 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


29 


quantitative terms. This is alleged to produce in Marx’s theory an 
unscientific vagueness. Once again, if this objection makes Marx’s 
theory unscientific, it makes Darwin’s theory equally unscientific. Yet 
surely no one in his senses would expect all generalisations about social 
and biological evolution to be given the quantitative form of the laws 
of mechanics or thermodynamics. 

It is worth noting, however, that despite these differences we may 
discern in the “exact” sciences, too, the self-same procedure for 
establishing fundamental theory as is exemplified in the social and 
biological theories of Marx and Darwin. For example, in establishing 
the fundamental theory of mechanics the idea was adopted that the 
condition for the existence of any body in motion relative to other 
bodies is that it has a certain motion of its own and is acted on by 
external forces. Having once hit on this fundamental idea, there were 
then formulated the fundamental concepts of mass, force, inertia, 
energy, and so on, in terms of which the laws of mechanics were 
formulated — corresponding to the fundamental (but in this case non- 
quantitative) concepts of relations of production and forces of pro- 
duction formulated by Marx. 

The scrutiny of Marx’s fundamental ideas about society reveals, 
then, their scientific character. Dr. Popper’s failure to grasp this fact 
illustrates his failure, in his published work on scientific method, to 
grasp more than one single aspect of scientific procedures. He says 
that science proceeds by making “conjectures” which are “falsifiable”, 
and then devising all manner of ways of trying to falsify them. So 
far as it goes, that is true enough. But yet the body of scientific theory 
consists of more than just a collection of falsifiable conjectures which 
are variously revised or replaced by other conjectures as falsification 
actually overtakes them. Every well-developed science rests on its 
fundamental theory, and is guided by it in its inquiries. This is a 
feature of science which Dr. Popper never examines — possibly because 
he distrusts such expressions as “fundamental theory”, which he 
thinks redolent of pseudo-scientific metaphysics. 

This shortcoming is evidenced when, after saying that “every ‘good’ 
scientific theory . . . forbids certain things to happen”, he adds: 
“The more a theory forbids, the better it is” (CR. 36). 

In making this pronouncement about how to judge how “good” a 
scientific theory is, Dr. Popper had, perhaps, in mind examples like 
the zoological statement: “eagles do not catch flies”. This statement 
is true, and well-authenticated — but its scientific value, as an item of 


30 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


zoological science, is slight. It simply “forbids” eagles to catch flies, 
and permits them to do anything else. But a “good” scientic account 
of eagles must be much more exacting in what it forbids and permits 
these birds to do. However, what undoubtedly applies to items of 
scientific theory about particular phenomena, does not apply to those 
very general theories and very general laws which, by virtue of their 
great generality, serve as the fundamentals for all scientific theory 
dealing with a whole class of phenomena (biological, physical, chemical, 
social, and so on). For example, the first and second laws of thermo- 
dynamics simply “forbid” energy not to be conserved and entropy 
not to increase; they allow anything to happen within these pro- 
hibitions. Again, the Darwinian theory simply forbids species or 
varieties to survive for long unless adapted to their environments (a 
very liberal prohibition); and similarly, the Marxist theory simply 
forbids societies to develop without adapting relations of production 
to forces of production. These laws and theories would not be “better” 
if they forbade more. On the contrary, they would not be much good 
if they forbade too much. 

What Dr. Popper seems to have overlooked in his pronouncements 
about prohibitions and falsifications is the work of abstraction and 
generalisation in scientific theory. The task of “fundamental” theory 
is to abstract the necessary or universal condition of existence of the 
phenomena studied, and to put forward corresponding generalisations. 
Such fundamental theory, very abstract and very general, does not, 
should not and cannot satisfy Dr. Popper’s principle that “the more a 
theory forbids the better it is”. It is, indeed, difficult to imagine why 
on earth Dr. Popper should ever have enunciated such a principle — 
except that it gives him a stick to beat Marxism with. But it is not a 
“good” stick, and in wielding it Dr. Popper joins the very numerous 
and very distinguished company of those who have allowed anti- 
communism to cloud their judgment. 

In short, in making out that Marx’s theory about society is rein- 
forced dogmatism, Dr. Popper has totally neglected to consider 
Marx’s actual methodology. Marx in fact laid the foundations of his 
theory of society in just the same way as others have laid the founda- 
tions of other sciences. And this is plainly evidenced in what Marx 
said. As we shall see, having ignored Marx’s actual methodology, Dr. 
Popper proceeds to explain that Marx’s theory really means all kinds 
of pseudo-scientific things (summed up in such denigratory epithets 
as “historicism” and “essentialism”) which, however, could not have 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


31 


been products of Marx’s scientific method, and which Marx did not say. 

Instead of examining Marx’s scientific method, Dr. Popper deals 
at some length with the “origins” of Marx’s theory in the philosophy 
of Hegel. Hegel was a philosopher who accepted the idealist view of 
human affairs, that ideas are what accounts for everything; but in 
contrast to those who said, and continue to say, that there is no 
accounting for ideas and that therefore there is no discernible “law 
of development” in human history, Hegel did see a law of historical 
development, namely the logical law of the working out of ideas. 
Marx, it is true, was greatly impressed by Hegel’s conception of a 
discoverable law of development — but not by Hegel’s account of 
what this law of development was. He totally rejected Hegel’s idealism, 
and sought instead to arrive at the formulation of a law of development 
by the well-tried methods of empirical science. He called this “putting 
Hegel on his feet”. The result was the theory of historical materialism. 

Dr. Popper, on the other hand, concludes that because Marx 
admired and was stimulated by Hegel, therefore his theory originated 
from Hegel, and therefore it must be as foreign to science as Hegel’s 
theory was. He concludes that the Marxist theory is essentially 
unscientific on the grounds that it originated from Hegel. This kind of 
exposition comes, incidentally, very strangely from one who h&s also 
devoted much space to exposing the fallacy of deducing what a thing 
is, its “essence”, by theorising about its “origins”. 

4. DOES MARXISM ALLOW LOGICAL CONTRADICTIONS? 

Dr. Popper further maintains that what makes Marxism into “a 
reinforced dogmatism” is its use of “dialectics” — which he sees as 
totally opposed to science. He does not object so much to Marx’s 
“materialism” as to “dialectics”. “Although I should not describe 
myself as a materialist, my criticism is not directed against materialism”, 
he says. “The materialist element in this theory could be comparatively 
easily reformulated in such a way that no serious objection to it could 
be made” (CR. 331-2). But “thanks to dialectics . . . Marxism has 
established itself as a dogmatism which is elastic enough, by using its 
dialectic method, to evade any further attack. It has thus become what 
I have called a reinforced dogmatism” (CR. 334). 

True to his own method of reinforced refutation, Dr. Popper 
proceeds to say what “dialectics” means — and makes it mean some- 
thing remarkably stupid. 


32 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


“Dialectics ... is a theory which maintains that something — more 
especially human thought — develops in a way characterised by what 
is called the dialectic triad: thesis, antithesis and synthesis” (CR. 313). 

As against this, it is worth recalling what Lenin said about dialectics 
in his very famous book What the Friends of the People are and how 
they fight the Social-Democrats. “Anyone who reads the definition 
and description of the dialectical method given by Engels will see 
that the Hegelian triads are not even mentioned, and that it all amounts 
to regarding social evolution as a natural-historical process of develop- 
ment. . . . What Marx and Engels called the dialectical method is 
nothing more nor less than the scientific method in sociology, which 
consists in regarding society as a living organism in a constant state of 
development, the study of which requires an objective analysis of the 
relations of production which constitute the given social formation 
and an investigation of its laws of functioning and development.” 

Quite in accord with this, Lenin also said that “the most essential 
thing in Marxism is the concrete analysis of concrete conditions”, and 
that “genuine dialectics” consists of “a thorough detailed analysis of a 
process”. 

Dr. Popper has, of course, read Marx and Engels (though possibly 
not Lenin). However, having read them, he concludes that they did 
not mean what they said, so he has undertaken to say it for them. 
Having foisted on to them the rather incoherent “theory” that “some- 
thing, more especially human thought” always develops through 
“thesis, antithesis and synthesis”, he proceeds to foist on them a logical 
conclusion even more absurd than the alleged theory. 

According to the “dialectical” theory of “triads”, the thesis and 
antithesis are “contradictory”. Therefore, says Dr. Popper, dialecticians 
“assert that contradictions cannot be avoided, since they occur every- 
where in the world. Such an assertion”, he continues, “amounts to 
an attack upon the so-called ‘law of contradiction (or, more fully, 
upon the ‘law of the exclusion of contradictions’) of traditional logic, 
a law which asserts that two contradictory statements can never be 
true together, or that a statement consisting of the conjunction of 
two contradictory statements must always be rejected as false on 
purely logical grounds” (CR. 316). Hence, he concludes, dialectics 
rests on the absurdity of asserting that logically self-contradictory 
statements are true. 

This is, indeed, an absurdity. But Marx was never responsible for 
enunciating it — he never said anything of the kind. On the contrary, 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


33 


he frequently (like any other scientific inquirer) concluded that certain 
generalisations were false because certain verified statements of fact 
contradicted them ; and he would hardly have done that if he had 
thought that the logical “law of the exclusion of contradictions” 
could be dispensed with. If two logically contradictory statements 
could both be true, then a generalisation could still be true even 
though facts contradicted it. One could then say whatever one liked, 
there could be no test of truth or falsehood, and, as Dr. Popper 
correctly remarks, “one would have to give up any kind of scientific 
activity: it would mean a complete breakdown of science” (CR. 317). 

Dr. Popper’s foisting on to Marxism the absurd view that logical 
contradictions are allowable in true statement depends on making a 
play with the use of the word “contradiction” quite in the style of 
the characters Alice met in Wonderland. 

If, in describing a certain person, one says that “he is a mass of 
contradictions”, no one but the Mad Hatter, the March Hare, or 
Dr. Popper, would conclude that one means that a true statement of 
his character is logically self-contradictory. Similarly, Marx wrote 
about “the contradictions of capitalism”, indicating that in the 
development of capitalism the combination of “socialised production” 
with “private appropriation” produces certain strains and instabilities. 
But to state that capitalism combines socialised production and private 
appropriation, between which there exists a relationship of a type 
which may, without misuse of language, be termed “contradictory”, 
is not a logically self-contradictory or inconsistent statement, but a 
perfectly consistent general factual statement, of the kind which may 
be verified or falsified. There is not a sentence in the “concrete analysis 
of concrete conditions” or “thorough detailed analysis of a process”, 
undertaken by Marx, Engels, Lenin, or any responsible Marxist 
practising the dialectical method, by which they sort out and display 
the “contradictions” exemplified in conditions and processes, which 
contains even a hint at a logical contradiction. 

Having concluded that Marxism means to say that logical contradic- 
tions are allowable, Dr. Popper triumphantly produces his final 
demonstration that Marxism is “reinforced dogmatism”. “For if we 
are prepared to put up with contradictions, pointing out contradic- 
tions in our theories could no longer induce us to change them. In 
other words, all criticism (which consists in pointing out contradic- 
tions) would lose its force. Criticism would be answered by ‘And 
why not?’ or perhaps even by an enthusiastic ‘There you are!’; that 


34 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


is, by welcoming the contradictions which have been pointed out to 
us” (CR. 317). So you cannot falsify Marxism, because Marxism 
maintains that falsification or contradiction does not falsify. This 
account of Marx’s “reinforced dogmatism” does not, of course, quite 
accord with other accounts which Dr. Popper gives of how Marxism 
evades falsification. But never mind that! His reinforced refutations 
can never fail, because, whatever Marx or Marxists may say, he will 
always find a way of saying what we mean which renders it utterly 
absurd. 

Outside of Wonderland, it is a commonplace that the Marxist 
“dialectic” is concerned with understanding things “in their changes 
and interconnections”, and formulating “laws” about how real 
changes and interconnections go. 

As Engels said in the introduction to Atiti-Duhring , it is a mistake 
if “in considering individual things” one “loses sight of their inter- 
connections”, or if “in contemplating their existence” one “forgets 
their coming into being and passing away”. And if one makes such a 
mistake, he continued, one ends by being involved in contradictions. 
Thus “for everyday purposes we know, for example, and can say 
with certainty whether an animal is alive or not; but when we look 
more closely we find that this is often an extremely complex question 
... it is impossible to determine the moment of death, for physiology 
has established that death is not a sudden instantaneous event but a very 
protracted process. In the same way every organic being is at each 
moment the same and not the same; at each moment it is assimilating 
matter drawn from without, and excreting other matter; at each 
moment the cells of its body are dying and new ones are being formed; 
in fact within a longer or shorter period the matter of its body is 
completely renewed ... so that every organic being is at all times 
itself and yet something other than itself”. Hence if you overlook 
the way tilings come into being and cease to be, the way they dis- 
integrate and are renewed, and the way they exist only in complex 
interrelations with other things, and try to say of each tiling what 
its state is at each moment regardless of its changes and relationships, 
you will be led to make contradictory statements — “it is . . .” and 

n » • ^ >> 

it is not .... 

What does this imply? It certainly does not imply that we should 
be “prepared to put up with (logical) contradictions”. On the contrary, 
the occurrence of logical contradictions is a sign that the categories 
employed in describing things in abstraction from “their intercon- 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


35 


nections” and “coming into being and passing away” are inadequate 
to the “concrete analysis of concrete conditions”. When, in accordance 
with principles of dialectics, one substitutes for such abstract and 
inadequate accounts of things the “thorough detailed analysis of a 
process”, the logical contradictions vanish. 

To describe, for example, how an organic body renews its cells 
in the course of its interaction with its environment, and to describe 
the “contradictory” relationship of the processes of decay and renewal 
which make up its life, does not involve making logically contra- 
dictory statements. On the contrary, the whole analysis is done in 
strict conformity with the principles of consistency, or non-contradic- 
tion, laid down by formal logic. Dialectics does not encourage us in 
inconsistency, but, on the contrary, accepts the most rigid demands 
of formal logical consistency of statement. To say “A thing is the 
same and not the same” is a logical contradiction which no scientifically- 
minded person can be “prepared to put up with”. To say “At every 
moment it is assimilating new matter and excreting old matter” is 
to give a more adequate account of it, and contains no logical con- 
tradiction whatsoever. Dialectics does not permit logical contradic- 
tions, but gets rid of them. 

The truth is that if one says “It is the same and yet not the same”, 
the question immediately raised by such an enigmatic statement is 
the question: “In what respect is it the same, and in what respect 
not the same?” For (as Aristotle pointed out when he originally 
formulated the logical law of non-contradiction) to say that something 
is in all respects the same and in all respects not the same is a logical 
contradiction which cannot be allowed. To explain, then, “At every 
moment it is assimilating new matter and excreting old matter” is 
to answer the question about the respects in which the thing changes 
while otherwise remaining the same. By supplying information about 
the processes going on in the thing, it explains that while the thing 
remains the same in respect of its external form it ceases to be the 
same in respect of the matter composing it. From that one might 
then further conclude that in all probability the external charac- 
teristics will sooner or later undergo change as well and become 
different as a result of internal changes. 

When one thus undertakes, in accordance with dialectics, “a 
thorough detailed analysis of a process”, which exhibits its contra- 
dictory sides and how the character and mode of change of the whole 
is determined by the relationship of these contradictory sides, the 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


36 

result is something which, far from being logically self-contradictory, 
completely satisfies all the logical criteria for scientific statement. We 
get statements which can be verified or falsified, and which are 
relevant to the drawing of probable conclusions about the further 
development of a process. 

This point can, incidentally, be put in a formalised way, in complete 
accordance with the principles of formal logic. Let P be a process, 
which contains contradictory sides or aspects A and B. If one then 
considers A by itself, apart from its relationship with B, one can infer 
a conclusion about P which may be written “A(P)”; and similarly, 
considering B by itself, one infers the conclusion “B(P)”. These 
conclusions are then incompatible or inconsistent with each other. If, 
however, one makes a correct analysis of P, as containing the con- 
tradictory sides A and B, one reaches the conclusion “AB(P)”. This 
conclusion is a statement of the mode of relationship and interaction of 
the contradictory sides of P ; and from it one may infer the probable 
course of development of P. 

The Marxist dialectic does not, as alleged, allow logical contradic- 
tions. Nor is it designed, as alleged, for producing statements which 
cannot be tested, but for precisely the opposite end — producing 
scientific statements which can be tested. As for Dr. Popper, all he 
has done is to derive logical absurdities from a pseudo-scientific theory 
about “triads”, and then solemnly to inform his readers: This is what 
Marxism means ! One is tempted to ask which he thinks the stupider — 
the Marxists, or the readers to whom he presents such nonsense. 

5. DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM AND SCIENTIFIC METHOD 

If dialectical materialism is not the nonsense Dr. Popper makes it out 
to be, what exactly does it say? What is its content and aim, as a 
philosophy? 

One thing should be made clear at the outset, and that is that 
Marx and Engels never and nowhere worked out a fully systematic 
statement of dialectical materialism. All they did was to argue against 
other views in philosophy and lay down certain guiding principles 
for the development of their own. So the scientific philosophical 
principles need more working out, and Marxism in this sphere means 
working them out — on the basis of following up the indications 
afforded by Marx and Engels, and following them up, moreover, 
in a way that does not involve groundless dogmas, or logical absurdities, 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


37 


but accords with the advances of logical and scientific knowledge, 
and social technology, achieved to date. These have gone considerably 
past the point reached in Marx's day. Although Dr. Popper seems to 
think that a bona fide Marxist is by definition ignorant of progress in 
logical and mathematical analysis, scientific discovery and tech- 
nological achievement, the job of Marxists is, on the contrary, to 
take account of these matters and formulate the Marxist position 
accordingly. Marxism, as I have said, is the continuation of Marx's 
work. In this Marxists inevitably become involved in controversies 
with one another, as well as with opponents of Marxism. That, of 
course, is how the thing develops, how it continues. 

The practitioner of reinforced refutation may fancy he detects here 
a loophole for the insinuation of reinforced dogmatism. If Marxism 
is permitted such rational and scientific development (lie will ask), 
cannot any statement found valid be then labelled “Marxist", while 
any discredited statement, even if made by a Marxist, will by definition 
be excluded from “Marxism"? This is obviously a quibble. The 
development of Marxism continues so long as it continues to follow 
the original guiding principles. If these are refuted then Marxism is 
destroyed, and if what is then propounded is still called “Marxism" 
it is a mere impersonation. In the same way, we regard the man as 
the same person as the boy; but if at a certain point he were knocked 
on the head, laid out and buried, and someone else assumed his name, 
we would regard that person as an impersonator. These sorts of 
consideration apply to anything that grows, including scientific 
theories. 

I fully agree with Dr. Popper that all views should be subject to 
continuous test, and modified or, if need be, scrapped, in the light of 
it. But if I nevertheless remain a Marxist it is not because I except 
Marxism from this critical principle, but because I do not interpret a 
“critical" attitude as entailing readiness to fall over backwards in 
deference to every “critic". For my part, I am a Marxist because I 
have not yet found any logical or scientific argument that refutes 
Marxism, though there are plenty that contribute to its development, 
whereas I have always found that arguments which claim to refute 
Marxism are neither logical nor scientific. 

To arrive at a general idea of what dialectical materialism, as the 
basic philosophical outlook exemplified or applied in Marxist social 
theory, says and means in contemporary terms, it is advisable to 
start by taking into account, first, what sort of question it seeks to 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


38 

answer, and second, to what sort of answer it is opposed. Generally 
speaking, these are two considerations of paramount importance for 
the exposition and explanation of views. A sure way of misunder- 
standing or misrepresenting what people mean is to suppose them to 
be trying to answer some other question than the one that actually 
interests them, and opposing other views than those they are actually 
concerned to oppose. 

I begin, then, by remarking on a question which dialectical 
materialism is sometimes supposed to answer, but which is not the 
question that it begins by posing. Dialectical materialism does not set 
out to answer the question: “What is the nature of the universe ?” 
It does not , therefore, consist of any set of statements about “the 
totality of things”, or about “everything”, or about “the world as a 
whole”, or about “the ultimate substance of things” or “the ultimate 
structure of reality”. If it is supposed that dialectical materialism is the 
sort of “metaphysical system” which proposes an answer to those 
sorts of questions, then it is misunderstood and misrepresented from 
the outset. As modem studies of logic and scientific method have 
quite conclusively shown, those are all badly formulated questions 
and any answers proposed to them are worthless because incapable 
of any sort of test. And as Engels, anticipating these studies, 
emphatically stated in his Ludwig Feuerbach: “One leaves ‘absolute 
truth’ alone . . . instead, one pursues attainable, relative truths along 
the path of the positive sciences”; and in the introduction to Anti- 
Duhring: “Modern materialism ... no longer needs any philosophy 

standing above the other sciences What still independently survives 

of all former philosophy is the science of thought and its laws — formal 
logic and dialectics. Everything else is merged in the positive science 
of nature and history.” 

Marxism and dialectical materialist philosophy emphatically teach 
that well-grounded and reliable theory about ourselves and the 
universe around us can be obtained only be the methodical investiga- 
tion of particular phenomena open to observation, and is always 
subject to the tests of experience. To ask, therefore, about the structure 
of the universe as a whole, or about what kinds of things exist and 
what are their properties and relations, in advance of investigation, 
and to propound any theory which on general philosophical grounds 
answers “it must be like this”, is as contrary to Marxism as it is 
contrary to the accepted precepts of logic and scientific method. What 
is sensible is rather to ask about the nature, constitution, structure or 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


39 


laws of operation of observable objects or processes — and to seek the 
answer by the methods of science, and test it in experience. Such 
knowledge as we can get about “the totality of things’ * can be got 
only by piecing together items of knowledge about particular things — 
hence it necessarily remains always incomplete and provisional. More- 
over, Marxism is practical — it seeks to develop theory to inform 
practice and to be tested in practice. Grandiose theories about “the 
universe as a whole” do not inform practice, but only befuddle it, 
and cannot be submitted to any practical test. To inform practice we 
want testable theories about what concerns us in practice (just as Dr. 
Popper himself maintains). 

The question to which dialectical materialism proposes an answer 
concerns rather the approach or method to be adopted in making and 
developing reliable theory to inform practice and to be tested in 
practice. Thus it rejects the invitation “Please invent a theory about 
the nature of the universe”, but accepts the invitation “Please state 
the principles to be adopted in making theories”. When we speak 
about “materialism” and about “dialectics”, separately or together, 
we are not propounding a philosophical theory about “everything” 
in contrast to or supplementing scientific theories about particular 
things, but we are propounding the approach or guiding principles 
recommended for making theories. 

We shall see later that dialectical materialism, as an answer to the 
question “Please state the principles to be adopted in making theories”, 
does nevertheless in a sense also supply an answer to the question 
“What is the nature of the universe?” For to answer the question of 
the approach to be adopted in making theories cannot but lead to 
conclusions about the form of statements corresponding to accessible 
reality. For example, any statement that can inform practice must deal 
with things detectable by the senses and which exist only in their 
interconnections with other things in processes of change. This shows 
that the world we live in and get to know is a world of material 
change; and that, of course, is a very general conclusion about “the 
nature of the world”. The point is, first, that a question about “the 
nature of the universe” cannot be answered directly, but only 
derivatively via questions about approach and method; and second, 
that the job of reliably informing ourselves about the world we 
inhabit requires the investigation of particular things and not of “the 
nature of the world as a whole”. 

Dr. Popper mentions with some scorn the contention that Marxism 


40 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


is not “a theory” but “a method”. It is, he insists, “a theory”. So it is — 
it is a theory employing a method. Marxism is a theory about human 
affairs employing the method of dialectical materialism. But dialectical 
materialism is not a theory about “everything” added to theories 
about particular matters of concern. Marxism does not have a theory 
about human affairs plus the theory of dialectical materialism, but its 
theory is dialectical materialist. And the same principles for making 
theory which are exemplified and applied in Marxist theory about 
man are found implicit also in all scientific theory about nature. 
Dialectical materialism is “fundamental” in Marxism, not in the 
sense of its being a dogma about the universe into which everything 
must somehow or other be made to fit, regardless of the facts, but in 
the sense of its being a generalised statement of the principles of 
approach or method to be adopted in studying facts in such a way as 
to arrive at “the concrete analysis of concrete conditions”, or the 
“thorough detailed analysis of a process”. 

But that, it may be objected, abolishes the peculiar character of 
dialectical materialism as “the philosophy of Marxism” and merely 
equates it with “scientific method’. In the broadest sense, it is true, 
materialist dialectics can claim to be “nothing but scientific method”. 
This is just what Lenin said: it is “nothing more nor less than the 
scientific method . . .”. The distinguishing feature of Marxism is 
not that it invents and uses some new-fangled method of its own, 
quite different from the method evolved, used and approved in the 
normal conduct of the sciences, but that it develops and applies 
scientific method universally , and that includes drawing conclusions 
about men, human society and human affairs. Marxism seeks to apply 
scientific ways of understanding to everything that comes within 
human ken, including humanity itself. It is therefore critical of and 
opposed to traditional ways of understanding ourselves t which are by 
no means scientific — and this is what primarily distinguishes Marxism 
as a philosophy or outlook opposed to what is still generally current. 

Of course, scientific understanding of ourselves relies on already 
achieved scientific understanding of nature, for man becomes what he 
is and lives by his intercourse with nature. At the same time (and this 
is a point our English Marxist Christopher Caudwell emphasised in 
The Crisis in Physics ), by understanding the relation of men with 
nature it enhances and corrects the concept of nature, which is to 
some extent distorted so long as men’s intercourse with nature is 
misconceived. 


THE SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER OF MARXISM 


41 


But while materialist dialectics is in truth “nothing more nor less 
than scientific method”, that does not by any means reduce the field 
of inquiry of Marxist philosophy to the problems commonly debated 
by non-Marxists under the heading of “scientific method”. If we were 
to take Dr. Popper as our guide, these would be simply problems about 
the formal criteria of differentiation between “scientific” and “non- 
scientific” theories (the scientific ones are “falsifiable”), plus some 
problems about probability, induction (so-called), and the special 
techniques required for special investigations. I do not wish to suggest 
that these are not genuine problems, or that Dr. Popper and other 
contemporary writers on “scientific method” and “the logic of 
scientific discovery” have not dealt with them usefully. But it would 
not be true to suggest that the field of inquiry of dialectical 
materialism is reduced to “nothing more nor less” than these problems 
— because while these problems do fall within it, it comprises a great 
deal more . 

Dialectical materialism is primarily concerned with something 
which these more limited inquiries about scientific method neglect, 
namely, the way of thinking , the principles of working with and assembling 
concepts , requisite for scientific understanding in general. As Engels put 
it in the Preface of Anti-Duhring , the results of scientific work are 
summarised in concepts “but the art of working with concepts is not 
inborn and is not given with ordinary everyday consciousness, but 
requires real thought”; and consequently to master facts by theory 
we should be “equipped with the consciousness of the laws of dialectical 
thought”. Science, he added, “can no longer escape the dialectical 
synthesis”. But “to make this process easier for itself”, it must not 
only rid itself of so-called “philosophy standing apart from it, outside 
it and above it”, but also of its own traditional “limited method of 
thought”. 

This brings me to the question of the sort of approaches to which 
dialectical materialism is opposed . Marx and Engels said over and 
over again^that it is opposed to “idealism” and to “metaphysics”. 
Its opposition to “idealism” is expressed by the word “materialism”, 
and to “metaphysics” by die word “dialectics”. These words, expres- 
sive of opposition — “materialism” against “idealism”, and dialectics” 
against “metaphysics” — arc here used in rather specialised senses 
(different from those in which the same words are sometimes used 
in other contexts) which must now be explained. 


2 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 

I. MATERIALISM VERSUS IDEALISM 

“The great basic question of all philosophy,” wrote Engels {Ludwig 
Feuerbach , Chapter 2) concerns “the relation of thinking and being. 
. . . The answers which the philosophers gave to this question split 
them into two great camps. Those who asserted the primacy of spirit 
to nature . . . comprised the camp of idealism. The others, who regarded 
nature as primary, belong to the various schools of materialism .” 

Alice was reproached by the March Hare and the Mad Hatter with 
obscurity of utterance. Whatever could she mean? Similarly, many 
Wonderland philosophers profess themselves baffled by the obscurity 
of Engels’ statements. But like his younger contemporary, he simply 
meant what he said. 

In the above statement Engels opposed “thinking” to “being”, and 
“spirit” to “nature”, and said that “the great basic question of all 
philosophy” concerned which side of this opposition was “prior” to 
the other. Evidently, the opposition is that of the “material” on the 
one side, and the “non-material’ ’ (° r ‘ 'ideal”) on the other. He 
classed “being” and “nature” as “material”, and “thinking” and 
“spirit” as “non-material”. This is the sort of terminology regarded 
as so very obscure by many philosophers nowadays — but it is merely 
expressive of distinctions which are perfectly familiar to everyone, 
and which receive perfectly precise expression in the things people 
ordinarily say, however much some philosphers may try to confuse 
them. 

The “material”, as people ordinarily understand it (and we need 
not credit Engels with intending to give ordinary words any extra- 
ordinary meaning), is the sort of thing which affects the senses — which 
we can see, hear, smell, touch or taste. The non-material, on the other 
hand, is not accessible to the senses. Thus, for example, a tree or a 
mountain is material, whereas the idea of a tree or of a mountain is 
non-material. In ordinary language we would say that we see or touch 
a material thing, whereas we think or understand an idea. It would 
be as nonsensical to say that “we think a tree” as that “we see a 
thought”. Again, a person’s body is material, but his thoughts, desires, 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


43 


and other operations of his mind or “spirit” are non-material. Hence 
the opposition which Engels posed, between the material and non- 
material, or between “being” and “thinking”, or “nature” and “spirit”, 
is both familiar and obvious. 

From this opposition there ensues the opposition between materialism 
and idealism in theory, depending on the answer to the question 
“which is prior”, the material or the non-material. To be an idealist is 
to approach questions of the analysis and explanation of phenomena 
on the basis that there are ideas, intentions and purposes (whether of 
God or man), and that what is or happens is made what it is or made 
to happen by them, i.e. that the non-material is prior to the material. 
To be a materialist , on the other hand, is to approach such questions 
on the basis that there are material things and happenings, and that 
ideas about them, and intentions and purposes relating to them, 
result from the material circumstances in which such ideas, intentions 
and purposes are engendered, i.e. that the material is prior to the 
non-material. 

Thus to say that thunderstorms, for example, are manifestations of 
the anger of the gods exhibits an idealist approach, whereas to say 
that they are electrical disturbances exhibits a materialist approach. 
Again, to say that a social event (for instance, the French Revolution) 
is the expression of some idea (such as the idea of liberty) exhibits 
an idealist approach ; whereas to say that it results from class struggles 
rooted in the relations of production (from which also arise the 
characteristic ideas motivating the event) exhibits a materialist 
approach. Again, to say (as certain modern philosophers have said) 
that material objects are logical constructions out of the data of sense 
exhibits an idealist approach; whereas to say that the data of sense 
are the means whereby we become aware of material objects exhibits 
a materialist approach. 

All theories exhibit an idealist or a materialist approach (or in many 
cases a muddled and inconsistent mixture of the two), and “the great 
basic question of philosophy” is the question of which is the right 
approach to make. 

Marxism recommends and adopts a consistently materialist approach 
to all questions ; and it propounds and bases itself upon a materialist 
philosophy in as much as it investigates and formulates die guiding 
principles of a consistently materialist approach, in opposition to 
idealism. What are these principles? 

The first principle of materialism, as presented by the Marxist 


44 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


materialist philosophy, is that material processes certainly take place, 
and material things certainly exist, independent of any ideas about them. 

To explain this we need to enter a little further into the meaning of 
such words as “material” and “matter”, and the implications of their 
use. The use of the adjective “material” derives its meaning, of course, 
only from its opposition to “ideal”, “mental” or “spiritual”. Thus 
we speak of “matter” and “material processes” in contrast to “mind”, 
“spirit” and “ideas”. Thus if, for example, one says that a dining-room 
table is “material” one is not specifying some property of it, as one is 
when one says it is “made of wood” or “has a plastic top”. One is 
simply contrasting and distinguishing it from one’s idea of a table, 
emphasising that it is there in the dining-room independently of one’s 
idea of it. 

Materialism asserts the independence , the independent existence , of 
whatever is material. The use of the word “material”, in the Marxist 
statement of the fundamental standpoint of materialism, emphasises 
the existence of the material world independent of the ideas and per- 
ceptions by which we become aware of it, and of any other ideas, or 
ideal or spiritual entities, which may be imagined to exist. 

Thus in his work Materialism and Etnpirio-Criticism Lenin carefully 
explained that to speak of “material” things and processes, and in 
general of “matter” and of “the material world”, does not imply 
any particular theory of the constitution of material things (not, for 
instance, that they are made of “matter”, as distinct from being made 
of something else, such as “energy”; nor that they consist of “solid 
particles” as opposed, say, to “wave motions”). It implies their 
objective existence, -independent of our own or any other conscious- 
ness of them or ideas about them. As to the constitution of material 
things — what they are made of, what their structure is, what properties 
they have — that has to be found out by investigating them, and much 
of the product of such investigation must remain at the level of 
conjecture. 

Lenin’s exposition of the use of the terms “matter” and “material” 
in the statement of the fundamental standpoint of materialism was 
made in answer to those idealists who claimed that the discoveries of 
physics had demonstrated that “matter does not exist” and that 
“materialism is out of date”. True, the older materialist philosophies 
(derived from ancient speculations in Greece, China and India) were 
associated with a definite theory about the constitution of matter, 
namely, that the material world consists of solid indivisible particles, 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


45 


or “atoms”, moving about in empty space. In the seventeenth century 
Descartes regarded matter in another way, as “extended substance” 
filling space, and invented a theory of “vortices” in matter to account 
for various observed phenomena. Maxwell later elaborated the same 
type of idea when he postulated the “ether” which fills the whole of 
space and in which electro-magnetic waves occur. The old atomic 
theory of matter was discredited by subsequent investigations of the 
atom, and the theory of the ether was discredited by investigations 
of electro-magnetic phenomena and replaced by the theory of 
relativity. But that does not mean that physics has shown that there is 
no such thing as matter, or material process. The idealists who said it 
had were simply confusing materialism in general with relics of pre- 
scientific materialist speculation. Modem physics has replaced pre- 
scientific speculation by scientific investigation. That does not make 
materialism out of date, but only out-dates certain speculative 
materialist hypotheses. 

Does this, then, reduce materialism to nothing but the bare abstract 
assertion that there is an objective reality independent of ideas? No, 
for material things and processes are known to us through our sensa- 
tions and perceptions. As Lenin put it: “Matter is that which, acting 
upon our sense-organs, produces sensation; matter is the objective 
reality given to us in sensation.” Materialism does not consist in the 
merely empty assertion that something or other exists independent 
of ideas, but asserts that objective reality — the material world — has 
the fundamental characteristics of being knowable through the senses, 
that is, of causal process in space and time . 

The first principle of materialism can therefore be put like this : that 
causal process in space and time, given- to us in sensation, exists or 
continues independently of any mind or spirit, consciousness or idea. 
The second principle is the complement of this, and denies the in- 
dependent existence of anything non-material. Perceptions, ideas, 
intentions, feelings, purposes, ideals, consciousness and mind only 
exist as products of particular kinds of material processes. They are the 
perceptions, ideas and so on of material organisms, products of the 
functioning of specific organs of their bodies, formed in the conditions 
of their material mode of life. 

For materialism, then, there is nothing outside the material world. 
There is no separate or independent spiritual world, no mind or spirit 
separate from matter. There is one world, the material world; and, 
as Engels put it in Anti-Duhring , “ the unity of the world consists in its 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


46 

materiality”. “Space and time,” he wrote, are “the basic forms of all 
being”. There is nothing apart from what is comprised in causal 
process in space and time; and all those phenomena which we call 
mental or spiritual take place within the material world, as products of 
particular forms of material motion at particular times and places. 

Thirdly, then, materialism propounds the principles for a theory of 
man,* a general account of ourselves. We ourselves are material organ- 
isms. And as such we become aware of ourselves and of our environ- 
ment through the sensations which we obtain in the course of our 
material interactions, and through the processes of thought which we 
develop from our sensations. Although our senses may often deceive 
us and our ideas often prove illusory, nevertheless the material world 
which is given to us in our sensations, and which supplies all the data 
for our thought, objectively exists as the arena of all our action and 
the object of all our consciousness and knowledge. We get to know 
it and to know ourselves, and to master material processes for our own 
purposes and learn how to satisfy our needs, by active investigation, in 
which theory is first drawn from practical experience and then tested 
in it. 

Such, then, are the basic philosophical principles of materialism, as 
presented by Marxist philosophy in opposition to idealism. 

Dr. Popper, as we saw, has kindly said that there can be “no serious 
objection” to materialism, provided it is “reformulated” in some 
unspecified but nevertheless “comparatively easy” way. But he adds: 
“I should not describe myself as a materialist.” This addition bears 
witness, at least, to his honesty. For his part, he simply emphasises that 
theories should be susceptible to experiential test, and so be falsifiable; 
and he presumably finds no objection to materialism in so far, and only 
in so far, as it advocates that theories should be testable in experience. 
But he would not call himself a materialist because he regards the best 
of the theories as no more than conjectures, which one makes in order 
then to engage in the scientific pursuit of trying to falsify them — 
whereas materialism would generally be understood to imply (and 
Marx's materialism certainly does imply) something more. However 
conjectural and subject to correction particular theories about parti- 
cular things may be, materialism means claiming that there are principles 
to be adopted in formulating theories which are not conjectures at all, 
but are certainly true. 

Dr. Popper's exclusive emphasis on the conjectural character of 
scientific theories comes from his exclusive preoccupation with the 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


M 


way those theories are made subject to experiential test . Well of course, 
scientific theories are made subject to experiental test — otherwise they 
would not be scientific; and consequently they always do have a 
conjectural or provisional character. But what is the point of such 
theories? Why should it be considered so vitally important to place 
our whole trust in conjectures which are subject to experiential test 
and may therefore be falsified? Why prefer the hazard of reliance on 
conjectural and falsifiable theories to the assurance and satisfaction of 
reliance on unfalsifiable ones? Dr. Popper accuses Marxism of pro- 
pagating a reinforced dogmatism which is incapable of falsification 
and can provide a ready-made answer to any question. Marxism does 
at least answer the above questions, which is more than he can do. And 
in answering them we may now accuse him in return of inclining to a 
one-sided account of scientific theory, which is totally incapable of 
answering pertinent questions about science. 

We do not conjecture the existence of the material processes of which 
we ourselves are part and on which our very being, our whole 
conscious existence depends. We get to know them, and in knowing 
them learn in some degree to master them for our own purposes. 
That is what we do through science, and that is why scientific theories, 
made subject to experiential test, are so important for us. 

2. THE CASE AGAINST IDEALISM 

Engels had no doubt at all that materialism is the right approach, and 
idealism wrong — and the reasons for his confidence on this point are 
pretty clear. He was not a dogmatist who believed himself the prophet 
of some revelation “that matter is prior”. He was simply a scientific 
thinker, distinguished by a capacity for generalising the principles of 
his thinking, who realised that the idealist approach could never be 
productive of anything but what he called “fancies” — that is, theories 
which could not be tested, or which would be, as Dr. Popper now 
expresses it, “unfalsifiable”; whereas the materialist approach is the 
only one to produce testable theories. Thus in Chapter 4 of Ludwig 
Feuerbach he proceeded to justify the decision always to adopt the 
materialist approach, as follows: “It was resolved to comprehend the 
real world — nature and history— just as it presents itself to everyone 
who approaches it free from preconceived idealist fancies. It was 
decided relentlessly to sacrifice every idealist fancy which could not be 
brought into harmony with the facts conceived in their own and not 


48 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


in a fantastic connection. Materialism means nothing more than 
this/’ 

Evidently, then, it cannot be claimed that a theory is true because it 
is materialist — the truth of a theory can be substantiated only by testing 
and retesting it in experience. On the other hand, there can be no 
scientifically valid grounds for adopting any theory unless it is material- 
ist. Particular idealist theories may be rejected because they make 
assertions 'which do not accord with experience — but every idealist 
theory may be rejected, not because experience shows it to be false (for 
whatever the experience, some idealist fancy or other can always be 
thought up to account for it), but because it is a mere “preconceived 
fancy” which no experience can substantiate. However much particular 
materialist theories may be falsified by events, we can remain sure that 
the right explanation is along materialist lines; and however well 
particular idealist theories may evade falsification, we can remain sure 
that they are nevertheless mere fancies. That is why Marxism rejects 
every idealist theory about human affairs. But it does not adopt its 
own materialist theory because it claims to be able to deduce it from 
“first principles of materialist philosophy”. It adopts it because the 
investigation of human affairs leads to it; and Marxists continue to 
stand by it and develop it because it continues to ring true as a guide to 
practice unfalsified by the event. 

If we want to inform our practice, we cannot but follow the paths 
of materialism. If we want to find out what we are and what we can 
do, what our real needs are and how we can satisfy them, the materialist 
approach must be our guide. 

What is the fundamental error in idealism, as a way of thinking? 

To say, for example, that there are disembodied spirits, or first 
causes, or eternal forms (as different schools of idealism have said) is a 
quite different kind of error from saying that there are unicorns or 
phoenixes or (as Aristotle said in his treatise on zoology) sabre-toothed 
tigers. Similarly, it is a different kind of error to say that thunderstorms 
are caused by gods getting angry than it is to say (as certain early 
materialist speculations erroneously suggested) that they are caused by 
heavy particles in clouds banging against each other. Again, it is a 
different kind of error to say that one gets from Golders Green Crema- 
torium to Heaven via the ministrations of the Church of England than 
it is to say that one gets from London to Birmingham via Crewe. 

The latter sorts of error consist in wrongly describing and relating 
material things, and can be exposed and corrected in the course of 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


49 


practice, by observation and experiment. The former sorts of error are 
different, since spirits, first causes, eternal forms, gods and the way to 
Heaven are not observable, so that statements about them cannot be 
checked in the same practical empirical way. When one theologian 
says that only one angel can stand on the point of a needle while 
another says it will accommodate more, the way to enforce the one 
view against the other is to convene a church council and get the one 
party excommunicated, since it is impossible to devise any instrument 
for measuring the size of angels’ feet. 

All statement abstracts. For example, to say “This rose is red” 
abstracts a particular rose from the total environment, and its colour 
from the totality of its other properties. If a particular rose is red and 
I say that it is white, my statement is false in point of fact. The 
erroneousness or falsity of idealist statements, on the other hand, is not 
in the same way factual but consists in a false abstraction . Thus to say 
“Mr. Smith is at the office”, when in fact he has cut work to watch a 
cricket match, is to make a statement in which the abstraction of an 
object (Mr. Smith) from its environment, and of its whereabouts from 
the totality of its properties and relations, has been quite properly done, 
and the object has merely been asserted to be located somewhere else 
than where it is actually to be found. On the other hand, to say 
(supposing Mr. Smith to have died) “Mr. Smith’s soul is in Heaven” 
is to make an improper abstraction — for to abstract Mr. Smith’s soul 
from Mr. Smith is to make an abstraction such that the resulting state- 
ments cannot possibily be checked; and similarly to speak of Heaven is 
to speak of a place abstracted from space and time is such a manner 
that there is no possible way of finding who is or is not present there. 

The fundamental error of idealism, as a way of thinking, lies in its 
making false abstractions. This way of thinking is a habit, a method, a 
systematic use of false abstraction. 

Thus for example, an idealist historian may faithfully report that 
William the Conquerer won the Battle of Hastings and that King John 
signed Magna Carta. He may make no misstatement of fact. He does 
not say that people did things which they did not do, or did not do 
things which they did do. Some historians do go wrong in that way 
too, but it is not in this that idealism consists. Idealism consists in 
abstracting “minds”, “souls”, “spirits”, “ideas”, “intentions”, “ten- 
dencies”, and the like, in such a way as to represent them as independent 
entities, independent forces, which are then the operative causes of 
historical events. 


50 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


Now of course, people do have ideas and do act consciously; and if 
this characteristic of their activity is not taken into account, then their 
activity is misrepresented. But to represent “mind” or “consciousness” 
as though it were something which existed and operated independent 
of and prior to the total life activity of people who are conscious is to 
make a false abstraction. As Marx put it in the Preface to Critique of 
Political Economy , “it is not the consciousness of men that determines 
their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that determines their 
consciousness”. 

Similarly, Mr. Smith is conscious, and in that respect he differs from 
an automaton. To describe his mental processes and conscious motives 
is to abstract certain features of his life-process from the rest and to 
describe them, just as to describe, say, his eating habits and digestive 
processes is to make an abstraction. But it is not a false abstraction. 
What is a false abstraction is to say that his consciousness exists 
independently of his conscious activity in his material environment. 
To say he has a mind separate from his brain is rather like saying he 
has a digestion separate from his stomach. 

These examples make it evident that idealism is not a way of 
thinking invented by idealist philosophers. What the philosophers have 
done is rather to generalise and systematise popular ways of thinking 
(embodied in superstitions, myths and religions) into elaborate 
theories about the universe and about man and human knowledge. 
But in so doing, they have not only theorised about minds and spirits, 
human and divine, but engaged in further flights of false abstraction 
which the unphilosophical would never attempt. 

Thus, for example, Plato and all those philosophers who have been 
influenced by him right up to the present day abstracted the “forms” 
or “qualities” or “essences” of things, bestowed on them an idealised 
existence separate from and prior to things, and said that things are 
what they are because they partake of the form or essence. This 
doctrine is sometimes known as “realism” (though it is not very 
“realistic” in the common sense of that word), or better, “objective 
idealism”. In modern philosophy there arose a quite different doctrine, 
often known as “subjective idealism” (its clearest exponent was the 
Anglo-Irish philosopher George Berkeley). While objective idealism 
supposed the supersensible and divine essences to be somehow appre- 
hended and known by the intellect independent of the senses, subjective 
idealism arose from theorising about how we gain knowledge through 
our senses. It consists in abstracting the data of sense from the total 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


51 


situation in which a person is aware of his surroundings, bestowing on 
them an independent existence, and then saying that we have no reason 
to suppose that anything else exists and that what we call “material 
objects” are merely mental constructs out of sense-data. 

The examples show how false abstraction differs from false state- 
ment of fact. At the same time, false abstraction does make a certain 
kind of misrepresentation of fact: it misrepresents the ways happenings 
are connected and determined. For in place of the real connection and 
determination of events it poses a fantastic connection and deter- 
mination. For example, if you say that Mr. Smith cut work because of 
the sinful pleasure-seeking propensities of his soul, you have repre- 
sented his action as being determined by what goes on in his soul, 
whereas in fact it is determined by what goes on in his brain. For this 
reason an idealist way of thinking may, and usually does, lead to over- 
looking happenings, and connections between them, which a material- 
ist way of thinking leads one to search for and discover. Marx’s 
materialist approach led him to study economic processes and relations 
of production which the idealists had ignored — because their idealist 
way of explaining what happened made them blind to the significance 
of these processes and relations. They excused themselves from having 
to make the kind of scientific investigation Marx made. 

As Engels put it, materialism, or the materialist approach, consists 
in refusing to engage in “idealist fancy” or false abstraction, and 
resolving to comprehend the facts “in their own and not in a fantastic 
connection”. This involves investigating the facts in such a way as to 
find out what their own real connections are. To engage in idealist 
fancies, on the other hand, is to excuse oneself from any such investiga- 
tion. 


3. THE CASE FOR MATERIALISM 

The recommendation of the materialist approach is often opposed as a 
mere arbitrary dogma, and the materialist theoretical principles as 
incapable of proof. It is indeed logically impossible to prove from 
theoretical considerations alone that the materialist approach is 
requisite for the discovery of truth, and idealism productive only of 
fantasy. But that does not mean that materialism is to be dismissed as 
unproven. One great contribution made by Marx to the substantiation 
of the materialist approach was to have shown that its recommenda- 
tion is a conclusion from the requirements of practice , and is grounded 
on practical considerations. 


52 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


“The dispute over the reality or non-reality of thinking isolated 
from practice is a purely scholastic question”, wrote Marx, in his 
Theses on Feuerbach. If you set out to reach conclusions about what 
exists or does not exist, about which is prior, thinking or being, and 
about how tilings are really connected, by a purely theoretical deduc- 
tion from premises to conclusions, without any reference to practice 
and to what practice requires and what can be learned from it, then 
you can dispute for ever but can never prove any conclusion. Logic 
itself proves tills. For it proves that no existential conclusion can 
follow from any but an existential premise, and that no existential 
premise can be certified by pure theory as self-evidently or necessarily 
true. There are and can be no theoretically certified premises from 
which one can conclude as to how the world must be and how true 
theory can be worked out and tested. 

But theories are made by living people, who are not pure intel- 
ligences engaged in theorising, but practical agents whose practice 
leads them to theorise. “Social life is essentially practical”, Marx 
continued. “All mysteries which mislead theory into mysticism find 
their rational solution in human practice and in the comprehension of 
this practice.” The right approach to making theories, which will 
enable people in social practice to comprehend the facts in their own 
and not in a fantastic connection, has to be learned from trying to meet 
the requirements of practice , and is proved in terms of practical require- 
ments and in no other way. It is a practical question, not an exclusively 
theoretical one — and has to be answered as such. 

In theorising about practice Marxism brings into the practical 
argument in favour of materialism the conclusions of the empirical 
investigation of the actual conditions of human life. Marxism does not 
argue in terms of the bare abstract oppositions of “practice” against 
“theory”, but in terms of a concrete analysis of human practice, which 
shows how theory and practice can be made one, in such a way that 
theories are consciously derived from practical experience and serve 
to inform practice. 

What, then, is “practice”? What does this word mean in the context 
of the Marxist argument in favour of the materialist theoretical 
approach? 

To talk of “practice”, in this context, is to talk about certain activi- 
ties (or certain aspects of the activity) of human beings. In other 
contexts one may well talk about the practice of chimpanzees in 
swinging through the trees, or of bees in building honeycombs, but 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


53 


in the present context “practice" means “human practice”. The word 
is used to refer to certain unique kinds of activity performed by human 
beings. 

Of course, if organic life has evolved on other planets in the galaxies, 
and has evolved forms similar in relevant respects to human beings on 
the earth, then what we say about human practice would apply equally 
to the practice of these similar organisms. They would be able to draw 
conclusions from their practice in the same way as we do. In general, 
the laws of thought are the rules for drawing conclusions from practice ; and 
they would be the same for any thinking organism, just as the laws of 
nature would be. However, it will be convenient to ignore the possible 
existence of conscious intelligent life on other planets than the earth, 
and continue to talk only about ourselves — with the proviso that what 
we say about ourselves would presumably apply also to other organ- 
isms sufficiently like us. 

Human practice is characterised by its being at once conscious, 
purposive and productive. 

In The German Ideology Marx and Engels wrote that men “begin 
to distinguish themselves from animals as soon as they begin to produce 
their means of subsistence." " It is from the labour process that the whole 
of human practice derives its distinctive human character— just as it is 
from the forces of production and the relations which people enter 
into in using them that human society derives its specific features. 
Writing of the labour process, Marx said in Capital (Vol. i, Chapter 27) 
that it is “a process in which both man and nature participate, and in 
which man of his own accord starts, regulates and controls the material 
reactions between himself and nature . . . setting in motion arms and 
legs, head and hands, the natural forces of his body, in order to appro- 
priate nature"s productions in a form adapted to his own wants"". 
Human labour, he continued, differs from the various constructive 
operations of other animals. “A bee puts to shame many an architect 
in the construction of her cells. But what distinguishes the worst of 
architects from the best of bees is that the architect raises his structure 
in imagination before he erects it in reality."" From this is derived the 
distinctive character of human practice. The practical activities of the 
human body and its organs, in which individual men interact with 
objects environing them, arc consciously directed to an end which 
already exists “in imagination"". And by so acting people change 
external objects so as to adapt them to their wants. 

In the Theses on Feuerbach Marx described human practice as “activity 


54 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


through objects” — it consists of men's conscious interactions with 
objects in the course of which they purposively turn objects to their 
own use. It is because of the way we turn objects to our use (i.e. act 
on them consciously, purposively and productively) that we form 
ideas of them — of their existence, their properties and relations, and of 
what we can do with them. Those ideas, Marx concluded, are first 
formed in human practice, and they can only be tested in practice, 
which he termed “human sensuous activity”. It is in practice, and only 
in practice, that we can establish the truth about objects. 

By calling practice “sensuous activity” Marx was calling attention 
to the circumstance that all our conscious action on objects depends 
on their acting on our sense-organs. The operations of the hands, to 
which he refers in describing the labour process, have to be initiated by 
and guided by sense-perceptions. It was with this in mind that Engels 
replied (in the Introduction to Socialism , Utopian and Scientific) to those 
philosophers who argued that there are no good grounds for supposing 
that any objects at all exist corresponding to our perceptions. “This 
line of reasoning”, he said, “seems undoubtedly hard to beat by mere 
argument. But before there was argument there was action. . . . And 
human action had solved the difficulty long before human ingenuity 
invented it. . . . From the moment we turn objects to our own use we 
put to an infallible test the correctness or otherwise of our perceptions. 
If these perceptions have been wrong, then our estimate of the use to 
which an object can be turned must also be wrong, and our attempt 
must fail. But if we succeed in accomplishing our aim, if we find that 
the object does agree with our idea of it and does answer the purpose 
we intended it for, then that is positive proof that our perceptions of 
it and of its qualities, so far, agree with reality outside ourselves . . . 
the result of our action proves the conformity of our perceptions with 
the objective nature of the things perceived.” 

It is, of course, inherent in practice that it can be successful or un- 
successful — and that in varying degree. In so far as what people do fails 
to meet the end they set themselves, or fails to satisfy their wants, 
practice is unsuccessful. So there is always a kind of “trial and error” 
going on in practice. And in this we test and (if we have any sense) 
try to correct our ideas. 

Human practice requires, and always must require, to be informed . 
By this I mean that in order to act on the objects surrounding us in a 
practical way, so as to contrive to turn them to our own use, we must 
first of all manage to obtain perceptions from which to conclude as to 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


55 


how things actually are, and then formulate (in language) concepts and 
theories about the properties and connections of objects in the light of 
which we can plan out what to do. 

The information which we require for practice begins with sensa- 
tions. But sensations, or sense-perceptions, are not themselves in- 
formation, in the sense in which I am here using the word. On the other 
hand, all information is derived from and checked by perception. 

Being conscious, purposive and productive, human practice has a 
social co-operative character. A man on his own can, of course, do all 
sorts of things; but that is only because he learns at least the rudiments 
of human practice in association with other men. To conceive purposes, 
to imagine something that can be made and to set about making it, 
people have to work together and learn from each other. They have 
to have evolved language, or the means of communication in articulate 
speech. The information which practice requires is communicable , and is 
expressed in sentences and conveyed by language. Sensations are not com- 
municable; but aware through sensation of the objects of their practical 
activity, people formulate and communicate information about 
objects to inform and guide their practice. 

A builder, for example, could not build anything unless he could 
see (or at least touch) his various building materials. But the mere sight 
of a lot of bricks does not by itself supply the information required for 
building. In this, as Marx observed, the human builder differs from, 
and shows his superiority to, various other animals which build things. 
For the nesting bird it suffices to see a bit of straw, and it picks it up and 
adds it to the nest: it acts instinctively, and does not require to be 
informed, as people do. Hence also it can get along with merely 
chirruping, and does not require to speak and be spoken to. The 
human builder, on the other hand, not only distinguishes the various 
materials of his trade by sight, but also requires such information about 
them as “This is a brick”, “This is the hod for carrying bricks”, “This 
is the mortar to stick them together”, and so on. And as well as such 
particular information, be also requires information of a more generalised 
kind, such as “The bricks must be aligned like this or else the wall will 
fall down”. True, a skilled man knows all this by heart, and does not 
keep repeating it to himself all the time, or asking his mates. He does 
not mutter to himself “This is a brick” every time he picks one up, or 
consult with his mates to decide what it is. Nevertheless it is on such 
communicable information that his skill is based. 

Theory is required by men to inform practice. And while the word 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


56 

“theory” is commonly reserved for communications of a certain 
degree of generality, every item of information is, strictly speaking, 
an item of theory. The theory of an object generalises about it beyond 
whatever is immediately present to the senses at any time. Evidently 
therefore, such a statement as “This is a brick” is a theory — in just the 
same way as “This is a structure in which atoms are arranged in a 
certain pattern” is a theory: the second statement embodies more 
generalised theory than the first, that is the only .difference. In fact, all 
statements are theories. And theoretical work or activity does not, 
rightly understood, consist exclusively in cooking up particular kinds 
of very generalised statements, but in arranging, co-ordinating, 
checking and criticising statements for the purpose of assembling 
information. 

Theory to inform practice must fulfd, then, two very obvious con- 
ditions. First, it must deal with sensible objects f their properties and 
relations. For since our practice consists of interactions with objects 
that affect our senses, it is obvious that what informs practice is in- 
formation about such objects. Second, what it says must be capable of 
being tested in the practical experience of our interactions with objects. 
This means that it must lead us to expect that certain observable 
happenings will result in other observable happenings : if they do not, 
then the theory is (so far at least) falsified. 

Thus, for example, the theory that informs building operations 
deals with sensible objects, such as bricks. And what it says about them 
is capable of experiential test. The theory that “This is a brick” would 
be falsified if, on picking it up, it went off Bang ! And the more general 
theory of building would be falsified if, in the absence of eathquakes 
or air raids, most of the buildings fell down. Obviously, a theory 
incapable of falsification would not impart any expectation regarding 
the objects we deal with in practice, and so would not inform practice. 
That is why the condition of falsification, which Dr. Popper so properly 
and vehemently stresses, is of such great practical importance in the 
making of theory. 

The practical reason for keeping theory materialist is now evident. 
It is that only on that condition can theory inform and continue to 
inform practice. 

But does not idealist theory also claim to inform practice, and to 
supplement in important ways statements about material things? 

Let us suppose that someone asks the way to church, and is told: 
“Straight on and the second on the right — then you will get to the 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


57 


church.” Having acted on this theory and found the church, he then 
asks the way to Heaven, and is told: “Pay two-and-sixpence and light 
a candle — then when you die your soul will go to Heaven.” He acts 
on this theory too, and pays up and lights the candle. But it does not 
inform his practice in the way the other theory did, because in the first 
place it concerns his soul, which is not an object in any way accessible 
to the senses, and in the second place it cannot be tested in experience 
and is incapable of verification or falsification. He is not informed , 
but is simply handed out instructions which he has to take on trust. 
Information is capable of being tested in practice as you follow it up — 
but not the theory handed out in church. What is the faithful believer 
to do when he meets an atheist who tells him he has no soul and there 
is no such place as Heaven, or when he visits another place of worship 
where they tell him it is not of the slightest use lighting candles? He 
can only reaffirm his faith. 

This example illustrates the difference between informative and un- 
informative theory. And it also shows how easy it is to suppose that 
uninformative theory is informative. It appears to be informative 
because it prescribes certain courses of action, just as informative 
theory does. “You want certain results? Then do something. You want 
to go to church? Then take the second on the right. You want to save 
your soul? Then light a candle.” But it prescribes without informing. 
For the end which the prescription is prescribed to serve is defined as 
lying outside practical recognition, and whether it is achieved or not 
cannot be practically decided. It simply instructs you what to do, but 
offers no test of whether it leads to the results claimed for it. 

All idealism bears this deceptive character. The idealist false abstrac- 
tion is a pretence at information. It simulates information, and often 
stands as a substitute for it — but it does not inform. It is sham informa- 
tion. It is in this that its falsity consists. Information is true or false, and 
one can decide which by testing it in practice. But sham information 
cannot be tested. It does not present the same alternative of “true or 
false” because it is not susceptible to any decision procedure. It is 
“false”, not in the sense in which a statement of fact is false when 
objects are related differently from how the statement says they are, 
but in the sense in which, say, a beggar on horseback is a false gentle- 
man — it is not what it purports to be. 

It is perhaps partly for these reasons that, in a scientific age, there is 
a growing tendency, at all events within the Christian religion, for 
religious believers to maintain that what is important, what really 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


58 

counts, in Christian teachings, are its precepts about the development 
of individual personality and human relations rather than its doctrines 
about another world. This is one of the reasons for the development 
of the contemporary “dialogue” between Christians and Communists, 
who on such questions find themselves in a good deal more agreement 
than either side previously supposed could be possible. What would 
be left of religion, and how long it could survive as an institution, 
supposing its precepts to be detached from the false abstractions with 
which they have always hitherto been associated, is a problem for 
the religious. So far as Marxists are concerned, we are not disposed to 
quarrel with people about what may happen to us after we are dead 
if we are able to reach a measure of agreement as to what to do so long 
as we remain alive. Marxists consider that to decide the latter questions 
we require only verified information about the conditions of our 
life in this world. Our grounds for always adopting a strictly material- 
istic approach in theory, and always rejecting the idealist approach, 
consist in the fact that only by adopting the materialist approach can 
we hope to inform our practice , whereas the idealist approach can 
never achieve anything but a pretence at information. 

It may be said that we do not want merely to inform our practice 
but to discover “the truth”, which serves higher ends than mundane 
practical ones. But what is this but to use the phrase “the truth” for 
the purpose of embellishing groundless fancies which serve to dictate 
modes of practice but not to inform them? We have no other way of 
seeking truth — that is, framing our ideas so as to correspond with the 
facts — than by seeking to inform our practice and testing our ideas 
accordingly. 

Again, it is said that to adopt a view according to which man is a 
purely material being, with no “soul”, is to adopt a very narrow view 
of human practice — for men are deeply concerned with “spiritual” 
things too, and impoverish themselves if they ignore them. Well, of 
course we are not concerned in practice only with material satis- 
factions, but with the satisfactions to be got from human relations, 
from love and companionship, and from cultivating all the higher 
human qualities of individuals. If by “soul” and “spiritual life” these 
things are meant, then of course it is no “fancy” to say that we possess 
souls and the capacity for spiritual life, and our practice includes our 
spiritual life too. But to recognise that does not require us to postulate 
immortal souls distinct from bodies. As a matter of fact, those who 
do so have so far signally failed to do much to raise the capacity for 


THE MATERIALIST APPROACH 


59 


“spiritual life” of the majority of human beings. For if people’s 
material life is impoverished, they do not get much chance to cultivate 
the things of the spirit— just as they do not do so either if they fail 
to appreciate the real character of human relations and concern 
themselves with nothing but their own individual material satisfactions. 
If only we can better inform our practice, in the materialist sense, by 
getting better to know ourselves, our needs, our dependencies on one 
another, we stand at least a chance of finding how in practice to 
cultivate all the higher human capacities, the things of the spirit. 


3 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


I. DIALECTICS VERSUS METAPHYSICS 

The materialist approach, as recommended by Marxism, has to be 
dialectical . While opposing “materialism” to “idealism”, Marx and 
Engels opposed “dialectics” to what they called “metaphysics”. This 
means that the necessary approach for working out informative theory 
is that of materialist dialectics — in opposition to the idealist error of false 
abstraction, and also to the sort of error denoted by the word “meta- 
physics”. 

In several passages of his writings Engels said what he meant- by 
“metaphysics”, or the metaphysical way of thinking, and by “dialec- 
tics” in contrast to “metaphysics”. Although the account with which 
Dr. Popper has favoured us of what “dialectics” means in Marxist 
philosophy supposes that what Engels meant was something entirely 
different from what he said, I shall continue to assume that Engels 
nevertheless meant what he said — including what he said in those 
passages where he said what he meant. 

“The metaphysical mode of thought,” wrote Engels in Anti- 
Duhring (Chapter i), consists in “the habit of considering objects and 
processes in isolation, detached from the whole vast interconnection 
of things; and therefore not in their motion, but in their repose; not as 
essentially changing, but as fixed constants. . . .” Thus “in considering 
individual things it loses sight of their connections ; in contemplating 
their existence it forgets their coming into being and passing away; 
in looking at them at rest it leaves their motion out of account. ...” 

In opposition to metaphysics, he continued, the dialectical way of 
thinking considers things “in their interconnection, in their sequence, 
their movement, their birth and their death”. 

As so defined, metaphysics consists in failure properly to connect. And 
dialectics, on the other hand, consists in properly tracing out connections. 

Strictly speaking, Engels’ addition of “sequence, movement, birth 
and death” to “interconnection” was redundant and unnecessary — 
a mere labouring of the point, done perhaps (though done in vain) for 
the benefit of those who study dialectics at mad tea parties where points 
are not always very clear. For quite evidently, if one fails to take 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


6 1 


account of “sequences, movements, births and deaths”, one thereby 
“loses sight” of an essential element in “the whole vast intercon- 
nection”. 

To study “interconnections” is, therefore, a sufficient definition of 
the dialectical approach. So Engels, at the head of the chapter on 
“Dialectics” in Dialectics of Nature (Chapter 2), wrote that the study 
of the laws or principles governing the dialectical approach, and the 
dialectical understanding of the real world, should “be developed as 
the science of interconnections, in contrast to metaphysics”. 

Some may complain that in thus opposing “dialectics” to “meta- 
physics” Engels created confusions by using the latter word in a 
different sense from that in which it has often been used by other 
writers, both before and since. He used it in fact in a sense in which 
it was quite commonly used in Germany at his time, and which 
was employed by Hegel. And as he did explain quite clearly, and 
certainly more clearly than other German writers did, what this sense 
was, there is no good reason for finding his meaning obscure. By 
contrast, the other senses in which some philosophers have used the 
word “metaphysics” do leave a lot to be desired by way of clarification. 

In the contemporary literature of would-be scientific philosophy, 
for example, the word seems often to stand for any doctrine that the 
particular philosopher disagrees with — and especially for any doctrine 
which says that the real world is other than it seems to be, and that 
the true nature of reality cannot be discovered by observation and 
experiment but only by pure reason. Of course, the dialectical mate- 
rialist approach agrees with that of these other philosophers in finding 
such doctrines unacceptably “metaphysical”; but it finds many of 
their own doctrines equally so. What it objects to alike in their own 
“metaphysics” and in the “metaphysics” to which they are opposed 
is the failure to connect “appearance” and “reality”, or the data of sense 
and the circumstances they reflect. Those whom many contemporary 
philosophers call “metaphysicians” consider “reality” as something 
quite separate from its “appearance”; but the “anti-metaphysical” 
philosophers consider the appearances in isolation and take them to be 
the complete reality. 

At the same time, it should perhaps be admitted that, if we take 
into account how the term “metaphysics” originated long ago, the 
subsequent use made of this term to denote the antithesis of dialectics 
can be regarded as somewhat unfortunate. In its original use, the word 
“metaphysics”, which is Greek in derivation and means “after physics”, 


62 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


was the title given by the editors of the manuscripts of Aristotle to that 
philosopher’s treatise on what he called “being as being”. They gave 
this treatise that title for the simple reason that in their arrangement 
of his works it came next after his treatise on physics. It was largely as 
a result of the discredit into which Aristotle fell at the start of the 
modern age that the word subsequently acquired a perjorative signi- 
ficance, and was used to denote any sort of philosophical discourse 
which combines obscurity of expression with a priori reasoning. But 
the treatise of Aristotle to which the title was given was in fact a 
treatise about the universal interconnections of things, investigating 
in particular the connections between “substance” and “form”, and 
“potentiality” and “actuality”. To be fair to Aristotle, therefore, his 
“metaphysics” can properly be regarded as one of the first systematic 
essays in dialectics. So far from being guilty of the fallacy of meta- 
physics in the sense defined by Engels, that is to say, considering things 
apart from their connections, he sought to show how things must be 
understood in their connections And so if by “metaphysics” we were 
to mean anything which follows up Aristotle’s original treatise, then 
we would have to call any general statement of principles of dialectics 
“metaphysics”. 

In view of all this, and of the ambiguities attaching to the uses of 
the word “metaphysics”, one might well wish to employ some other 
word to denote the mode of thought to which Engels opposed dialec- 
tics — and the simple expression “undialectical” at once presents itself. 
However, after its employment for more than a century in the sense 
defined by Engels, the word “metaphysics” has become so firmly 
entrenched in the discussion of dialectics that Humpty Dumpty 
himself could perhaps not now hope to press any other word into this 
employment. Its use need occasion no confusion, providing one bears 
always in mind the definition which has been given of it. 

Having described the metaphysical or undialectical way of thinking 
(in Chapter i of Anti-Duhritig), Engels said that what is wrong with 
it is that it “becomes one-sided, limited, abstract, and loses its way in 
insoluble contradictions”. I have already quoted some of these con- 
tradictions when making the point that, far from welcoming them, 
the dialectician agrees with the formal logician in finding them highly 
objectionable. Metaphysics “loses its way” in contradictions, which 
become “insoluble” for it. Dialectics, on the other hand, finds the way 
to solve them by getting rid of them. 

The undialectical way of thinking of things and their properties 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 63 

“in isolation, detached from the whole vast interconnection”, leads to 
a formal counterposing of “is . . .” and “is not . . 

Thus, for example, considering living creatures, as Engels put it, 
“each one separately”, it would seem that they have the property of 
being “alive”, which is the opposite of, and incompatible with, being 
“dead”. However, if one considers what actually happens to them, 
in the real circumstances of their interactions with their environments, 
it is quite evident that death is a process. If that process continues long 
enough, the animal is quite definitely dead at the end of it ; but during 
the process it survives in an intermediate condition. This fact is often 
illustrated nowadays at hospitals. Someone “dies”, in the sense that 
his heart stops beating and he ceases to breathe, so that the processes of 
organic disintegration set in. But for a short time he remains sufficiently 
“alive” for the doctors to bring him back to life. Did he “die” or not? 
A less dramatic example of the same point is afforded by men who are 
losing all their hair. At a given moment, is such a man “bald” or “not 
bald”? The answer is that he is “growing bald”, and that if he doesn’t 
apply a hair restorer he will soon become completely bald. 

Such examples are extremely simple and obvious, and as such not of 
great interest. As we shall see, the application of the same principle in 
other cases produces conclusions of greater interest. But meantime the 
simple examples make the basic point. 

What is characteristic of the undialectical or metaphysical way of 
thinking, wrote Engels in the Preface to Anti-Duhring , is that it poses 
“rigid antitheses” and “sharp impassible dividing lines”. It disconnects. 
But the continued investigation by the sciences of how things are 
connected in the real process of nature (and of society) means that these 
hard and fast antitheses and divisions “are more and more disappear- 
ing”. Engels quoted a number of examples. “Since it has been proved 
that a body can be brought into a condition in which the liquid and 
gaseous forms cannot be distinguished from each other, the physical 
states have lost the last relics of their former absolute character. . . . 
And since biology has been pursued in the light of the theory of 
evolution, in the domain of organic nature one fixed boundary line of 
classification after another has been swept away.” 

Hence his conclusion : “The recognition that antagonisms and dis- 
tinctions are in fact to be found in nature, but only with relative validity, 
and that on the other hand their imagined rigidity and absoluteness 
have been introduced into nature only by our minds — this recognition 
is the kernel of the dialectical conception of nature.” 


6 4 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


Hence he wrote in Chapter i : “To the metaphysician, things and 
their mental images, ideas, are isolated, to be considered one after 
the other apart from each other, rigid fixed objects of investigation, 
given once for all. He thinks in absolutely irreconcilable antitheses. . . . 
For him a thing either exists or it does not exist: it is equally impossible 
for a thing to be itself and at the same time something else. Positive 
and negative absolutely exclude one another; cause and effect stand 
in an equally rigid antithesis one to the other.” 

But once one has grasped the point of dialectics, Engels wrote 
(Ludwig Feuerbach, Chapter 4), “one no longer permits oneself to be 
imposed upon by the antitheses insuperable for the old metaphysics. . . . 
One knows that these antitheses have only a relative validity. ...” 

In all these examples and explanations one looks in vain for the 
“thesis, antithesis and synthesis”, and acceptance of logical contradic- 
tion, so beloved of Dr. Popper and other debunkers of dialectics 
(so beloved because so very easy to debunk). Engels’ point in contrast- 
ing “dialectics” to “metaphysics” is quite simple, clear, and even 
painfully obvious. Metaphysics poses “absolutely irreconcilable anti- 
theses”, in the form of disjunctions: “Either it is ... or it is not . . ., 
but not both.” Such disjunctions do reflect distinctions and oppositions 
which are in fact to be found in the world. But they are nevertheless 
“only of relative validity”. Dialectics consists in following up the 
connections of opposites, as discoverable in the real processes of nature 
and society. In these processes things come into being, change and 
pass away, not each separately, but in interaction and interrelation 
within “the whole vast interconnection of things”. 

When quotation from Engels removes the sort of objections to 
dialectics which, as we saw earlier, Dr. Popper lodged (for it is clear 
that Engels could not have meant what Dr. Popper says dialectical 
materialism means), a quite different kind of objection is sometimes 
lodged. This is the objection that what Engels said was obvious, and 
so obvious as to be trivial. The erroneous undialectical or “meta- 
physical mode of thought” to which he opposed dialectics, is a dead 
duck. No sensible person would ever think in such a way, so why 
make up a whole philosophy out of “dialectics” as opposed to “meta- 
physics”? “Dialectical materialism” turns out to be a mere truism. 

The answer to this objection falls into two parts. The first part is 
that any philosophical principles which can be definitively established 
must always be, in a sense, mere truisms. Philosophies which appear 
as revelations of mysteries, revealed one knows not how, are, scienti- 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


65 

fically speaking, fraudulent. Valid philosophical points must be capable 
of being made “obvious”, otherwise they cannot be valid. Hence 
Engels himself said (in Dialectics of Nature , Chapter 2) that, if only it is 
properly explained, dialectics must “become as simple and clear as 
noonday”. 

The second part of the answer is that the so-called “metaphysical 
mode of thought” is in fact anything but a dead duck, but is, on the 
contrary, widely engaged in with unfortunate consequences. To learn, 
formulate and inculcate the obvious principles of dialectical thinking is, 
therefore, far from unworthy of serious attention. 

It is true that, as Engels said, all successful scientific thinking is, and 
must be, dialectical. All the same, to advise even scientists on the 
principles of dialectical as opposed to metaphysical thinking is not 
altogether the same as teaching one’s grandmother to suck eggs. 
For what Engels also said is still worth quoting, even though not now 
so true as it was at the time he said it: “The scientists who have learnt 
to think dialectically are still few and far between, and hence the 
conflict between the discoveries made and the old traditional mode of 
thought is the explanation of the boundless confusion which now 
reigns in theoretical natural science and reduces both teachers and 
students, writers and readers, to despair” (. Anti-Duhring , Chapter 1). 

In more abstract and philosophical spheres the confusions that result 
from the metaphysical mode of thought, or lack of dialectics, are 
evident and notorious. One need not go back to the Middle Ages, or 
even to the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, for examples. The 
most up-to-date kind of “logical-analytic” philosophy started off with 
the extremely “metaphysical” statements in which Russell and Witt- 
genstein enunciated the principles of so-called “logical atomism”. 
“The existing world consists of many things with many qualities and 
relations”, Russell announced in Our Knowledge of the External World 
(Chapter 2). “A complete description of the existing world would 
require not only a catalogue of the things, but also a mention of all 
their qualities and relations.” And Wittgenstein elaborated this in 
certain famous propositions of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: 
“The world is everything that is the case. . . . The world divides into 
facts. Any one can either be the case or not be the case, and everything 
else remain the same. What is the case, the fact, is the existence of 
atomic facts. An atomic fact is a combination of objects. . . . The 
object is the fixed, die existent. . . . The configuration of the objects 
forms the atomic fact. . . . Atomic facts are independent of one 


66 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


another.” Russell and Wittgenstein saddled themselves, in their later 
activity, and their followers, with the unenviable task of trying to 
solve the numerous conundrums posed by these metaphysical state- 
ments. 

In the philosophy of science, the “insoluble contradictions” posed 
by the metaphysical separation and counterposing of opposites supply 
further examples of the prevalence of metaphysics. Thus “particles” 
and “waves”, “matter” and “energy”, “determinism” and “indeter- 
minism”, continue to stand in “irreconcilable antithesis”. In the dis- 
cussion of ethics the metaphysical counterposing of “freedom of 
choice” and “determinism” still provides a subject for fruitless debate. 

Finally, the metaphysical mode of thought is by no means widiout 
its influence in everyday and practical affairs. Take politics, for example. 
Engels said that metaphysicians adopt the precept from The Gospel 
according to Saint Matthew (5, 37): “Let your communication be Yea, 
Yea, Nay, Nay, for whatsoever is more than these cometh of evil.” 
When people talk and act in terms of political formulas, and have a 
set of labels readymade to stick on to everything so as to judge it in 
accordance with its label, regardless of the actual changing circum- 
stances in which both parties and individuals are acting and changing 
themselves by their actions, what is this but political metaphysics? 

In the passages from which I quoted earlier, Engels mentioned some 
more difficult and interesting examples than the simple and easy ones 
with which we began. 

“Closer investigation also shows us that the two poles of an anti- 
thesis, like positive and negative, are just as inseparable from each other 
as they are opposed, and that despite all their opposition they mutually 
penetrate each other. It is just the same with cause and effect: these are 
conceptions which only have validity in their application to a parti- 
cular case as such, but when we consider the particular case in its 
general connection with the world as a whole they merge and dissolve 
in the conception of universal action and interaction, in which causes 
and effects are constantly changing places, and what is now or here an 
effect becomes there or then a cause, and vice versa” (Anti-Duhring, 
Chapter 1). 

Again: “That which is recognised now as true has also its latent false 
side which will later manifest itself, just as that which is now regarded 
as false has also its true side by virtue of which it could previously have 
been regarded as true.” And again: “One knows that what is main- 
tained to be necessary is composed of sheer accidents, and that the so- 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


67 

called accidental is the form behind which necessity hides itself” 
(Ludwig Feuerbach , Chapter 4). 

To get the point of dialectics one need only consider how many 
confused and confusing arguments have resulted from such abstract 
oppositions as “true” and “false”, “cause” and “effect”, or “necessity” 
and “accident”. Fruitful discussion will always keep an eye open for 
the “latent false side” in propositions put forward as true, and for the 
element of truth in propositions condemned as false. Again, one may 
remember the confusion that results in discussion about social develop- 
ment when the idea that political actions are the effects of economic 
causes is divorced from the obvious fact that economic effects are 
caused by political actions. Or again, it is interesting to analyse the 
paradoxes and contradictions which accrue from saying that “every- 
thing happens by necessity”, where “necessity” is supposed to exclude 
“accident”. This last is a typical example of what many philosophers 
besides Marxists would recognise as a “metaphysical statement”. 
The error in it results from counterposing the concepts of “necessity” 
and “accident” without analysing their interconnectedness; or, as some 
contemporary philosophers put it, not considering how such words as 
“necessity” and “accident” are properly used together in describing 
what actually happens. 


2. MATERIALIST DIALECTICS 

The account rendered of dialectics by Engels makes it quite clear that, 
for Marxism, the dialectical approach means considering things in 
their real interconnections, instead of separately — and therefore in their 
changes (“coming to be and passing away”) instead of in abstraction 
from change. 

There is the less excuse for Dr. Popper’s making out that “dialectics” 
means nonsense about “thesis, antithesis and synthesis”, because the 
actual use of the term by Engels and all competent Marxists in fact 
corresponds to its customary use over the years (not merely centuries, 
but millennia) by other philosophers. 

Thus Plato, for example, stressed again and again the need for a 
“dialectical” approach, and for the understanding of “dialectic”, 
precisely in order to avoid fallacies and contradictions resulting from 
thinking of things in a merely abstract way. Indeed, it was just this 
emphasis which accounts for the progressive quality of Plato’s thought, 
despite his idealism and political reactionariness. His approach was 


68 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


the very reverse of metaphysical dogmatism; he was always inquiring, 
so that his Dialogues have remained living dialogues for over two 
thousand years, and will go on living so long as people go on thinking. 
In one place Plato illustrated “dialectic” by asking whether one of his 
fingers was short or long, and pointing out that it was short in relation 
to longer things and long in relation to shorter things. In other places 
he said that “dialectic” consisted in properly sorting out the relations 
of likeness and difference between things of a kind. Those who over- 
looked dialectic, he pointed out, got into absurdities and contradictions 
by posing what Engels afterwards called “irreconcilable antitheses”. 
Thus a man who says his fmger is not short but long gets involved in 
contradiction when he is made to admit that it is also short, and a man 
who says how different things are when he is made to admit how like 
they are. 

Hegefs dialectic was derivative from Plato’s; and similarly, his 
idealism was of the same “objective” type as Plato’s — a resemblance 
duly observed by Dr. Popper in The Open Society and its Enemies , 
though he misrepresents Hegel on a scale that makes his misrepre- 
sentation of Marx seem almost like scholarly accuracy. 

The purpose of dialectics, Hegel wrot c (Logic, 81) “is to study things 
in their own being and movement”. And to do this, he pointed out, 
we must study the connections of opposites — not simply hold them apart 
but connect them together. “We say, for instance, that man is mortal, 
and seem to think that the ground of his death is in external circum- 
stances only ; so that if this way of looking at it were correct, man 
would have two separate properties, vitality and — also — mortality. 
But the true view of the matter is that life, as life, involves the germ of 
death, and that the finite, being radically self-contradictory, involves 

its own self-suppression. ... its own nature is the cause of its abroga- 
• >» 
tion. 

The difficulty in Hegel (as in Plato, but much more so) results from 
his idealism. He supposed that concepts or ideas are prior to things, and 
that the forms of relationship and development observable in the world 
are but realisations of concepts — so that the ways things are connected 
are deducible from the ways concepts are connected. A concept is 
correlated with and cannot be dissociated from its opposite (as “being” 
with “non-being”, “quantity” with “quality”, “continuity” with 
“discontinuity”, “life” with “death”, and so on). Hence (Hegel 
concluded) in the material world, where concepts are realised, oppo- 
sites are indissociable. Quantitative changes consequendy pass into 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


69 

qualitative changes, and the hard is soft, the short is long, the contin- 
uous is discontinuous, in the midst of life we are in death, and so 
forth. The artificiality and fallaciousness of Hegel’s “dialectic” was 
due to the way he sought to deduce concrete connections of things 
from abstract connections of concepts. Thus in the notorious opening 
section of his Logic he claimed to deduce the temporality and change- 
fulness of things (“becoming”) from the correlation of the abstract 
concepts of “being” and “nothing”: because of this, he said, whatever 
has being must necessarily pass into nothing. 

In a well-known passage (the Afterword to the second German 
edition of Capital) Marx said that with Hegel dialectics was “standing 
on its head. It must be turned right side up, if you would discover the 
rational kernel within the mystical shell.” Instead of trying to deduce 
the interconnections in the real world from the development of con- 
cepts, we should try to develop our concepts in such a way as to reflect 
the interconnections in the real world. To do that is materialist dialectics. 

Hegel (and, to a lesser degree, Plato) provides an object lesson in 
how a good dialectical, as opposed to an undialectical or metaphysical, 
approach can be turned into nonsense by being combined with ideal- 
ism. Materialist thinking, prior to Marx, likewise provides object 
lessons in how a good materialist, as opposed to idealist, approach can 
be turned into nonsense by being combined with metaphysics, or by 
being dialectical. 

Dialectical materialism is critical not only of idealism but also 
of metaphysical materialism. Marx and Engels included under the 
latter heading both ancient materialists, like Democritus and Epicurus, 
and modem ones like the French Encyclopaedists — the latter being also 
called “mechanical materialists” because of their idea that the laws of 
mechanics were fundamental for all material systems. All these mate- 
rialist thinkers persisted in thinking in terms of “rigid antitheses” 
and “sharp impassible dividing lines”. 

Thus ancient materialism posed the antithesis of space, as a sort of 
empty container, and matter, as what was to be found inside it. 
Democritus put forward the well-known metaphysical proposition, 
that what exists is “atoms in the void”. This idea was simply taken for 
granted by the founders of modem physical science (Newton and 
others), and the subsequent scientific development of relativity theory 
and field theory (which connect space, time and matter) was necessary in 
order to try to get over the consequent theoretical difficulties. 

Again, and especially in modern materialism, matter was separated 


70 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


from motion. Matter was thought of as either at rest or in motion, and 
some impulse had always to be given to it to get it moving. This led 
to the idea that God created matter and gave it its laws of motion, and 
then gave it a push so that thereafter material things kept moving. 

Again, mechanical materialism took over from ancient materialism 
the metaphysical separation of mechanical motion, as spatial dis- 
placement of particles of matter, from all those forms of motion 
(such as chemical changes, or vital processes like sensations, perception 
and thought) which can be described only in qualitative terms. The 
former was then said to be the real motion, while the latter were only 
forms of appearance associated with it. The metaphysical separation of 
mechanical from other forms of motion was thus at the same time a 
metaphysical counterposing of appearance and reality. All that really 
happens in the world is that particles of matter move and interact 
according to the laws of mechanics. This led to the famous deter- 
ministic principle of Laplace, that from the position and momentum 
of every particle at a given instant could be calculated everything that 
would ever happen afterwards. 

Such a metaphysical conception of matter and motion produced an 
equally metaphysical conception of the relation of matter and mind. 
Feeling, perceiving and thinking were regarded as nothing but sub- 
jective accompaniments of certain mechanical interactions. Thus, for 
example, the impingement of light on the retina causes a displacement 
of matter in the optic nerve, and this is “accompanied” by a “sensa- 
tion”. 

Such metaphysical materialist conceptions were, of course, a gift to 
idealists. George Berkeley argued very convincingly, in his Principles 
of Human Knowledge, that the conception of matter put forward by 
“the most accurate philosophers” of his day (by which he meant 
metaphysical materialists) was “abstract and incomprehensible”. 
It is not difficult to discredit metaphysical materialism, and then to 
claim that materialism is refuted. 

In explaining what “materialist dialectics” means, Engels pointed 
out how metaphysical abstractions — counterposing one thing or 
aspect to another, and not connecting them — lead logically to absurd 
and unanswerable questions. Thus in Chapters 5 and 6 of Anti-Duhring 
he showed what absurdities arise from the metaphysical separation of 
space, time, matter and motion. 

How could there be space and time without material events taking 
place in space and time? And what “matter” would be left if there 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


71 


were no such events? It is as absurd to talk of space and time separable 
from the relations of material things as it is to talk of anything existing 
outside of spatial-temporal relation, or (we may add) of space relations 
independent of time, or of temporal relations independent of space. 
“The basic forms of all being are space and time, ,, Engels tersely 
summed up. 

It is equally absurd to separate matter from motion. To do so is to 
talk as though “matter” were some sort of basic stuff or substance out 
of which things are made, and which is itself inert though things made 
of it will move if pushed. As against such absurdity Engels posed the 
principle: “Motion is the mode of existence of matter.” 

He then stressed the distinction and connection of different forms 
of motion of matter. There is not one single form of real motion 
(mechanical displacement), all other forms being mere appearances of 
it, but the investigation of the real motion of things involves connecting 
together the different forms of motion and studying transitions from 
one form into another. “Matter in motion” thus presents no simple 
picture of mechanical interactions. Simply to describe mechanical 
interactions, far from providing a complete picture of all that really 
takes place, is to abstract one single aspect — and then to present this 
abstraction as though it were the concrete reality. 

“Motion in cosmic space, mechanical motion of smaller masses, 
the motion of molecules as heat or as electrical or magnetic currents, 
chemical combination or disintegration, organic life — at each given 
moment each individual atom of matter in the world is in one or other 
of these forms of motion, or in.several forms of them at once”, Engels 
wrote. Under definite conditions one form of motion produces 
another, and that other does not then replace the first but the totality 
of motion of the material structures concerned contains them both. 
Thus mechanical motions generate heat, physical motions pass into 
chemical, chemical combinations produce living organisms, and so on. 
But when heat is generated mechanical motion continues, chemical 
systems continue to obey the laws of physics, and living organisms 
exemplify the workings of the laws of mechanics. A person, for 
instance, who is acting voluntarily and purposively, is not thereby 
emancipated from the laws of mechanics, any more than his body 
ceases to be a physical structure and the processes in his tissues chemical 
processes. All the same, it is not true to say that a person’s life is really 
nothing but a set of mechanical, or of physical or chemical, interactions. 

Non-motion or “rest”, Engels went on, “only has meaning relative 


72 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


to one or other definite form of motion”. Absolute rest, or motionless- 
ness, is nonsense. So it is nonsense to suggest that matter may be either 
at rest or in motion, and only moves in response to an “initial impulse”. 
One can no more separate matter from motion than from space and 
time. A body may be motionless in one or other respect, but it cannot 
possibly be motionless in all respects. Thus a body at rest relative to 
the earth is* in motion relative to the sun; the internal motion of heat 
continues inside it; and so on. 

In Chapter i of Anti-Duhring Engels explained in simple terms how 
the fallacy of metaphysical abstraction arises in the development of 
the natural sciences, and how the principles of materialist dialectics 
are necessary principles of the scientific way of thinking. And he 
repeated it all in Chapter 4 of Ludwig Feuerbach . It is indeed a pity that 
the ratde of the teacups prevented Dr. Popper from hearing these 
explanations. 

In order to understand connections one has first to make distinctions. 
There is nothing wrong with “examining things separately”: on 
the contrary, it is right to do so. Where metaphysics goes wrong is in 
sticking at the corresponding conceptions of distinctions and anti- 
theses, and failing to go on to study the connections. 

For an adequate conception of things, Engels wrote in Anti-Duhring , 
we must study things in detail. And “in order to understand these 
details, we must detach them from their natural and historical connec- 
tions, and examine each one separately. ...” So, he wrote in Ludwig 
Feuerbach , “it was necessary first to examine things before it was 
possible to examine processes. One had first to know what a particular 
thing was before one could observe the changes going on in connection 
with it.” Science has to start with analysis, description and classifica- 
tion. But “when investigation had progressed so far, it became possible 
to take the decisive step forward of transition to the systematic in- 
vestigation of the changes which things undergo”; and so science in its 
later development has become “a science of processes, of the origin 
and development of things and of the interconnections which bind all 
processes into one great whole”. Materialist dialectics is thus nothing 
but a generalisation of principles embodied in all scientific thinking, 
when it has advanced beyond the more primitive stage of analysis. 

Once the point is made, it is very obvious indeed that no concrete 
or complete account of what is the case and what takes place can be 
content to consider each thing or aspect of things “in isolation” or 
metaphysical abstraction. It must take “the interconnections” into 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


73 


account. And when that is done, the kind of “antitheses” and mutual 
exclusion of “opposites” which come from undialectical thinking, 
together with the resulting puzzles and absurdities, vanish. Dialectical 
materialism makes this very obvious and very commonsensical 
point. 


3. THE CONCRETE ANALYSIS OF CONCRETE CONDITIONS 

“The world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made 
things, but as a complex of processes,” wrote Engels in Chapter 4 of 
Ludwig Feuerbach . 

“This great fundamental thought,” he continued, “is in its generality 
scarcely ever contradicted. But to acknowledge this fundamental 
thought in words and to apply it in detail to each domain of investiga- 
tion are two different things.” The general principles of dialectics — 
those “laws” which have been so often questioned, ridiculed and dis- 
missed ever since Hegel first talked about them — are simply generalised 
guiding principles for this application. 

And as Engels further said, “if investigation proceeds from this 
standpoint, the demand for final solutions and eternal truths ceases 
once for all ; one is always conscious of the necessary limitation of all 
acquired knowledge, of the fact that it is conditioned by the circum- 
stances in which it was acquired”. The standpoint of materialist 
dialectics is thus one of continuous inquiry, opposed to all dogmatism 
— even though, according to Dr. Popper, the rules or dialectical laws 
of such inquiry constitute “a reinforced dogmatism”. 

To describe the world as “a complex of processes” is not, of course, 
to deny that there are “things”. Engels made this perfectly clear when 
he wrote further that, in the processes of the world, “things apparently 
stable, no less than their mind-images in our heads, the concepts, go 
through an uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing 
away”. The point is that “things” are not “ready-made”, but are 
formed, transformed and dissolved in processes; and their properties, 
and their relations, are not fixed attachments of theirs, but come to be 
and cease to be exhibited by them in the course of the processes through 
which they go. If, for example, a stone has the property of being hard, 
and the relation of being harder than a heap of sand, that is because 
stones get formed out of certain processes — and if one takes this into 
account, it becomes evident that no stone is likely to remain hard for 
ever, but will grow crumbly and eventually crumble right away. 


74 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


Stones are harder than heaps of sand, but sand may get formed out of 
crumbled stones, and can also itself get turned into sandstone. 

To speak in terms of “complexes of things” is not always wrong. 
On the contrary, it is for many purposes the proper way of speaking. 
The point is that it is not the only proper way of speaking, but just 
one particular way. As I pointed out earlier, whatever we think, 
whatever we say, is always based on abstraction . To think and speak of 
“a complex of, things” exemplifies one particular mode of abstraction. 
This mode of abstraction is properly adopted for certain specific 
practical purposes. For other purposes it will not do. And it certainly 
will not do for the purpose of working out as complete and concrete 
an account as possible of what actually goes on in the world. 

Let me take a very fragrant example, the scene of which is a com- 
mercial rose garden. Someone comes along to buy a dozen roses. 
In supplying this demand the rosegrower thinks only in terms of 
“ready-made things”: he views his rosebeds simply as containing so 
many roses, some of this colour and some of that colour. In making 
up his accounts in the evening he continues to think in this same way: 
so many roses at so much per rose, so many labourers working so 
many hours at so much per hour, and so on. Nethertheless in seeing 
to everything that has to be seen to in his business he cannot always 
think in such an abstract way. He has to grow the roses, and in doing 
so does not think of them as “ready-made things” at all. His rose 
garden is no longer seen as “a complex of things”, but as “a complex 
of processes in which things apparently stable go through an un- 
interrupted change of coming into being and passing away”. So long 
as his only interest in roses was as commodities to be bought and sold, 
the “complex of things” mode of abstraction provided the proper 
way of thinking of them; it had to be supplemented by other kinds of 
concept as soon as his interest was widened to include also the concrete 
conditions under which roses are actually grown. 

If from this humble rosegrower we turn to the philosopher, Lord 
Russell, we can see that his observation that “a catalogue of things” 
with “a mention of all their qualities and relations” would constitute 
“a complete description of the world”, which I quoted as a typical 
example of a “metaphysical” statement, provides also an example of 
how deeply the commercial spirit has penetrated the thinking even of 
the British aristocracy. This whole type of metaphysics would, indeed, 
hardly have arisen had it not been for the development of commodity 
production and the separation of mental from manual labour. 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


75 


When from viewing the world as “a complex of things” one 
proceeds to view it rather as “a complex of processes”, in which things 
come into being and pass away in ever-changing interconnection, this 
procedure may be described as the passage from a more to a less 
abstract way of viewing things, or from a more abstract to a more 
concrete way of thinking. I cannot go here into the exact definition of 
“abstract” and “concrete”, as technical terms of logic; it suffices to 
point out that a statement, B, is more concrete and less abstract than a 
statement, A, when everything A says is included in what is said by B, 
but not everything B says is included in what is said by A. 

The “complex of processes” view is evidently more concrete com- 
pared with the more abstract “complex of things” view, for it includes 
whatever was included in the latter, and more besides. We do not 
think of processes as an alternative to thinking of things, but to think 
of processes is to think of things in a much less abstract way — in a way that 
more adequately reflects the actual concrete conditions of existence of 
things, the real interconnections. Thus whatever received reflection in 
the “complex of things” view is still reflected in the “complex of 
processes” view. When our rosegrower thinks of rosebeds in terms of 
the processes actually taking place there, he does not lose sight of the 
separate roses, or of their individual colours. Rather he sees them now 
(to quote Hegel) “in their own being and movement”, instead of 
thinking of them in a more abstract way, in relative isolation from 
their actual conditions of existence. 

Lenin, as I remarked earlier, wrote that dialectics was concerned with 
“the concrete analysis of concrete conditions”. Dialectics enters into 
thinking , and the principles of dialectics apply , whenever we require to make 
our thinking more concrete . The dialectic of thinking does not consist 
in some artificially contrived performance of passing from “thesis and 
antithesis” to “synthesis” (wheoever but a charlatan or a pedant would 
undertake that?), but in passing from more abstract to more concrete 
concepts. Similarly, the dialectic discovered in the objective world consists 
of those forms of interconnection within real processes which the concrete 
analysis of concrete conditions reveals , and which are ignored in more abstract 
metaphysical ways of thinking. 

The concrete analysis of concrete conditions demands the study of 
the forms of interconnection within the processes of the world, and it 
shows things as interdependent, changing, coming into being and 
passing away — and, moreover, as turning into their opposites, ex- 
hibiting contradictory aspects in different relationships and entering 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


7 6 

into contradictory relationships in which they suffer stresses and strains, 
conflicts and transformations. 

Thus Marx wrote, in the Afterword to the second German edition 
of Capital , in connection with the analysis he had made of the concrete 
conditions of capitalist society, that dialectics “in its rational form is a 
scandal and abomination to bourgeoisdom and its doctrinaire profes- 
sors, because it includes in its comprehension and affirmative recog- 
nition of the existing state of things at the same time also the recog- 
nition of the negation of that state, of its inevitable breaking up, 
because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid 
movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature no 
less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing impose upon 
it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.” 

Of course, Dr. Popper does not like that. He represents dialectics, 
instead, as being doctrinaire nonsense. This he does by making out that 
dialectics is opposed to formal logic. But it is not opposed to logic , 
it is opposed to metaphysics . 

The laws of logic are the laws of consistency. To advocate ignoring or 
breaking them is to advocate inconsistency. So of course, if that were 
what dialectics advocated, dialectics would be, as Dr. Popper says, 
nonsense. But, as we saw earlier, materialist dialectics advocates nothing 
of the kind. Its concern is with a consistent account of how things are really 
connected. It would be merely moronic to suggest that “the concrete 
analysis of concrete conditions’' could be correct only if inconsistent. 
When Marx insisted on not only recognising “the existing state of 
things” but also “the negation of that state”, he advocated no violation 
of the laws of logic. On the contrary, from the concrete analysis of 
the existing state of things the negation of that state follows logically. 
Marx was in fact very logical indeed. The scandal he caused “to 
bourgeoisdom” was due to his drawing the logical conclusions from 
a concrete analysis. 

The laws of formal logic are of absolute validity, and any form of 
statement which sets them aside becomes thereby incoherent and 
inconsistent. The dialectical approach, therefore, certainly includes 
no suggestion that they may be broken with impunity for the purpose 
of a concrete analysis which treats of the real forms of interconnection 
of things — as though a statement of how things are connected could 
somehow break away from the norms of formal logic. Of course, if 
you ignore the ways things are connected — if you ignore, say, those 
connections of things which lead to an existing state of affairs generating 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


77 


its own “negation” — you will reach wrong conclusions. That un- 
fortunate result will not then be due to your respect for formal logic, 
but to your disrespect for real connections. If you lack respect for 
formal logic you can reach no conclusions at all. 

What the dialectical approach does suggest and, indeed, insist on is 
something quite different. Practical thinking (that is, thinking to inform 
our practice) must always be logically consistent, but the laws of 
logical consistency cannot by themselves provide sufficient principles 
for its guidance. Formal consistency is not enough; though necessary 
it is not sufficient. In other words, simply to say (as Dr. Popper says) 
that the task of scientific thinking is to formulate generalisations con- 
sistent with observation, and then try to falsify them and, if they are 
falsified, reformulate them so as to be consistent also with the new 
observations, does not suffice. That must, of course, be done; but not 
only that. 

Generalisations about a given topic may be perfectly consistent — 
consistent with observations, and falsifiable by observations — so that 
by formal criteria there is nothing wrong with them; but even though 
the thinking which employs only such criteria obeys the logical laws 
of consistency with scrupulous care, and earns high rating from Dr. 
Popper as science on account of its falsifiability, it is still hopelessly 
inadequate for all but the most limited purposes of informing practice, 
because it is still so “one-sided, limited and abstract”. In order the 
better to inform our practice we must formulate generalisations which 
are not only consistent with observation, and falsifiable, but contribute 
to the concrete analysis of the conditions observed. 

Plenty of examples can be found of one-sided abstract generalisa- 
tions, which illustrate also their obvious limitations. Such generalisa- 
tions abound nowadays especially on social topics. Take, for example, 
generalisations about the workings of the capitalist economy — which 
are intended not only as descriptions of how things go, but also as 
practical guidance for the direction of economic affairs, or for taking 
advantage of economic circumstances for purposes of profit. What was 
formerly called “the dismal science” of economics formulates such 
generalisations, correlating all manner of observational variables in 
the most scientifically complicated fashion, basing it all on statistical 
inquiries, and correcting the generalisations whenever (as frequently 
happens) they are falsified. These generalisations satisfy the formal 
criteria of being based on systematic observations, being consistent 
with the observations, and being falsifiable by other observations. 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


78 

They tell us that when wages go up in excess of productivity such and 
such results tend to happen — and so on, and so on. Today in Britain 
such information is useful for persons trying to vet wage claims on 
behalf of the Prices and Incomes Board, or in the U.S.A. to establish 
Federal guide-lines on wages. But for the purposes of trying to find 
out how to organise human society to satisfy human needs, they are 
inadequate. For they just take the existing economic relations for 
granted, and describe how they work, without showing how they 
arose, develop and may be changed. 

I11 the Afterword to the second German edition of Capital Marx 
quoted what he called a “striking and generous” account of his 
method of investigating economic processes written by a reviewer in 
the European Messenger of St. Petersburg. Marx investigated economic 
phenomena, said this reviewer, not only “in so far as they have a 
definite form and mutual connection within a given historical period. 
Of still greater moment to him is the law of their variation, of their 
development, i.e. of their transition from one form into another, from 
one series of connections into a different one. This law once discovered, 
he investigates in detail the effects in which it manifests itself in social 
life.” “What else is he picturing”, Marx commented, “but the dialec- 
tical method?” This method enjoins the concrete analysis of concrete 
conditions, and studies things in their real interconnections, in the 
processes in which they come into being and change, instead of being 
content with merely noting certain phenomena in abstraction from 
the processes in which they actually come into being. 

The concrete analysis of concrete conditions has to be not only 
formally consistent, derived from observations and falsifiable by 
observations, but consonant with the principles of dialectics. It must 
comprehend the world “not as a complex of ready-made things but 
as a complex of processes”; it must not “in considering individual 
things lose sight of their connections”, or “in contemplating their 
existence forget their coming into being and passing away”; it must 
not “be imposed upon by the antitheses insuperable for the old meta- 
physics”, and must not simply note “the two poles of an antithesis” 
but also their inseparable connection ; it must not in noting qualitative 
changes overlook their quantitative basis, nor in measuring quanti- 
tative changes ignore their qualitative consequences; it must not in 
dealing with one aspect of a relationship deny a contradictory aspect; 
it must, in short, always “study things in their own being and move- 
ment”. 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


79 


As I have pointed out, the one-sided abstract type of generalisation 
is perfectly adequate for certain limited purposes. For example, if you 
are a tradesman interested in things solely as commodities, it is adequate 
for your purposes to ignore the processes in which things come into 
being and cease to be. But for other purposes this will not do. 

It is a striking characteristic of the modern development of the 
sciences, that the natural sciences, which are required to serve pro- 
duction, have had to give up the more limited kind of generalisation 
and investigate the dialectic of nature. For example, the biological 
sciences began by simply distinguishing the different characteristics 
of living species and noting how one characteristic is generally correlated 
with another — how horns and hoofs always go with a vegetarian diet, 
the frequencies with which the characteristics of parents are reproduced 
in their offspring, and so on. But they passed from this type of investi- 
gation to investigating how species evolve in interaction with en- 
vironments, how living organisms are built of cells and their life 
consists of the disintegration and renewal of cells, and how the pro- 
cesses of heredity work. In this, said Engels, in the Preface to Anti- 
Duhring, “there could be no question of building the laws of dialectics 
into nature, but of discovering them in it and evolving them from it” ; 
and in Chapter i : “Nature is the test of dialectics, and it must be said 
for modern natural science that it has furnished extremely rich and 
daily increasing materials for this test, and has thus proved that in the 
last analysis nature’s process is dialectical and not metaphysical/ * 

The revolution which Marxism introduced into the social sciences was 
the same as that which took place in the natural sciences — the passage from 
abstract limited generalisation to dialectics , the concrete analysis of concrete 
conditions . But Marxism is not officially recognised by the capitalist 
scientific establishment. And so in the officially recognised social 
sciences the more limited type of generalisation has remained pre- 
dominant. The practical reason for this contrast is not hard to guess. 
The Marxist analysis reveals the capitalist system in a light in which 
the successful bourgeoisie is not willing to see it, whereas more limited 
and abstract generalisations about costs, prices, wages, productivity, 
investment, and so on, provide them with sufficient information about 
its workings for their own profit-making purposes. 

Thus the same methodology which has paid off in the natural sciences is 
officially considered quite uncalled for in the social sciences. Theories, like 
those of Dr. Popper, which formulate “criteria” for science simply and 
solely in terms of consistency and falsifiability, make out that limited 


8o 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


and abstract generalisations are fully scientific. It then requires only a 
little ingenuity (or shall I say sophistry?) to talk about “reinforced 
dogmatism” and to make out that anything less limited and abstract 
is unscientific. Such limited criteria fulfil an extra-scientific function — 
they duly uphold the prejudices of the establishment. 

In writing about Adam Smith, in Theories of Surplus Value , Marx 
remarked that Smith adopted two distinct lines of inquiry, which he 
never connected together. On the one hand, he “traces the inner 
comiection between the economic categories — or the hidden structure 
of the bourgeois economic system”. On the other hand, he was content 
with “only describing . . . the external phenomena”. But this second 
line of inquiry was enough to satisfy “the man who is preoccupied and 
interested from a practical point of view in the process of bourgeois 
production”. 

The subsequent “vulgar” bourgeois economists developed only the 
second line of inquiry. Marx himself, following Ricardo, developed 
the first. And doing so, he also connected “the hidden structure” with 
“the external phenomena”. Writing to Engels (April 30, 1868), he 
claimed that, at the conclusion of his analysis, “we have arrived at the 
forms of appearance which serve as the starting point in the vulgar 
conception. ... But from our point of view the thing is now seen 
differently. The apparent movement is explained.” 

The same sort of development of two lines of inquiry can be seen 
in political theory. Political philosophers like Hobbes and, later, Hegel 
worked out “a theory of the state”. Others (and one source of their 
inspiration will be found in the political essays of David Hume) 
considered such theories purely speculative and contented themselves 
with “only describing the external phenomena”. This, to do them 
justice, they did with accuracy and care. They analysed, classified and 
minutely described different forms of state institution and different 
departments of state function. But the Marxist theory of the state again 
followed the first line of inquiry, theorising about “the inner comiec- 
tion”. Briefly, it connects the development of states, and of state insti- 
tutions and state functions, with the development of class divisions 
and class struggles. 

According to Hegel, the state is “the realisation of the Moral Idea 
on ear tli”. This is an idealist theory, employing false abstraction, 
incapable of empirical verification or falsification. So it has been very 
properly rejected by those who consider it better only to describe what 
states actually look like. The Marxist theory of the state, on the other 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


8l 


hand, is a scientific and materialist theory, subject to the test of whether 
historical events confirm it or otherwise. For it investigates and verifies 
“the inner connection” in such a way that “the apparent movement is 
explained”. 

Many studies by non-Marxist political scientists in Britain and the 
U.S.A. are content today with no more than describing British and 
U.S. state institutions, for example, and how they work — adding 
eulogies in their praise together with some suggestions for their 
improvement. Marxist analysis takes all the facts into account, and 
duly displays them, but then explains how the state institutions are 
the means by which the social dominance of monopoly capital is 
maintained. That is a fact too. But when this “inner connection” is 
traced, as Marx said, “the diing is seen differently”. The eulogies begin 
to sound a little hollow, the suggestions for improvement become 
rather more sweeping. 

In general, if you accept existing economic relations and the 
existing political power structure as unchangeable, then abstract and 
limited generalisations about economic phenomena and state institu- 
tions are all that you practically require, and you will have no use for 
dialectics. If, on the other hand, you are practically interested in 
changing economic relations and the political power structure, you 
are compelled to replace such abstract generalisations by a more 
concrete analysis of the concrete conditions in which you live. You 
have resort to dialectics. 

4. THE DIALECTICAL MATERIALIST THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 

The passage from more abstract to more concrete concepts, or concrete 
analysis of concrete conditions (in which materialist dialectics consists, 
and the principles governing which are the principles or laws of dia- 
lectics) is, viewed from the point of view of the development of human 
knowledge, a passage from knowing only “the forms of appearance” 
to the discovery of “inner connection” and “hidden structure”. It is 
also a passage from knowledge useful only from the limited point of 
view of managing things as they are, to knowledge of how to change 
things. 

And so Lenin, in his encyclopaedia article on Karl Marx , observed 
that “dialectics, as understood by Marx, includes the theory of know- 
ledge, studying and generalising the origin and development of 
knowledge, the transition from non-knowledge to knowledge.” 


82 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


In considering questions about knowledge, and how to obtain and 
develop it, it is very important indeed to make clear that “to know” 
is not the same as to be “absolutely sure”. This can be put, initially, 
as a rather obvious point about the normal use of words. If “knowing” 
were synonymous with “being absolutely sure”, it would follow that 
we “know” hardly anything at all. I would then “know” that two 
plus two equals four, and that I myself exist, but not much else. This, 
however, is not what we generally mean by ‘‘know”. For what we 
generally mean by “knowing” is something capable of development , 
whereas “being absolutely sure” is not capable of development. One 
is either possessed of absolute surety or else one is not. There is no 
development of it from being “less absolutely” sure to “more ab- 
solutely” sure. Hence what we generally mean by “knowing”, and 
what it is interesting and important to study, is (as Lenin said) the 
process of knowing, “the transition from non-knowledge to know- 
ledge” — from not knowing at all to knowing a bit, and then to 
knowing better. What counts as “knowing” in this process is certainly 
not identifiable with “being absolutely sure”, and only very excep- 
tionally ends in surety. 

What we call “knowledge” must also be distinguished from “true 
belief”. If, for example, there is life on Mars, the belief that there is 
life on Mars is true belief. But at the same time we certainly, as yet, 
know nothing of the matter. True belief only becomes knowledge 
when backed by some kind of investigation and evidence. Some of our 
beliefs may be true and others false, but we only start getting to know 
which are true and which are false when we undertake forms of syste- 
matic investigation. 

In investigating and gathering evidence we are devising tests of the 
truth or falsity of beliefs or ideas, or of how far they are true. For 
nothing can count as “knowledge” except in so far as it has been 
properly tested. An essential part of the business of knowing is, there- 
fore, the devising of appropriate methods of investigation and test. 

What comes of the process of knowing would, then, be better 
described by such a phrase as “getting to know” than by unqualified 
“knowing” — for it seldom if ever reaches finality about anything, and 
contains few if any guarantees against error. The sort of tests we can 
devise are not final tests. To say we have got to know about something 
is not to say that our ideas about it have been finally certified as either 
true or complete, for the methods of investigation and test generally 
preclude such finality. 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 83 

A great many philosophers, however, have supposed that we could 
not get to know about anything at all unless there were something we 
were sure about to start with. They have been unable to see how we 
can get to know without ever being sure. They have supposed, on the 
contrary, that whatever we know must be somehow or other based on, 
or deducible from, something we are sure about. We must begin by 
finding something we can be sure about — only so can knowledge 
develop. 

As a result, there have been two sorts of theory of knowledge, 
both of which are wrong. On the one hand, philosophers have posited 
“first principles”, or indubitable “data”, which they claim to be sure 
about, and have then deduced all sorts of queer consequences from 
these and declared: “This is what we really know, the world must 
really be like this!” On the other hand, other philosophers have 
stressed human fallibility, and because they can find little they can be 
sure about have concluded that we “really know” hardly anything at 
all. 

A grand source of error in the theory of knowledge has thus been 
the covert idea that knowledge must always begin from something we 
are sure about; and that to .discover, therefore, whether we do or do 
not know something we think we know, it is necessary to find whether 
or not our belief in it is based on some form of certainty. But on the 
contrary, as Lenin said (setting forth the ideas of Marx about materialist 
dialectics), knowing, or getting to know, is a process in which there 
occurs “the transition from non-knowledge to knowledge”. The 
process of knowing does not consist in the transition from being sure 
about one thing to drawing conclusions about another thing, but from 
not knowing about something, or being totally ignorant of it, to 
getting to know something about it. 

Knowledge and ignorance are opposites. There are some things we 
do know something about, and other things we do not know anything 
about. And the process of getting to know is the transition from not 
knowing to knowing, and not simply from knowing something to 
knowing something else. It illustrates, therefore, the general dialectical 
principle of “the unity of opposites”. But in the theory of knowledge 
nearly all philosophers have failed to appreciate this dialectic, and un- 
wittingly adopted the metaphysical procedure of posing “rigid anti- 
theses” and “sharp impassible dividing hues”. They have opposed 
“not knowing” to “knowing”, and supposed that knowing cannot 
come from not knowing, but that, on the contrary, whatever we get 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


84 

to know must be derived, somehow or other, from something we 
knew initially. 

The route from not knowing to knowing is found in human practice . 
And if philosophers have not been able to discern. this route, that is 
because they have failed to notice the role of practice in the process of 
knowing. “In practice man must prove the truth, i.e. the reality and 
power, the ‘this-sidedness’ of his thinking’ ”, wrote Marx in the Theses 
on Feuerbach . Ideas that are formed for the information of practice, 
and then developed through investigation and tested in social practice, 
are the stuff of knowledge. Men pass from not knowing to knowing 
in their practical activity of developing their relations with one another 
and the external world, investigating the facts and the possibilities, 
and testing their conclusions. And in doing this they not only extend 
the scope of their knowledge, but also pass from one level of knowledge 
to another — from knowledge of particular properties of particular 
things, and relatively abstract generalisations about them, to the 
concrete analysis of concrete conditions. 

Dr. Popper is, of course, quite right in stressing the necessity of 
applying tests in the development of scientific knowledge, and in 
stressing that none of these tests is ever fmal and that scientific theories 
are therefore always provisional. But in concluding from this that all 
scientific theories are alike “conjectures” awaiting “refutations” 
he is either concluding something which does not follow, or else 
using words in a very misleading way to mean something else than 
what those words would generally be taken to mean. To know is not 
to “conjecture”, but neither is it to be “sure”. Scientific knowledge is 
not conjecture, any more than it is final and complete certainty. The 
process of investigating the world and testing theories (which Dr. 
Popper lumps all together as alike “conjectures”) is the process of 
getting to know — of passing from not knowing to knowing, and 
from not knowing well to knowing better. 

In opposition to Dr. Popper’s simplifications, and in opposition too 
to standard approaches to the theory of knowledge which Dr. Popper 
himself opposes, we may now try to sum up the dialectical materialist 
theory of knowledge in five cardinal points. 

First, knowledge stems from experience, from the practical inter- 
actions of human individuals with their environments, in which people 
form judgements about objects and about themselves, and test and 
reformulate their judgements in the course of human practice. It is in 
thus connecting ourselves, in human practice, with things and with 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


85 

one another, that we pass from ignorance to knowledge, from know- 
ledge to more knowledge, and from imperfect to more perfect 
knowledge. The extent of our knowledge is always commensurate 
with the variety and complexity of our real connections. 

The more we do the more we can know, and the more we know the 
more we can do. For example, we have found out about how chemical 
changes are produced by the combination and recombination of atoms 
in molecules, by elaborate experiments, with close observation and 
much counting and measuring, and by finding how to produce 
controlled changes for ourselves. 

Second, while it is individuals who know, knowledge is only 
possible in society, through the communication and co-operation of 
individuals. A solitary manlike animal, cut off from human com- 
munication and lacking language, might perceive, feel and learn from 
experience — like other animals — but would lack human knowledge. 
The knowledge acquired in human social activity is all acquired by 
human individuals — and yet its sum exceeds that possessed by any 
individual, and no individual could acquire knowledge if deprived of 
all social relations with other individuals. The traditional empiricist 
approach to the theory of knowledge, therefore, which asks what 
conclusions the abstract individual could draw from his own private 
experience, asks the wrong question, since the abstract individual 
not only does not exist but could draw no conclusions even if he 
did. 

Thus even the most elementary human knowledge differs in kind 
from the learning from experience of which other animals are capable. 
It differs because human individuals communicate what they observe 
and learn, by means of human language. To acquire even the most 
elementary store of human knowledge you have to learn to speak, and 
none of it could exist unless human individuals communicated. We 
find things out and test our conclusions together, in communication, 
and not each one separately. 

Third, knowledge passes from affirmation to negation and back to 
affirmation, from the particular to the general and back to the parti- 
cular, and from the abstract to the concrete and back to the abstract. 

Thus in confirming that a tiling has a certain property we pass to 
the conclusion that it has not got some other property. This makes the 
affirmation more definite. But in then testing it in relation to the 
negative conclusion we are able both to correct and amplify the 
original theory. This comprises the scientific procedure of “falsifi- 


86 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


cation” which Dr. Popper correctly thinks so essential in the develop- 
ment of knowing. 

For example, if a certain substance is a gas it follows that it is not a 
liquid. But if the proposition that it is not a liquid is thoroughly tested, 
it will be found that in certain conditions it becomes a liquid. Hence 
the original statement that it is a gas is corrected, and replaced by the 
amplified statement that it is a gas under certain normal conditions of 
temperature and pressure. 

Further, in finding out something about each of some set of parti- 
cular things or events we pass to generalised conclusions about things 
or events of that kind, test these conclusions, and then apply them back 
again to the particular cases — so that our knowledge of the latter 
becomes more generalised, and what we have to say about them is 
more than we could originally discover by examining each separately. 

For example, it was discovered that whenever burning takes place 
there is oxidisation. From this the generalised conclusion was reached 
that burning is a chemical process in which oxygen is consumed. 
As a consequence, to say that something is burning is made to say 
more than simply that certain recognisable effects are being produced — 
it says that a definite kind of process is taking place, which could not 
take place except in an environment containing oxygen. 

And further, we begin with abstractions. To get to know about 
things we must first examine them separately, and consider certain 
of their properties and certain of their relations in abstraction or 
detachment from the totality of the interconnections of things in the 
processes that actually go on in the world. From the relatively abstract 
conclusions thus established we go on to investigate the intercon- 
nections, to attempt the concrete analysis of concrete conditions. For 
this purpose we form theories about the processes in which particular 
things come into being. We ask how it is that things come to exhibit 
given properties and to enter into given relationships, and how it is 
that they come to change their properties and relationships, and to 
cease to be and give place to other tilings. We undertake new investi- 
gations in order to arrive at such theories, and test them in renewed 
investigation. Finally, we then reformulate our conclusions about 
separate things and separate relationships in the light of our more 
concrete analysis of the conditions of their existence. And in doing 
that we at one and the same time correct the abstract ideas we started 
with and further test and, if need be, revise our theories. 

For example, to find out how Britain is governed we must first 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


87 

examine the actual institutions — how they are constituted, and what 
the persons who administer them do. We must establish such facts as 
that there is a monarch, and discover what the Queen actually does. 
From this we may pass to a more concrete analysis and formulate (as 
was mentioned earlier) the theory that existing institutions of govern- 
ment are adapted to the function of preserving the dominance of 
monopoly capital. After that we shall have something more to say 
about the Queen than was comprised in the original observation of her 
behaviour — we shall have more to say than that she attends race 
meetings, confers honours, has a guaranteed income, and signs Bills. 

Fourth, because knowing consists in the passage from not knowing 
to knowing, knowledge is always limited, partial, relative and subject 
to correction. 

It is limited by the limits of the connections from which it springs. 
What is known is incomplete even in relation to its immediate object. 
Knowledge is limited by the conditions under which it was established, 
and is not only Fable to be added to, but to be corrected when more is 
known. 

Thus one should never say, without qualification, “This textbook 
summarises knowledge of the subject”, but rather, “It summarises 
knowledge so far as it has been won by using certain techniques in 
certain circumstances”. Consequently most scientific textbooks have 
to be periodically revised, and old ones replaced by new, not because 
their authors made mistakes but because knowledge has itself changed. 

At the same time, knowledge is limitless in the sense that, whatever 
the limits resulting from the particular conditions in which we passed 
from not knowing to knowing, the discovery of new techniques and 
establishment of new connections may overcome them. Limits there 
always are, but no limit is finally known to be the final limit. The 
known is bounded by the unknown, but not by the unknowable. 

Lastly, we can pass from knowing more and more about the pro- 
cesses which go on in the world, including our own individual and 
social life, to formulating the general principles or laws which have to 
be applied in and are exemplified by all knowledge, or genuine in- 
formation. 

This is the passage from the discovery of matter of fact , all statement of 
which is falsifiable, to the demonstration of the necessary , the correct 
statement of which, because it is necessary, cannot possibly be falsified. 
The principles of logic, which govern consistency of statement; 
the theories of mathematics, which are used for counting and mea- 


88 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


suring; and the principles of materialism and dialectics, which rule 
out fantasy and govern the concrete analysis of concrete conditions — 
are of this order. 

All the processes we know are of the material world, they conform 
to logic, they exhibit number and measure, and they exemplify those 
forms of interconnection which we sum up as “dialectics”. That this 
is so, we learn from getting to know about processes. That it must be 
so, is to be demonstrated by the tests applied in the development of 
logical, mathematical and dialectical materialist theory. In the develop- 
ment of such theory we are at one and the same time working out rules 
and criteria for the management of practical information, and testing 
the correctness and adequacy with which such rules and criteria are 
formulated. 


5. REINFORCED DOGMATISM REINFORCED 

Dr. Popper, as we have seen, regards dialectical materialism, or the 
materialist dialectic, as the fountain-head of the “reinforced dog- 
matism” of which he holds Marxism guilty. 

“Hegelian dialectic, or its materialistic version, cannot be accepted 
as a sound basis for scientific forecasts”, he writes (CR. 333). “Thus 
if forecasts based on dialectic are made, some will come true and some 
will not. In the latter case, obviously, a situation will arise which has 
not been foreseen. But dialectic is vague and elastic enough to interpret 
and to explain this unforeseen situation just as well as it interpreted 
and explained the situation which it predicted and which happened 
not to come true. Any development whatever will fit the dialectic 
scheme; the dialectician need never be afraid of any refutation by 
future experience.” 

There seems to be some little confusion in Dr. Popper’s remarks as 
to whether they mean that the principles of materialist dialectics are 
valueless because they are themselves unfalsifiable, or that what is wrong 
with them is that their application leads to unfalsifiable pseudo-theories 
— theories so “vague and elastic” that “any development whatever 
will fit”. 

We have seen already that the second charge is certainly not true. 
Undoubtedly, as Dr. Popper says, some of the forecasts which Marx 
made when applying materialist dialectic in the study of social deve- 
lopment have not come true, and yet Marx’s social theory has proved 
“vague and elastic enough to interpret and explain” the failure of 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


89 

predictions in all those cases where such failure has occurred. But in 
that, Marx’s theory is exactly like any other fundamental scientific 
theory. The sort of “dialectic scheme” (or rather, scientific analysis) 
which Marx worked out in Capital is testable, falsifiable and subject to 
correction and further working out in exactly the same way as any 
other scientific theory. 

Does Dr. Popper mean simply that general principles of materialist 
dialectics, as the principles of an approach or method, have been so 
formulated as to be unfalsifiable? But if that is what he means, he is 
mistaken in suggesting that these general principles themselves imply 
“forecasts”. If, as he says, “any development whatever” will fit them, 
then clearly no forecast is implied. In fact these general principles 
make no forecasts at all — and that is why no falsification of forecasts 
falsifies them. 

Certainly, such a principle as the materialist one, that “the material 
world is to be explained from the material world itself”, is unfalsifiable, 
and “any development whatever will fit”. A particular materialist 
explanation of some phenomenon may be falsified, but that does not 
falsify the materialist contention that the correct explanation must be 
sought along materialist lines. Such a principle as this makes no 
“forecast” at all about particular events. It does not compete in the 
forecast stakes in the way the theories of the special sciences do, so 
naturally the sort of tests which are applicable to theories which do 
make forecasts are not applicable to such a purely methodological 
generalisation. 

It is the same with principles of dialectics. They make no forecasts. 
For example, to say that things come to be and cease to be in processes 
makes no forecast about when or how any particular thing will come 
to be or cease to be. .Someone who accepts this dialectical principle 
may make a whole series of totally false forecasts — that will not falsify 
the dialectical principle. Similarly with such a dialectical principle as 
that which says that qualitative changes are based on quantitative 
changes, and that at a certain point quantitative change results in 
qualitative change. This makes no forecast about any particular change. 
All such forecasts might prove false, but that would not falsify the 
general principle. 

Materialism does indeed constitute “a sound basis for scientific 
forecasts”, because theories not based on materialism operate with false 
abstractions. And materialist dialectics constitutes “a sound basis” 
because theories not employing it remain abstract and one-sided. But 


90 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


principles of materialism and materialist dialectics are obviously not 
“a basis” for.forecasts in the same sense as scientific laws are a basis for 
forecasts. For example, the law of gravity is a basis for forecasts about 
what will happen to bodies in motion. At the same time, it is itself an 
exemplification of the materialist principle of explaining what happens 
in the material world from the material world itself, and in that sense 
its forecasts are “based on” applying the general principle of materialist 
explanation. But materialism itself, as a general principle, makes no 
forecast. The current formulation of the law of gravity might turn 
out to be mistaken, but that would not prove that materialism was 
mistaken. Similarly, laws of chemistry are a basis for forecasting 
chemical changes, and are themselves exemplifications of the dialectical 
principle of the connection of qualitative with quantitative change. 
They make forecasts “based on” applying that principle. But the 
dialectical principle itself makes no forecast. Particular chemical 
theories might turn out to be mistaken, but that would not prove that 
materialist dialectics was mistaken. 

Dr. Popper has made great play with the words “basis” and “based 
on” for the confounding of materialist dialectics. But the basis for 
using such words should consist in being more careful in their use than 
Dr. Popper seems to be. The claim that general principles of material- 
ism and dialectics must be “accepted as a sound basis for scientific 
forecasts” does not mean that those principles themselves make 
forecasts, so as to be tested, as scientific laws are, by whether or not 
the forecasts they make come true. What it means is that to make 
scientific forecasts we must study to comprehend the facts “in their 
own and not in a fantastic connection”, and investigate the inter- 
connections, the changes, the processes. If that is not done, forecasts 
may still be made, and some may come true and others not — as 
happens with the forecasts of prophets and astrologers; but they will 
lack what Dr. Popper justifiably calls “a sound basis”. 

The “sound basis” for forecasts lies in the materialist dialectical 
approach to investigating the facts. And that means that particular 
forecasts are based on scientific theories and scientific laws, which are 
arrived at by investigating facts and are tested in experience. Such 
forecasts are then based on the investigation, and on the investigation 
alone. This applies to all Marx’s forecasts, both those which have 
turned out to be true and those which have turned out to be false. 

But as Alice found at the mad tea party so we find with the critics 
of Marx, the type of exposition favoured by the March Hare and the 


THE MEANING OF DIALECTICS 


91 


Mad Hatter only obscures plain meanings by playing on the more 
obvious sorts of ambiguities in words in common use. It is quite 
evident from what Marx and Marxists have said and done that dialec- 
tical materialism, as a methodology, is far from being either a rein- 
forced dogmatism or a fountain-head of reinforced dogmatism. It is 
true that “any development whatever will fit the dialectical scheme”, 
because “the dialectical scheme” is simply a scheme for investigating 
things in their connections and development. But it is not true that 
for that reason “the dialectician need never be afraid of any refutation 
by future experience”. “The dialectician” is not a man sitting in an 
armchair who says “investigate the connections”, but a man who 
investigates the connections. The outcome of his investigation stands 
or falls by how it will fit future experience, and if actual development 
does not fit his theories he must proceed to alter his theories so that 
they fit the development — in fact, hje must carry on just like any other 
well-principled scientific inquirer. 

Always ready to reinforce his refutations, Dr. Popper, immediately 
following the passage quoted above, proceeds to admit (as he does in 
other passages of his writings too) that Marx’s teaching is opposed to 
“dogmatism” and in favour of genuine scientific inquiry. But what of 
it? Marxism is still a system of “reinforced dogmatism”. 

“Marx’s anti-dogmatic attitude should be discussed”, Dr. Popper 
writes (CR. 334). “Marx and Engels strongly insisted that science 
should not be interpreted as a body of fmal and well-established 
knowledge. . . . The scientist is not the man who knows a lot but 
rather the man who is determined not to give up the search for truth.” 

In this observation Dr. Popper transfers some of his own confusions 
into what “Marx and Engels strongly insisted” — for while insisting 
that no scientific knowledge could be “final” they certainly did not 
insist that it could not be “well-established”, and while regarding 
science as a “search” they did not deny that those who search may 
occasionally find something. But let that pass. What is of interest here 
is the argument by which Dr. Popper makes out that “Marx’s anti- 
dogmatic attitude” is transformed into “a reinforced dogmatism”. 
Here it is. 

“Marx’s progressive arid anti-dogmatic view of science has never 
been applied by orthodox Marxists within the field of their own 
activities. Progressive, anti-dogmatic science is critical — criticism is its 
very life. But criticism of Marxism, of dialectical materialism, has never 
been tolerated by Marxists. . . , Marx’s anti-dogmatic attitude exists 


92 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


only in the theory- and not in the practice of orthodox Marxism, and 
dialectic is used by Marxists, following the example of Engels' Anti - 
Duhring, mainly for the purposes of apologetics — to defend the 
Marxist system against criticism. . . . Thanks to dialectic the anti- 
dogmatic attitude has disappeared, and Marxism has established itself 
as a dogmatism which is elastic enough, by using its dialectical method, 
to evade any further attack. It has thus become what I have called a 
reinforced dogmatism" (CR. 334). 

Here Dr. Popper develops his charge in a series of very sweeping 
statements, of which it can at least be said that none of them suffers 
from the fault of being unfalsifiable, since all of them are false. 

He starts by telling us about the deplorable procedures of “orthodox 
Marxists". But if there are “orthodox Marxists" who “never apply 
Marx's progressive and anti-dogmatic view of science", that does not 
prove that the materialist dialectic which Marx regarded as the principle 
of scientific inquiry leads to dogmatism, but only that those who have 
become dogmatists have jettisoned the materialist dialectic of Marx. 

There have indeed been and there still are such “Marxists". It was 
of some of them that Marx made his well known and often misquoted 
remark: “All I know is that I am not a Marxist." Dr. Popper can call 
such dogmatists “orthodox Marxists" if he likes — it is true that they 
sometimes call themselves so. That cannot alter the fact that a “pro- 
gressive and anti-dogmatic view of science", such as Marxism ad- 
vocates, precludes any rigid adherence to unalterable formulations of 
dogmas. And the fact is that in the development of the theory and 
practice of Marxism such “orthodoxies" have been regularly and 
relentlessly discredited. 

“Marx's anti-dogmatic attitude" is acknowledged only in theory, 
never applied in practice, says Dr. Popper. Marxists have in practice 
so often experimented, rejected old schemes for new, and adopted 
theories about particular matters only to revise them, that a more 
common criticism is that their entire practice consists in a series of 
ideological and political somersaults. But Dr. Popper regards that as 
only another proof that Marxism is reinforced dogmatism. You can 
correct your previous analysis, alter your mind, change your policies — 
and still remain an “orthodox Marxist”. “Thanks to dialectic", 
Marxism is “elastic enough" to evade refutation. Marxists refuse to 
apply the “anti-dogmatic attitude" to Marxism itself. Whatever 
betides, they insist on remaining Marxists. 

What is the simple truth of all this? 


THE MEANING OP DIALECTICS 


93 


Marxism has been well described as “not a dogma but a guide to 
action”. When Dr. Popper talks about “Marxists” he is evidendy 
referring, not simply to persons who accept in theory certain pro- 
positions enunciated by Marx, but to persons who contribute to and 
participate in the world-wide movement which accepts Marx as its 
first teacher. These are the persons who have allegedly refused to apply 
“Marx's progressive and anti-dogmatic view of science . . . within the 
field of their own activities”. 

What characterises and unifies Marxism as a movement (amidst all 
diversities and disagreements) is the aim of achieving a socialist society 
through the means of class struggle, and converting it into a com- 
munist society which will provide “to each according to his needs” 
by the employment of advanced technology. These ends and means 
of the movement are based on, worked out and justified in terms of 
Marx's original investigations of society and its laws of development. 
And these investigations in turn were guided by the dialectical material- 
ist scientific principles of comprehending the facts in their own and 
not in a fantastic connection, in their movement and change, inter- 
connection and development. 

Obviously, anyone who decides that the principles employed and 
findings arrived at by Marx were fundamentally mistaken is not a 
Marxist but an anti-Marxist. And as obviously, if a sufficient number 
of those who are Marxists could be persuaded into “criticising” 
Marxism and becoming anti-Marxists, then Marxism would cease to 
exist as a force to be reckoned with, and the whole movement towards 
a communist society through the class struggle to establish socialism 
would fizzle out. Dr. Popper evidently regards this as a desirable 
outcome. So do many others — and they try to achieve it by a combi- 
nation of criticisms of Marxism and punitive measures against Marxists, 
Marxists disagree, and so resist both the criticisms and the punitive 
measures. 

Punitive measures have at some times and places been quite effective 
(though never for very long). But the same cannot be said of the 
criticisms. Marxists never tolerate criticisms of Marxism, Dr. Popper 
complains. True enough, they always answer them. I myself am 
answering some of them now. This dreadful intolerance of criticism, 
which Dr. Popper stigmatises as so contrary to the anti-dogmatic 
attitude of Marx himself, simply consists of listening to criticisms — 
and answering them. The critics, however, consider we should only 
listen — it is just too bad when we answer them back, and still worse 


94 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


when we make mincemeat out of them, as Engels did in Anti-Duhring. 
To reply to critics, and develop your own point of view at the same 
time — what a dogmatic thing to do ! 

Dr. Popper’s objection to Marxism is that the Marxist movement 
has not yet found reason to revise its fundamental principles. What is 
so dogmatic in the Marxist movement is that it has continued to grow, 
and has not yet liquidated itself. It will not abandon its aims, and it 
will not renounce the idea that the means of class struggle are the means 
for attaining them. 

There have been, of course, a number of people within the move- 
ment itself who have proposed to do so — but the movement has gone 
on without them. The so-called “revisionists” adopted Edward 
Bernstein’s attitude that “the movement is everything and the aim 
nothing”, regarding the communist aim as a utopian one based on 
dogmas, and the class struggle as a hindrance to the movement which 
could get to power more surely by class conciliation. This kind of 
“revisionism” has been justifiably described by Marxists as anti- 
Marxist. But the reasons for resisting “revisionism” are more cogent 
than simply that it is “revisionist”. Why not “revise” Marxism in this 
way, or, in other words, liquidate the Marxist movement? Because 
revisionists have failed, as they claim, to show that Marxist theory is 
based on mistaken principles or that facts falsify it, and because, on 
the other hand, abundant experience shows that the proposals of the 
revisionists do not in fact lead to the practical results claimed for them. 

The good reasons which Marxists have for defending the theory 
and practice of Marxism are not dissimilar, to those which, say, the 
directors of I.C.I. or Dupont would have for defending the theory and 
practice of the chemical industry, supposing some of the shareholders 
to object that a judicious employment of alchemy would be cheaper 
and easier. By diligent research and long practical experience I.C.I. 
and Dupont have found out something about what can be done with 
chemicals, and the necessary conditions for doing it. Similarly, 
Marxists have found out something about what can be done in society 
to satisfy human needs, and the necessary conditions for doing it — 
though the complexities and resistances met with in bringing about 
social changes are of another order than those involved in bringing 
about chemical changes. 

The aim of the Marxist movement is socialism and communism, 
attainable through class struggle. Marxists have not yet found any 
reason to renounce this aim, either as a result of their own experience 


THE MEANING OP DIALECTICS 


95 


or of the objections urged by critics. If they did, or thought they did, 
the Marxist movement would stop, and communism would remain 
where the critics say it rightly belongs, in the realm of utopia. 

At the same time, in order to move towards the aim, Marxists need 
to take at frequent intervals a long hard look at the conditions within 
which the movement is operating. They need to take into account, 
so far as they are able, all social changes and factors of change in all 
their complex interconnections. And on this analysis they have to base 
the policies pursued at different times and places, and the accounts 
rendered of particular situations. The Marxist dialectic is then exercised 
not “for the purpose of apologetics, to defend the Marxist system 
against criticism”, but to effect that “concrete analysis of concrete 
conditions” without which the movement cannot fmd its way. 

This analysis fails if it is not “critical”. It fails if it is not checked and 
tested point by point, and if it is not thoroughly revised wherever and 
whenever circumstances change or experience reveals an error. 

And of course it quite often does fail. It is but human to err, and 
Marxists often make mistakes — whether through inexperience, in- 
competence or dogmatism, or because they simply had not the time or 
means to conduct all the inquiries necessary. Their “reinforced dog- 
matism” then takes the form (luckily for the movement) of their not 
giving up the struggle or becoming anti-Marxists every time some- 
thing goes wrong. Thanks to this reinforced dogmatism or, as it 
might better be phrased, clear-headedness and high morale, and thanks 
to the fact that the movement is so deeply rooted in social realities that 
whenever some go wrong others come forward to put them right, 
errors get corrected, and when circumstances change changed policies 
are adopted to meet changed circumstances. 

It was for this reason that Lenin reinforced his dogmatism by 
.calling for continual “criticism and self-criticism”. Lenin did, however, 
venture to remark, when annoyed by critics who jeered at the mistakes 
of Communists from the security of their padded cells in the capitalist 
madhouse, that the mistakes we make are like making “two plus two 
equal five”, whereas the mistakes they make are like making “two 
plus two equal a tallow candle”. When we make two plus two equal 
five we soon discover our error and fmd the right way of making 
them four. 

In the international development of the Marxist movement, each 
generation is faced with conditions and tasks significantly different 
from those of the last. Circumstances change, and the very achieve- 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


96 

ments, as well as the errors, of the previous generation present new 
tasks to the next. Similarly, these circumstances and tasks are different 
from one economic region to another, even from one country to 
another. In this way the “Marxism** of one time is not precisely the 
same as that of another time, and the “Marxism* * of one place not 
precisely the same as that of another place. Besides errors which are 
peculiar to one time and place, the correct analysis, the correct de- 
finition of tasks, becomes different. 


4 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 

I. THE SCIENCE OF INTERCONNECTIONS 

Dr. Popper's contention that dialectical materialism is a reinforced 
dogmatism comes from his failure to comprehend that the terms 
“dialectics" and “materialism”, separately or together, do not stand 
for particular dogmatic theories but for the way of thinking or the 
approach necessary for working out non-dogmatic scientific theories. 
This applies equally whether the objects of investigation are processes 
of nature or of society — for there is no gulf between these. People 
are material organisms, and their individual and social activities are 
as much a part of the material world as are any other distinguishable 
types of material interactions. Dr. Popper is right, of course, in saying 
that Marx adopted an “anti-dogmatic attitude”. He is entirely wrong 
in saying that to go on maintaining such an attitude demands “criticism 
of dialectical materialism”. On the contrary, dialectical materialism is 
the principle of such an attitude, and consistently to maintain that 
attitude demands consistently maintaining dialectical materialism. 

But, it will be objected, is not dialectical materialism itself a theory 
— the general philo sophical theory of Marxism? And is not its intolerant 
assertion therefore dogmatic? 

This objection depends only on equivocation. The word “theory” 
is ambiguous, and is here employed in two senses. There is theory in 
the sense of theory which informs or claims to inform practice ; and 
theory in the sense of statement of the principles to be employed in 
informing practice. Scientific theories, religious theories, and also 
many traditional philosophical theories, are of the first sort. But the 
theory of dialectical materialism is of the second sort. 

If the reader fmds this confusing, I can only say that this ambiguity 
resides in the customary use of words, and that once it is pointed out 
the confusion vanishes. If one wanted, however, to use a technical 
term to point the distinction, the Greek prefix “meta-” could be 
adopted, and one could speak of “theory” and “meta-theory” (like 
those who now distinguish “mathematics” and “meta-mathematics”). 
Dialectical materialism would then be called the meta-theory of 
Marxism — the theoretical statement of the principles which Marxism 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


98 

advocates for the working out of all theory to inform human practice. 
But if one nevertheless prefers speaking English to speaking Greek, 
one will simply say (as is customary) that dialectical materialism is 
the general philosophical theory of Marxism. 

As I have tried to explain, materialism is opposed to idealism, and 
dialectics to metaphysics. When theory is idealist it engages in false 
abstraction and its claim to inform us is a sham. When theory is 
metaphysical it is not necessarily an uninformative sham (though it 
may be that as well, if it is also idealist), but it is abstract and limited, 
in the sense that it considers objects and processes, and assigns properties 
and relations to things, only in abstraction from the concrete conditions 
in which they come to be and cease to be. 

The principles of materialism, therefore, are the general ones to 
make theory informative, and the principles of materialist dialectics 
are the ones to carry forward informative theory into the concrete 
analysis of concrete conditions. And the general philosophical theory 
of dialectical materialism is the statement of the principles or rules of 
materialism and dialectics. This (like physics or mathematics) is not 
something that can be finally and completely formulated once for all. 
It has to be worked out and developed. 

Materialism expresses what is necessary to keep theory on the 
ground and stop it flying away on the wings of false abstraction. We 
must also make sure that all sides, all aspects of the concrete conditions 
to be investigated are properly related to and connected with each 
other. This is the business of dialectics. Dialectics expresses what is 
required in theory to connect the data properly, to assemble properly 
the various items of information, or to process the information, so as 
to make analysis concrete and avoid one-sidedness. To state the general 
principles or laws of dialectics is, then, to state those most general 
laws of interconnection which are and must be exemplified in processes. 
These laws do not state what is going to happen or not happen in 
particular cases, but they state th c forms of interconnection in the real 
world, which are exemplified whatever happens, and which it is the 
job of every concrete analysis to trace out. 

Can we discover such laws? Marx and Engels were of opinion, 
and said so clearly, that examination of the findings of science does 
lead to the conclusion that there are such laws which are universally 
exemplified. They were of opinion that such general concepts as 
those of “the unity of opposites” and “the transformation of quanti- 
tative into qualitative changes” express, however imprecisely in their 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


99 


initial formulation, universal laws which are always found exemplified 
in all the processes of both nature and society. That is to say, whatever 
process we may consider, the concrete analysis of what is going on 
always reveals the inseparable connection of opposite sides or aspects, 
the conflict or struggle of contradictory elements, the occurrence of 
qualitative changes as a result of quantitative changes, and so on. Of 
course, if the concepts are imprecise, and the terminology employed 
loose or ambiguous, these are defects of exposition which future work 
ought to be able to remedy. 

In their works Marx and Engels provided numerous illustrations 
of what they conceived to be the correct application of such general 
concepts of dialectics, as well as providing explanations (which I have 
quoted) of what they meant in general by “materialism” and 
“dialectics”. But they nowhere undertook any systematic working 
out of the “laws of dialectics” in their generality. What they did — 
and Engels especially in the chapters on the laws of dialectics in 
Anti-Duhring and Dialectics of Nature — was to cite examples of 
phenomena corresponding to these laws. 

Engels made the purpose of these examples perfectly clear. He was 
arguing against Duhring and others who had said that “dialectics” 
was nothing but a farrago of empty phrases. He cited examples to 
demonstrate that this was not so, but that the sorts of movements 
and interconnections described as “dialectical” do occur. He demon- 
strated that such concepts as “the transformation of quantity into 
quality” and “the negation of the negation” really are, as he said they 
were, “abstracted from the history of nature and society”, because 
many concrete examples of such modes of interconnection are in fact 
to be found in “the history of nature and society”. 

Such examples did demonstrate what Engels set out to demonstrate. 
But of course, the mere citing of examples did not and could not 
demonstrate the universality and necessity of the laws of dialectics. 
Examples can serve to make clear the meaning of concepts, and to 
refute criticisms based on misunderstanding their meaning or on 
saying that they are meaningless. But no list of examples, however 
long, could suffice to establish the universal validity of concepts. 
Nor could examples demonstrate that the “laws” exemplified were 
the complete laws, that there were no others. 

These are elementary points of logic which anyone who discusses 
dialectics ought to understand, though some apparently do not. There 
is no reason to include Engels among the latter. On the contrary, 


100 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


what he wrote makes it clear that he understood such points of logic 
very well. And he accordingly stated (I have already quoted this 
statement, but now I add my own italics) : “Dialectics is to be developed 
as the science of interconnections.” 

A science is meant to comprise, one would suppose, a good deal 
more than a list of examples. Engels also said that he was “not concerned 
with writing a textbook of dialectics ,, ) and that in citing examples 
of dialectical laws he did not “go into the inner connection of these 
laws with one another”. The “science of interconnections” would 
have, however, not only to state a set of laws but show how they 
were connected, and it would all have to be worked out and demon- 
strated by appropriate methods of formulation and test. 

That there is work to be done here was likewise emphasised by 
Lenin. In his notes On the Question of Dialectics Lenin criticised G. V. 
Plekhanov on the grounds that, in his exposition, laws of dialectics 
were only “taken as the sum-total of examples”. “The same is true 
of Engels,” Lenin added, “but it is in the interests of popularisation.” 
He then stated that the “principal” law of dialectics, “the unity of 
opposites”, ought to be expounded and demonstrated “as a law of 
cognition and as a law of the objective world”. 

At all events, unless it can be so expounded, and ways found of 
testing the exposition at every link and every step, dialectics can 
hardly claim the status of “the science of interconnections”. 

Materialist dialectics asserts “the unity of opposites”, and that there 
are “contradictions” in all the phenomena of nature and society, as 
universal truth. Examples, as I have just said, may help to illustrate 
what is meant, and to show that the concepts are not empty ones. 
But they cannot by themselves suffice to demonstrate the universality 
of the concepts, or to explain why it must be so. What is required, as 
both Engels and Lenin after him stated very clearly, is for more work 
to be done on the actual derivation and basis of these concepts, so 
as to show why “concrete analysis” should always exemplify, 
say, the unity of opposites and the discovery of dialectical contradic- 
tion. 

If Dr. Popper wants to criticise Marxists, he could well point out 
that we have been slow to follow up the very clear theoretical 
directives of both Engels and Lenin for the systematic study of 
materialist dialectics, which would make it more than “the sum-total 
of examples” and develop it as the real “science of interconnections”. 
But wanting to make out that Engels was only interested in 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


101 


“apologetics’ * and that dialectics is all nonsense anyway, he has not 
thought fit to assist us with any such constructive criticism. 

2. THE UNITY OF OPPOSITES 

The fundamental concept of dialectics is that of die unity or inseparable 
connection of opposites. This has been stated by nearly all who 
throughout the history of philosophy have variously discussed 
“dialectics”. At the start of the present discussion, when examining 
the distinction of “dialectics” from “metaphysics” as a method of 
thinking, the point emerged that “dialectics consists in following up 
the connections of opposites ”. 

The idea that everything that comes to be is the product of the 
mutual interaction and interpenetration of opposites, and holds them 
within itself, is a very ancient one, being founded on universal 
experience. Thus, for example, in very ancient Chinese philosophy 
the. world and everything in it was said to be the product of the 
action and conflict of eternally opposite forces or principles, mani- 
festing themselves in all the particular oppositions to be found in the 
universe. Every unity necessarily divides into two opposite com- 
ponents contained within it, and development results from the 
interaction of these inseparable opposites into which it divides. 
Undifferentiated unity would be motionless: motion arises and 
continues as a result of “the division of the One” into conflicting 
opposites. Something of the sort has, indeed, recently been repeated 
by Mao Tse-tung and his followers in China. For this way of thinking, 
the existence of opposites and their inseparable connection is the 
fundamental fact of the universe. It is an ultimate mystery for which 
there is no accounting. It just is so. 

It is certainly true that a fundamental opposition is always to be 
found in every process or aspect of processes we may consider. For 
example, in vision the light and the dark, black and white; in touch 
the hot and cold, rough and smooth, hard and soft; in magnetism, 
opposite poles ; in all motion, forwards and backwards, up and down, 
right and left; and so on. However, in considering such examples of 
opposition we would be well advised to avoid the fallacy of false 
abstraction into which both the earliest philosophers and some of their 
later followers seem to have fallen. Thus, for example, the opposite 
terms “light” and “dark” do not stand for eternal and primeval 
forces of Light and Darkness the war between which produces the 


102 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


phenomena of variations in light and shade. On the contrary, the 
opposition between “light” and “dark” is simply the logical opposition 
of abstract terms employed in the description of the phenomena of 
vision familiar to us in changes of light and shade, and from light 
to dark. 

In general, any terminology adapted to the statement and description 
of changes (or in other words, any language, or any apparatus of 
workable concepts) is sure to reveal in logical analysis a structure of 
opposite terms. It is a logical necessity. Why is this? It is because to 
specify a change one must specify a direction of change — from this 
to that. The total complex of observable changes includes many 
different aspects of change, each of which can be considered in 
abstraction. For instance, there are changes in colour, in shape, in 
relative motion, and so on. To specify what change is taking place in 
any particular case under a given aspect of change, one must be able 
to specify a direction of change, and then that the change is taking 
place either in that direction or in the opposite direction. Every possible 
direction of change necessarily has its opposite. It follows that 
in specifying the changes taking place under any aspect of possible 
change, we always find ourselves confronted with opposites, two 
opposite directions of change , imder which the totality of possible changes 
can take place. 

Suppose, then, that instead of specifying changes we are concerned 
with comparisons. The respects under which things may be compared 
are the same as the respects under which they can change. And 
comparisons are the same thing as estimates of what change would be 
involved in changing the state of the one thing compared into that 
of the other. So of course the opposites of directions of change also 
appear as the opposites of comparison. Hence in comparing shades, 
for example, we have the “opposites” — dark and light, black and 
white. They appear not as opposite directions of change but as 
opposite qualities. 

The most elementary instances of the principle of “the unity of 
opposites” are those afforded by the logical principle that to specify 
changes we have to specify them under opposite directions of change 
peculiar to each aspect of change. All those elementary examples of 
inseparable opposites like black and white, hot and cold, wet and 
dry, up and down, north and south, and so on, quoted to illustrate 
the principle of the unity of opposites, are examples of the principle 
that possible changes go in opposite directions. If, then, dialectics is 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


103 

(as Lenin said) “the concrete analysis of concrete conditions'’, and the 
principles or laws of dialectics are the principles or laws which have 
to be applied in passing from a more abstract to a more concrete 
account of things, the most elementary principles of dialectics are 
those concerned with the use of concepts of opposite directions of 
change when specifying changes and engaging in comparisons. 

These principles are very elementary and seemingly trivial. And 
so it cannot but seem something of an anti-climax when one arrives 
at them as a result of eliminating false abstractions from the impressive 
but obscure and mystical conception of the eternal law of the division 
of unity into inseparable and contradictory opposites, whose omni- 
present conflict produces all the phenomena of the world. 

However, lest it be said that we are reducing dialectics to the 
commonplace, we should go on to observe that a good deal more is 
involved in the thorough working out of the principle of the unity 
of opposites. In this, a great deal of muddle can be created, not only 
by false abstraction (such as that engaged in by most ancient and 
some modern exponents), but also by muddling up together different 
types of example. For instance, if to the examples of “opposites” 
expressive of opposite directions of change (which I cited above) are 
added further examples of “opposites” such as “male and female” 
or “capitalists and workers” or “socialised production and private 
appropriation”, then the whole conception of opposites and of their 
connection is confounded by the confusion and indiscriminate lumping 
together of different types of opposition and of the unity of opposites. 
This shows that the principle of “the unity of opposites” is not one 
single universal law which can be expressed in a single formula, but a 
whole branch of philosophical inquiry which needs careful working out. 

So far as it relates to opposite directions of change, the principle 
of the unity of opposites expresses only what is logically necessary in 
the conceptual representation of changes. Further working out of the 
same principle can proceed on the same basis. 

I have already remarked several times upon the procedures of 
abstraction characteristic of all thinking. All thinking proceeds by 
abstractions out of the concrete processes amid which we live, and 
then represents them in terms of these abstractions and of com- 
binations of abstractions. I pointed out that “all statement abstracts”, 
and cited as an example the statement “This rose is red”, which 
“abstracts a particular rose from the total environment, and its colour 
from the totality of its other properties”. I then pointed out that 


104 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


there are different “modes of abstraction”, which are “properly 
adopted for different practical purposes”. For example, to talk about, 
say, colour is evidently one mode of abstraction, to talk about shape 
or size another, to talk about relative motion yet another. 

Principles of dialectics come in when we pass from more abstract 
to more concrete statement. They come in as the principles of properly 
combining or assembling different modes of abstraction in the concrete 
analysis of concrete conditions. The most elementary exercise in 
abstraction characteristic of our thinking is that of abstracting the 
different aspects of observable change and the opposite directions of 
change under these different aspects. In terms of these abstractions we 
state the changes and possible changes things undergo, and make 
comparisons by means of which we state the properties of things and 
relate them to each other by comparison of their properties. The most 
elementary exercise of dialectics is, therefore, the exercise of properly 
combining in the concrete analysis of concrete conditions the abstract 
conceptions of aspects of change and of opposite directions of change. 

But this is only the beginning of the story of the adventures of 
dialectical tliinking, not the end. 

“The world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made 
tilings, but as a complex of processes.” It will be remembered that 
Engels called this statement (which, as he said, is so obvious that it is 
seldom contradicted) a “great fundamental thought”. It follows from 
it (as I pointed out in an earlier chapter) that to talk about “things” 
and “complexes of tilings” is merely one mode of abstraction, adequate 
for some practical purposes but far from adequate for others. Quite 
evidently, to talk about the complex of processes going on, and to 
say how out of it there emerge the various complexes of things which 
we observe and which come and go and change in processes, is to 
talk more concretely than simply to say “There are such and such 
things” — which is true enough, but a much more abstract statement. 
Therefore the concrete analysis of concrete conditions always demands 
that we should combine modes of abstraction which deal with “things” 
and modes of abstraction which deal with “processes”. This involves 
rather more profound questions than those hitherto considered. 

As the ancient philosopher Heraclitus put it, “everything flows”. 
Or as Hegel put it, nothing just “is”: all “being” is “becoming”, a 
ceaseless coming to be and ceasing to be. A feature of conceptual 
consciousness, derived from the use of language, is, however, that as 
reflected in statements the passage of time is apparently arrested. If 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


105 


you make a remark like, for instance, “He came in at the door ,, J a 
particular event, a particular state of affairs, is, so to speak, taken up 
out of time and fixed in the combination of symbols. However, to 
reflect (however inadequately) the actual passage of time amd the 
actual spatial-temporal interconnection in that passage, from which 
momentary states of affairs, relations of things, and so on, are abstracted 
and fixed in repeatable images, it is necessary to say how particular 
things, complexes of things, facts and events come to be and cease to 
be in processes . 

For this reason there are always two fundamental and inseparable 
modes of abstraction employed in the reflection of concrete reality in 
thought — that mode which, in Engels’ words, produces only an 
abstract picture of “a complex of ready-made things”, and that which 
then contributes to a more concrete picture of “a complex of processes”. 

As we saw earlier, the more concrete picture of “a complex of 
processes” includes what was presented in the abstract picture of “a 
complex of things”. Evidently, therefore, the picture of “a complex 
of processes” is composed by combining with the products of the mode 
of abstraction which gives only “a complex of things” the products 
of that other and complementary mode of abstraction which gives 
“processes”. To reflect concrete reality, flowing in time, we have 
therefore to combine these abstractions in the picture of things coming 
to be and ceasing to be in ever-moving interrelationship in processes. 

It follows that for the adequate representation of concrete reality 
there is always required, as a strictly logical or logically necessary 
requirement, the combination of what may loosely be called “complex 
of things” concepts with “complex of processes” concepts — which are 
thus logically paired together. This, I believe, is the rational explanation 
of a remark by Hegel with which he introduced what he called “The 
Doctrine of Essence” in the Logic section of his Encyclopaedia of the 
Philosophical Sciences , a remark so obscure it may well have made Dr 
Popper groan (and not only him): “The terms in Essence are always 
mere pairs of correlatives.” The truth is, and this is a profound principle 
of dialectical thinking, that we must always connect die “opposite” 
but complementary and inseparable aspects or features which concrete 
reality presents to us — of flow and arrested flow, fluid process and 
fixed momentary state, unrepeatable passage and repeatable pattern — 
in the concrete analysis of concrete conditions. Hence we get the 
logically necessary correlation in pairs of such categories as those of 
“property and relation”, “form and substance”, or “quality and 


106 TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 

quantity”. The first term in each pair is the “complex of things” 
category, the second, its correlative or opposite “process” category; 
the second the category of flow, the first of arrested flow. 

Thus, for example, things are conceived of as having properties 
which “belong” to them: and at the same time, when considered in 
their movement, they enter into all manner of complex relations with 
other things. The “metaphysical” way of abstract thinking just sets 
down properties and relations side by side, as it were. There are 
properties and (also) relations. On the other hand, the concrete analysis 
of concrete conditions (in which principles of dialectics emerge) is 
concerned with tracing out how things come to manifest various 
properties as a result of the ever-changing relationships which occur 
in processes. Thus the properties of things change with changing 
relations: what is true of a thing in one relationship is not true in 
another, what is true in one set of circumstances is not true in another. 

Again, consider the pair of “opposites”: “form and substance”, or 
“form and content”. This involves consideration of the way in which 
the occurrence of processes, which may loosely be said to constitute 
the “substance” or “content” of things, always produces, and is 
circumscribed within, certain patterns or “forms”. (Unfortunately, 
the terms provided by ordinary language are far from precise and 
invariably ambiguous, so that unless we are to embark on a long 
discussion in which a whole series of technical distinctions and defini- 
tions are included these points about dialectics can only be hinted at 
in a rough and ready way; this is the best that limitations of time and 
space allow us here.) We find that substance determines form, and 
form limits the development of substance. For undialectical thinking, 
however, forms are considered abstractly, apart from the processes 
which take on such forms — as when, for example, political theorists 
analyse forms of state (such as constitutional monarchies, republics, 
democracies, despotisms) in abstraction from the processes of class- 
domination which are carried on under such forms. On the other 
hand, it is equally metaphysical to consider processes in abstraction 
from the forms they take on — as though one should generalise about, 
say, the course of the class struggle without realising that its character 
and outcome is vitally affected by whether it is waged under the 
form of a democratic process or of a struggle against a fascist dictator- 
ship. 

Again, the famous dialectical principle about “quality” and 
“quantity” comes in here. Things and complexes of things present to 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


107 

us distinctive qualities — they are of distinct “kinds”, they exemplify 
distinct “laws” in the manner in which they affect us and affect other 
things. At the same time, in the processes out of which qualitative 
differences emerge there are quantitative measurable changes of increase 
and decrease, in the course of which the proportion or balance between 
various factors is altered. For exam pie, if pressure piles up inside a 
boiler while its ability to contain the pressure remains constant, the 
balance of forces is altered and an explosion occurs. Or if extra atoms 
are added to a molecule there is a chemical change, because the balance 
of the molecule is altered and it reacts differently in its relationships 
with others. Thus qualitative characteristics depend on quantitative 
relations, and quantitative changes invariably lead up to qualitative 
changes. To consider quality and quantity, on the other hand, as 
distinct and unconnected — to consider qualities apart from quantitative 
relations, or to consider quantitative relations apart from the qualities 
which accrue from them — is mere metaphysical abstraction. 

These sorts of consideration lead to a result of very great interest. 
For when in the analysis of specific cases we seek to connect the opposite 
aspects under which processes of change and development are to be 
considered, we come upon the so-called “dialectical contradiction ”, or 
“the struggle of opposites”. As Lenin remarked in his Philosophical 
Notebooks (true, the language is rather obscure and it should be 
remembered these were only notes which he made for further work 
which he never did) : “The condition of the knowledge of all processes 
in the world ... is the knowledge of them as a unity of opposites. 
Development is the ‘struggle* of opposites.” 

When we consider, for example, how the properties manifested by 
things are conditioned by the circumstances of their existence, or the 
relationships occurring within processes; how form is conditioned 
by substance, and substance by form; how qualities depend on 
quantities, and so on — then we find necessarily and always in processes 
of change and development the incidence of “struggle** or “con- 
tradiction”. For changing relations destroy existing properties which 
nevertheless persistently manifest themselves for as long as possible, 
quantitative changes break up old qualities and bring new ones to 
birth, and processes break out of old forms which nevertheless, so 
long as they persist, limit the development of those very processes. 

It is, I believe, along these lines that we can expect to show why 
“concrete analysis** must (as Marxism says) always and necessarily 
exemplify the discovery of “contradictions**. But before proceeding 


108 TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 

further we should perhaps at this point listen again to Dr. Popper, 
who has, as usual, a “devastating criticism’' to offer. 

Generously endeavouring to explain, if not excuse, the mental 
aberrations of Marxists, Dr. Popper has accounted for the dialectical 
conception of the unity of opposites and of contradiction as follows : 

. if we look a little closer into these so-called contradictory facts, 
then we find that all examples proffered by dialecticians just state that 
the world in which we live shows, sometimes, a certain structure 
which could perhaps be described with the help of the word ‘polarity'. 
An instance of that structure would be the existence of positive and 
negative electricity" (CR. 329). 

So, according to Dr. Popper, what dialecticians have done is to 
notice that polarity “sometimes" occurs, cite examples of it, and then 
turn this into a universal necessary “law" of dialectical “contradiction" 
or “unity of opposites". First, as we saw earlier, he made “dialectical 
contradiction" mean “logical contradiction". Now, regardless of the 
inconsistency (for inconsistencies seem to trouble Dr. Popper as little 
as he says they trouble Marxists), he makes it mean “polarity". 

But in the first place, many examples of “contradictions" have 
been “proffered" which have little in common with the polar oppo- 
sition of positive and negative electricity — such as the contradiction 
between socialised production and private appropriation which is 
proffered as the basic contradiction of capitalism. In the second place, 
such polar oppositions as that between positive and negative electricity 
do not merely exemplify types of “structures" which “sometimes" 
occur in “the world in which we live", and might perhaps not occur 
at all in some other world, but types of “structures" which must 
necessarily occur if bodies move in space. 

Let us look for a moment at some phenomena which “could 
perhaps be described with the help of the word ‘polarity' ".A rotating 
sphere must have a north and south pole, for there cannot possibly 
be the one pole without the other and there must be both, opposite 
poles one at each end of the axis about which the sphere rotates. 
Similarly, if there is a flow of electricity there must be positive and 
negative charges. Where there is motion the description of it, whatever 
it is, is bound to involve polarity — if only because the concept of 
motion in one direction is tied with that of motion in the opposite 
direction. In this criticism of dialectics Dr. Popper has made a double 
error. In the first place, he has failed to notice that quite different 
types of relation fall under the heading of “unity of opposites", and 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


109 


has tried to convict Marxists of basing their ideas on a confusion of 
types of which it is he himself who is guilty. In the second place, he 
has confused logical necessities with mere “matters of fact”, when he 
supposes that such “structures” as those described “by the help of the 
word ‘polarity’ ” are simply “structures” which “sometimes” as a 
matter of fact occur, and not structures which must necessarily occur. 

It is of importance to make clear that there are necessities exemplified 
in the types of connection we discover in “the concrete analysis of 
concrete conditions”; and the working out of the general principles 
of dialectics means the working out of these necessities . Considerations 
about the type of “polarity” exemplified by “positive and negative 
electricity” belong to the more elementary part of this, being concerned 
with what is necessarily involved in the description and analysis of 
physical motions. The necessities considered under the heading of 
“dialectical contradiction” involve further considerations about the 
structure of all processes, going beyond the consideration of “physical” 
aspects alone. Then it is found that it makes not the slightest difference 
what sorts of process one is considering, whether they be processes 
of nature or of society — the concrete analysis, the scientific analysis 
and explanation, of processes always takes the form of the exhibition 
of specific contradictions, of “the struggle of opposites”. In general, 
the complete account or concrete analysis of processes must always 
be stated in terms of “the unity and struggle of opposites”. This is, 
indeed, the logical structure of explanation or concrete analysis. 

In the case of social development, for example, characterised by the 
conscious strivings and clashes of people, the basic contradiction which 
has to be taken into account in describing and explaining this develop- 
ment is that between the way in which men combine together to 
satisfy their needs by their intercourse with nature, and the forms of 
their own social organisation. It is on the basis of this contradiction 
that there develop the various conflicts and struggles of men with 
men — which are conscious struggles, unlike anything that takes place 
in nature as distinguished from human society. 

It is the universality of contradiction, the universal truth that in 
the connection of its different sides or aspects all process exhibits the 
unity of opposites, and that all development is die development of the 
consequent contradictions inherent in tilings and processes, that 
accounts for the incidence of those sudden changes, radical transforma- 
tions and breaks in continuity which are such a marked feature of the 
world as we know it. As Hegel used to say, the contradictions within 


no 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


a given state of affairs result in its eventually giving rise to “its own 
negation”. 

Needless to say, the word “negation” is here used, as was customary 
with Hegel, in a peculiar sense, not to be confounded with that 
defined in formal logic, but not for that reason particularly recondite 
or obscure. In formal logic, the negation of an expression is obtained 
by a formal logical operation — so that one can write down the negation, 
according to the rules of formal logic, without any investigation of 
what actually occurs. The sense of the word “negation” in which 
Hegel spoke of a given state of affairs having “its own negation” is 
quite different — for here the negation is not deduced by logic but is 
discovered as a result of investigating actual processes and finding out 
where they lead. In this sense, a given structure or a given state of 
things has “its own negation”, which is on the one hand opposed to 
and incompatible with it, and on the other hand is linked with it in as 
much as neither occurs without the other — the one issues in the other, 
as “its negation”, and the other comes into being only as such a 
negation. As Hegel observed, the connection of life and death, for 
example, is of this type. The processes of life give rise to death, and 
death only happens as the termination and negation of life. To under- 
stand life, as to understand death, we must, in our concrete analysis 
of real processes, have reached an understanding of this connection. 
In general, where B is thus “the negation” of A, we misunderstand 
and misinterpret what actually happens in the processes where A or 
B occur if we merely consider A and B as opposed and incompatible 
without grasping their “dialectical connection”. It was in this sense 
that Marx regarded socialism as “the negation” of capitalism. 

As Hegel further said, in definite conditions the “negation” is in 
turn “negated”, so as to produce a new version of the original structure 
or state of affairs. The Hegelian terminology is, as usual, puzzling, 
because of the ambiguity of the word “negation” which is used 
differently in the context of dialectics and in the more familiar context 
of formal logic. But the fact is undoubted. Of many irreversible but 
at the same time cyclical processes we can say (as Marx said when he 
showed how the working owner of means of production, expropriated 
by capitalists, would have the means of production restored to him 
when capitalists were expropriated), “it is the negation of the negation”. 
In such cases the original condition is not simply restored, it is recreated 
in a new enriched form, “on a higher level” — as when the individual 
owners of a few simple tools are eventually replaced by the joint 


THE NECESSITY OP DIALECTICS 


III 


owners of gigantic productive powers. In such cases, we will not fully 
understand the character of new structures unless we understand them 
as the products of such processes, in their connections ivith their conditions 
of coming into being , as “the negation of the negation”. 

3. THE TEST OF DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM 

I shall now try to sum up those very good reasons which Marxists 
can find for maintaining the truth, and the necessary truth, of dialectical 
materialism, and for confidently seeking to develop it. 

As I have tried to show, the principles of materialism and of 
materialist dialectics are intended to serve us as the most general 
guiding principles for understanding the problems of life — for com- 
prehending the facts in their own and not in a fantastic connection, 
and effecting the concrete analysis of concrete conditions, in the way 
that is necessary for seeking to answer the problems of life. 

For drawing inferences we rely on the principles of logic, for 
measurement and calculation we rely on the principles of mathematics, 
for investigating phenomena we rely on the principles of scientific 
method. Our reliance on these principles does not make us “reinforced 
dogmatists”. Nor does general reliance on the principles of materialism 
and materialist dialectics make us reinforced dogmatists. No, for we 
have very good reasons for all such reliances, and the principles relied 
on are all great human discoveries which have been and continue to 
be tested by the most rigorous tests. 

Of course, mistakes can always be made, and sometimes have been 
made, in the formulation of principles. That the principles of logic, 
for example, are necessary inviolable truths does not mean that 
logicians, who try to work out these principles, cannot get them 
wrong. On the contrary, the fact is on record that Aristotle — the 
first man who tried systematically to work out the principles of 
logic — not only did not establish them all, but some of those he 
thought he had established were wrongly formulated and were not, 
exactly as formulated, valid logical principles at all. The point is that 
where mistakes are made, they can be detected and corrected. Methods 
of test are applicable in the formulation and working out of principles. 
This goes for principles of materialism and dialectics equally with 
any others. 

Dr. Popper is, then, undoubtedly in the right about the necessity 
for finding tests for everything we propose to maintain. There must 


112 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


always be tests. And if we maintain propositions without being able 
to say how to test them, and without submitting them to test, then 
at the best we are mere dogmatists or people of extreme gullibility, 
and at the worst victims of superstitions, employing meaningless 
formulas as incantations. Rationality, with its implications of over- 
coming dogmas, ignorance and superstitions, demands discussion and 
investigation, and the decision of questions on the basis of testing the 
proposed answers. 

It is quite true (as I have said already) that the Marxist movement 
has suffered from dogmatists — with a division of labour between some 
who loudly proclaim dogmas and others who obediently repeat what 
they are told. However, dogmas get discredited, and Marxism is 
opposed to dogmatism. To be a Marxist you are not required to 
subscribe to anything without reason, not to accept any formulation 
as so authoritative that it cannot be modified, or indeed rejected 
altogether, as a result of discussion. And considering the amount of 
discussion that has gone on, and continues to go on, about the formula- 
tion of even the most fundamental principles of Marxism (to which 
this present work is intended as a modest contribution), there are 
certainly no grounds for asserting that Marxism imposes a dogmatic 
uncritical attitude towards even the basic principles of Marxism 
itself. 

So now we must ask: What are the tests, what are the reasons for 
the principles of materialism and materialist dialectics? Dr. Popper 
asserts that there aren’t any. I propose to show that there are. 

To know how to test the concepts and principles of dialectical 
materialism it is first of all necessary to be clear about what types of 
concepts and principles these are. For different types of statements 
require different types of test. As many contemporary philosophers 
have astutely observed, confusions result from taking statements of 
one type to be statements of another type; and if tests appropriate 
only for one type of statement are applied to another type of statement, 
then, as the saying goes, confusion becomes worse confounded. 

Not all statements are testable “by experience” in the same way as 
are statements of the empirical sciences and, in general, factual or 
what I have called “informative” statements. Dr. Popper himself 
stresses it. He insists (very properly) that statements which cannot be 
tested by experience and which, in that sense, are “unfalsifiable”, 
must be excluded from the body of empirical sciences. But he does 
not therefore conclude that no empirically unfalsifiable statements 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


113 

are ever to be accepted. On the contrary, theorems of formal logic 
and of mathematics, for example, are empirically unfalsifiable. But 
that does not mean we should have no use for them. It simply means 
that formal logic and mathematics are not empirical sciences. 

For example, a physicist having expressed a certain connection 
between observational variables in an equation proceeds to perform 
calculations from which he arrives at a conclusion which he submits 
to experimental tests. There is clearly a distinction between the 
experimental procedure he adopts to test his hypothesis about the 
connections of physical quantities and the mathematical procedure 
he adopts to deduce one formula from another. He checks his hypo- 
thesis empirically, whereas he checks the correctness of his mathe- 
matics by making sure that each step in the calculation is vouched for 
by valid rules of calculation. And the correctness of the laws of 
calculation is not established empirically like the correctness of physical 
laws. 

Suppose that what he calculated should happen does not happen: 
this would falsify his physical hypothesis, but not the laws of mathe- 
matics which he used in working out his hypothesis. For the latter 
are not empirically falsifiable. Here is a very simplified instance to 
illustrate this point. Suppose that having put two apples in a box and 
then two more I use the mathematical rule “2 + 2 = 4” to calculate 
that later on I shall find four apples in the box. Suppose that in fact I 
find only three: this does not falsify the arithmetical theorem that 
2+2=4, but only falsifies my hypothesis that four apples put into 
the box would stay there. I should conclude that someone must have 
taken one out when I wasn’t looking. 

It may be added that the empirical unfalsifiability of mathematical 
theorems does not imply (as some philosophers have assumed) that 
mathematical ideas are or could be arrived at and defined indepen- 
dently of experience. On the contrary, our ideas of numbers are 
derived from the practical experience of counting, and unless we 
observed numbers of things and counted them we would never be 
able to arrive at the definition of the series of numbers and formulate 
and prove theorems of mathematics. But that mathematics is thus a 
product of experience and practice, and is used for practical purposes, 
does not imply that theorems of mathematics are established experi- 
mentally or are falsifiable in experience. 

The point is that certain empirically unfalsifiable statements may 
yet admit of very rigorous tests. Wrong theorems of logic or mathe- 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


114 

matics can be corrected, and correct ones proved. There are highly 
developed techniques for correcting and proving empirically un- 
falsifiable statements, just as there are highly developed techniques 
for empirically testing empirically falsifiable statements. The theorems 
of logic and mathematics are types of statement which admit of 
proof but not of empirical test, just as the statements of the empirical 
sciences are a type of statement which admit of empirical test but 
not of proof. 

What Dr. Popper objects to, and what Marxists object to as well, 
are statements which do not admit of any genuine test at all. These 
include statements which involve what I have called “false abstraction” . 
These statements are neither empirically falsifiable nor are there 
non-empirical ways of establishing or refuting them. It is true that a 
great deal of argument and discussion goes on about such statements — 
for instance, the debates of theologians. But the trouble with this sort 
of argument is that it always, in the last resort, relies on dogmatically 
imposed authority. The argument applies tests of a sort, in which 
statements are tested by reference to some set of master statements. 
But how are the master statements tested? Only by finding out which 
master statements are supported by the loudest voices or most alarming 
excommunications, or, in more liberal circles, which are deemed most 
morally uplifting or most comforting. Dr. Popper seems to be of 
opinion, and Marxists who follow Marx most certainly are of opinion, 
that the test for whether statements are to be accepted for our practical 
guidance lies in whether there are ways of genuinely testing them. 

According to Dr. Popper, philosophical theories are empirically 
unfalsifiable. One cannot but agree with him on this point, for 
empirically falsifiable theories would be subject to the tests employed 
by empirical sciences and so would come under the heading of 
“empirical science” rather than “philosophy”. Historically there was, 
to begin with, no clear division between philosophy and the empirical 
sciences, but only a general speculation about “the nature of things”. 
As the empirical sciences developed, however, they separated off 
from philosophy; and so the division has been introduced between 
empirical sciences, the statements of which are empirically tested, 
and philosophy, the statements of which are tested, if genuinely 
tested at all, by different means. Indeed, the division of philosophy 
from the empirical sciences was largely the result of the systematic 
development of scientific method, systematically using techniques of 
empirical test; certain discussions not subject to such tests were 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


115 

channelled off from the sciences into the separate province of 
philosophy. 

Recognising this division, Dr. Popper says it is nevertheless possible 
“to examine critically” empirically unfalsifiable philosophical theories 
(CR 198). Of course, “critical examination” entails criteria for rejection. 
So Dr. Popper proceeds to suggest criteria for deciding to reject 
certain philosophical theories. These lead to the rejection of all (in 
Marxist terminology) idealist and metaphysical theories. We agree: I 
have already tried to indicate the grounds for rejecting these theories. 

The question has to be raised, however, whether there are valid 
grounds for accepting any philosophical theory. Dr. Popper’s whole 
stress is on finding good reasons to reject philosophical theories. How- 
ever, if the criteria employed in “critical examination” are so devised 
that any theory is eventually rejected , such criteria are evidently as 
worthless as they would be if there were no criteria for rejection at all. 
We require to know not only what makes a philosophical theory 
unacceptable, but also what makes it acceptable. 

Dialectical materialism (so Marxists contend) is a philosophical 
theory of such a kind that good reasons can be found for accepting it. 
That does not mean we are against “examining it critically”. It does 
mean that we are against the assumption that “critical examination” 
is always tantamount to rejection. 

General principles of materialism are empirically unfalsifiable. So 
are general principles of materialist dialectics. How could one set about 
falsifying them? They do not entail any predictions of what will 
happen in particular circumstances, and so nothing that happens will 
ever falsify them. But these statements are not empty ones (owing 
their appeal merely to an impressive combination of words with 
emotional resonance, like “The All is One” or “God is Love”, which 
will likewise never be empirically falsified). What gives them practical 
content is their function of stating guiding principles for formulating, 
assembling and concretising information. And it is in relation to that 
function that they are tested. 

The logical type of a statement is given by the function it performs 
in human practice. And principles of materialism and dialectics are 
distinguished from statements of empirical sciences, and from 
theorems of logic and mathematics, precisely by their logical type and 
practical function. In them is discovered the correct form for philo- 
sophical, as distinct from empirical, formal-logical or mathematical 
statements. And in that form, philosophy, the general principles of 


ii 6 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


materialism and of materialist dialectics, can be and should be 
developed as a science, so worked out as to be tested at every step and 
the findings confirmed. 

I shall now try to define the logical type of the philosophical state- 
ments of dialectical materialism, so as to characterise them as a distinct 
type of statement, and in doing so to indicate how they may be tested. 
The object of the exercise is to distinguish them, pn the one hand, 
from statements of the empirical sciences, and of logic and mathe- 
matics — all of which have their own specific types of test ; and on the 
other hand from those statements, made in other philosophies, which 
are to be rejected because so formulated as to evade any positive test. 
I must premise, however, that I shall attempt this here in only a very 
rough and ready way. To go into these questions with all the exactitude 
and attention to detail proper in a logical treatise would require much 
more space and time than is available here at present. 

To distinguish the type of philosophical statements made by dia- 
lectical materialism and how they are to be tested, it will be convenient 
to introduce one new technical term — category. This is defined in terms 
of “mode of abstraction”. 

The statements which result from different modes of abstraction 
employ different categories; conversely, the different categories we 
employ in making statements, or in terms of which we formulate our 
information are the products of different modes of abstraction. To 
distinguish modes of abstraction is to distinguish the categories wherein 
the products of such modes of abstraction are expressed, and to 
distinguish categories is to distinguish them as products of different 
modes of abstraction. 

Thus, for example, to talk of “things” is, as I have said, one particular 
mode of abstraction; and this mode of abstraction gives us the category 
of “thing”. To talk of “processes” is another mode of abstraction 
giving us the category of “process”. Similarly, “causality” is a category 
in as much as when we distinguish and relate causes and effects we are 
dealing in a special mode of abstraction. Thus to discuss causality in a 
philosophical way is to discuss how the category of causality is pro- 
perly applied, and is quite distinct from the empirical investigation of 
causes and effects. Again, the modes of abstraction which result in our 
distinguishing “properties” and “qualities” give us the categories of 
“property” and “quality”; and the modes of abstraction which result 
in our distinguishing “relations” and “quantities” give us the categories 
of “relation” and “quantity”. 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


117 

It is evident that there is and must be a connection between all 
legitimate modes of abstraction, inasmuch as they all abstract (to 
express it loosely) different interconnected aspects of one and the same 
concrete reality. These connections, in their generality, may be 
expressed as category-connections. Thus categories are connected by 
the way they complement and supplement one another in the reflection 
of concrete reality ; and (as noted in an earlier chapter) one result of 
this is the dialectical pairing of categories in the formation of pairs of 
“opposites”. 

In writing thus of categories, I am using the word “category” in a 
specialised sense. I am using the word as a specialised technical term for 
the purpose of discussing certain questions of philosophy. In everyday 
language, on the other hand, the word “category” is often used in 
much wider and looser senses, with which I am not here concerned. 
For example, we often speak of, say, engineers, miners and steel- 
workers as distinct “categories” of worker — that is to use the word 
“category” to apply to different trades associated with the division of 
labour in modern industry. Thus (like Humpty Dumpty) I am defining 
only how I propose to use the word “category” in this present dis- 
cussion, whereas both I and other people often legitimately use the 
same word in quite different ways in other contexts. However, my 
use here of the word “category” is not, I am sure, a mere personal 
idiosyncrasy: it corresponds pretty closely to the way this word has 
been traditionally used by many philosophers. 

What I am talking about now when I use the word “category” is 
much the same as what Aristotle was talking about at the beginning of 
scientific philosophy when he wrote a treatise called The Categories , 
and as Kant was talking about when ho spoke of “substance” and 
“causality” as “categories”. But while I am talking about what Kant 
talked about, what I am saying about the subject is quite different 
from what he said. For I am trying to express the standpoint of dia- 
lectical materialism, which is opposed to that of Kantian or any other 
brand of idealism. 

Kant said that the categories could be “deduced a priori ”. He said 
that they were somehow inherent in the mind, and that far from 
deriving them from the objective material world we project them 
from our own minds into the world — thus making the world appear 
to us, as a “phenomenon”, very different from what it is “in itself”. 
Hegel “corrected” Kant only by denying that the mind of “the finite 
individual” produces its own categories for itself; he said that the 


n8 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


categories are eternally present in the thinking of the Absolute Spirit, 
from whence they are all derived — a correction which, one may well 
protest, only makes what was mystifying already a great deal more 
mysterious. 

In saying that categories are products of different modes of abstraction 
I am saying the exact opposite of what Kant and Hegel said. I am 
adopting a materialist as opposed to an idealist approach to the 
question of categories. The categories we employ in stating information 
about the world reflect the world we are informing ourselves about. 
The interconnections of categories in informative statement, as we 
proceed to fit together relatively abstract items of information into 
the concrete analysis of concrete conditions, reflect the forms of 
interconnection of the different features and aspects of the material 
world. As Marx put it in the Afterword to the second German edition 
of Capital: “The ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected 
by the human mind and translated into forms of thought.” 

Statements formulated with such a high degree of generality as to 
deal purely with connections of categories, rather than state facts 
which come under those categories, may be called category-statements. 
For example, “Qualities depend on quantitative relations” is a category- 
statement — as distinguished from, say, “The chemical properties of 
molecules depend on how many atoms are combined in them”, which 
is a statement of fact exemplifying the connection of categories stated 
in the category-statement. The category-statement is empirically 
unfalsifiable, whereas the factual statement exemplifying it is of the 
empirically falsifiable type. It will be seen, too, that category statements 
are arrived at by a procedure of abstraction from statements of facts : 
the categories are abstracted from the facts. Categories are therefore 
in no sense “derived or known a priori”. They are not present in the 
mind or known independent of experience or prior to experience, 
but derived from or abstracted from experience. They are not imposed 
by the mind upon the known world, but abstracted by the mind from 
the material world as it is known to us in experience. 

The general philosophical principles of materialism and materialist 
dialectics may now be typified as category-statements. That is their 
logical type, as distinguished from other types of statements. It is as 
category-statements that they are of use to us, and it is as category- 
statements that they may be scientifically derived, formulated and 
tested. 

In formulating these principles it has been customary to distinguish 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 119 

“materialism” from “dialectics”. This distinction has its basis in the 
conditions of our conscious activity, which create (as I tried to indicate 
when discussing “materialism versus idealism”) the distinction and 
opposition of “material” and “ideal”. Principles of materialism are 
those of the real connection of the material and the ideal. The principles 
of materialist dialectics comprise all those further principles of inter- 
connection which come to light in the concrete analysis of concrete 
conditions. But so far as the logical type of the principles is concerned, 
there is no distinction: materialism and materialist dialectics are all of 
one piece. To suppose dialectical materialism to be some kind of 
artificial conjunction of two logically separable elements is, therefore, 
a crude error (an error which has, nevertheless, sometimes been made 
in expounding it as a philosophy). Historically, philosophical 
materialism and dialectics were separately developed — materialism in 
a metaphysical way, and dialectics mystified by idealism. By bringing 
them together Marx eradicated the twin fallacies of metaphysics and 
idealism, and laid the basis for a single unified development of philo- 
sophical principles. 

How, then, are these principles established and tested? 

First I shall repeat that, as Lenin stressed, they are not to be established 
simply by “examples”. Some Marxists do seem to have supposed that 
materialism and materialist dialectics are sufficiently established by 
citing a lot of examples to bear them out and none to contradict them. 
But this is to make the logically untenable supposition that very 
general statements embracing category-connections rest on the same 
sort of evidence as do the statements of empirical sciences. And then 
it is easy for logically trained critics to put Marxists on the spot. First 
it can be asked: Have we in fact examined all relevant cases? We 
certainly have not. But second, our claim to establish our points by 
citing positive instances is bogus. For what would happen if we did 
meet an apparently negative instance? If there arises a case where 
materialist explanation is lacking (for instance, some of the cases 
produced by so-called psychical research) it can be pleaded that the 
lack of it is only due to our not yet knowing enough; and if there 
arises a case where, say, a quantitative change does not lead to a 
qualitative one it can be pleaded that that is only because the quantitative 
change did not go far enough. Thus generalisations which claim the 
support of universal experience turn out to be so devised (just as Dr. 
Popper has said) that any experience which fails to support them may 
be dismissed as irrelevant. Principles of materialism and of materialist 


120 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


dialectics are empirically unfalsifiable. So it is absurd to claim to 
establish them as though they were ordinary empirical generalisations. 

To formulate and establish valid philosophical principles we must 
engage in that type of abstraction and generalisation which results in 
category-statements. And to establish that these statements are genuine 
it must be shown that they are necessary in the formulation and assembly 
of genuine information. Of course, it is just because they are necessary 
that genuine category-statements are unfalsifiable by experience. On 
the other hand, many statements unfalsifiable by experience are far 
from expressing genuine necessary principles — there are empty state- 
ments, statements of false idealist abstraction, and so on. 

In scientific philosophy we must, first, abstract the categories 
employed in informing ourselves about the world. That is how we 
arrive at the content of our philosophical statements. 

Second, we must work out how, in seeking a concrete analysis, 
we pass from one set of categories to another, and how we connect 
them. That is how we make our exposition scientifically systematic 
and coherent, and not a mere jumble of separate “principles”. 

Third, we must check up that every conclusion is in fact abstracted 
from the actual procedures and findings of scientific knowledge, and 
is a necessary principle in these procedures, in the sense that they 
could not get on without at least implicitly accepting it. That is how 
we test our conclusions. 

Let us briefly consider in this connection the test of the materialist 
dialectical principle about quality and quantity. Scientific procedures 
do in fact investigate the basis of observed qualities in quantitative 
relations — the principle really is adopted in scientific work. But it is 
not a principle which just so happens to be sometimes adopted, it is a 
necessary principle. For to investigate the quantitative basis of qualities, 
whether successful or not, is the only and necessary way of discovering 
how qualitative changes are determined and controlled. To suppose 
otherwise would be to suppose that the material processes of the 
structures exhibiting qualities do not affect those qualities. And if 
that were so, we could not inform ourselves of how qualities are 
determined. If, therefore, we are to try to so inform ourselves, it can 
only be by investigating quantitative relations. 

Philosophical principles are principles of “interconnection”. The 
right way of working them out and testing them must, in short, be 
such as to ensure: first, that they do relate to the actual information 
we possess and use, and are not merely cooked up out of metaphysical 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


121 


or idealist abstractions; and second, that they do state neccesary principles 
governing the formulation and assembly of that information. 

Is it, then, possible to finalise, once for all, a complete system of 
the principles of materialist dialectics? I do not think so. 

Aristotle, Kant and Hegel all supposed it possible to write down a 
complete list of categories. Professor Gilbert Ryle, the editor of the 
philosophical journal Mind , has described this idea as “scholastic”: to 
compile “a decalogue of categories” is, according to him, to try in a 
dogmatic scholastic way to circumscribe the range of our concepts. 
I think Professor Ryle is right. It does not seem to me that one can 
say: There are just so many possible modes of abstraction, and these 
are the ones. Nor can one say: The totality of forms of interconnection 
in the material world comprises exactly these, and no others. Lenin 
was apparently of the same opinion when he wrote (in his article on 
Karl Marx contributed to a Russian encyclopaedia) that “the indissoluble 
connection of all sides of every phenomenon . . . constantly discloses 
new sides”. 

Hence to assert that there are exactly three, four, or any other 
number, of “laws” to which the principles of materialist dialectics 
may be reduced, is a mistake. Of course, “in the interests of popularisa- 
tion” and illustration it is both useful and legitimate to cite certain 
“laws” (as Engels did). But that does not mean that those particular 
“laws” provide formulas under which everything that ever happens 
or ever comes to interest us is to be subsumed. As for “the unity of 
opposites”, this is less one law amongst several than a general pre- 
scription for the form that all interconnection takes. But' if one proceeds 
to consider, in a general way, the cases of “the unity of opposites”, 
there is no end to them; and each case has “its own dialectic”, requiring 
its own special study. 

Hence materialist dialectics is not a subject which can be completed 
by writing down and learning a few (or even a large number) of 
formulas in a textbook. And in that respect it is exactly like any other 
scientific discipline, whether the empirical sciences or the “exact” 
sciences of logic and mathematics. We should not expect ever to 
work out a final system of category-statements, sufficient for all 
purposes. 

4. THE PHILOSOPHY OF IDENTITY 

The value of philosophy is not that it tells us all about “the nature of 
reality” and sums it all up in a few formulas, but that it embodies a 


122 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


continued scientific activity of working out principles of how to 
think so as to inform ourselves and, informing ourselves, arrive at 
rational judgements about our human ends and the means to attain 
them. It does that, and in doing so arms us against idealist illusion 
and metaphysical abstraction. Such, at all events, is the value of 
dialectical materialist philosophy. 

It may be thought, however, that there are inconsistencies to be 
found in the way in which Engels, in particular, described the ideas 
and aims of dialectical materialism. 

Distinguishing philosophy from the empirical sciences, Engels wrote 
in the first chapter of Anti-Duhring that “what independently survives 
of all former philosophy is the science of thought and its laws — formal 
logic and dialectics”. So he very clearly coupled dialectics with formal 
logic in “the science of thought and its laws”, implying that laws of 
dialectics are laws of thought. But in the preface to the same work he 
wrote that “there could be no question of building the laws of dialectics 
into nature, but of discovering them in it and evolving them from 
it . . . Nature is the test of dialectics.” This implies that laws of dialectics 
are laws of the objective world. But can the same laws be laws of 
both? 

Engels evidently thought they could, for in Ludwig Feuerbach 
(Chapter 4) he wrote that dialectics comprises “the science of the 
general laws of motion both of the external world and of human 
thought”. And in Dialectics of Nature (Chapter 2): “It is from the 
history of nature and human society that the laws of dialectics are 
abstracted. For they are nothing but the most general laws of these 
two aspects of historical development, as well as of thought itself.” 

In similar vein Lenin asserted that dialectics must be demonstrated 
“as a law of cognition and as a law of the objective world”. 

To all this it may be objected, first, that there seems to be an initial 
uncertainty as to whether materialist dialectics formulates “laws of 
thought” or “laws of the objective world”; and second, that to say it 
does both makes the dogmatic assumption that these “laws” are 
identical. 

Such objections are (as we might have expected) rather vehemently 
lodged by Dr. Popper. 

The equation of laws of thought with laws of the objective world 
is called by Dr. Popper “the philosophy of identity”, with its pernicious 
source in Hegel. “Hegelian dialectic is based on his philosophy of 
identity. If reason and reality are identical and reason develops 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


123 


dialectically . . . then reality must develop dialectically too. The world 
must be ruled by the laws of dialectical logic” (CR. 329). With Hegel, 
Dr. Popper concedes, this notion might appear “plausible and under- 
standable” — for if, as Hegel asserted, “reality” is the creation of 
“reason”, then one would expect the laws of the objective world to 
be identical with the laws of thought. But all the same, the whole 
“philosophy of identity” is, so Dr. Popper assures us, an “utter 
absurdity”. And it becomes “even worse” when “dialectic idealism” 
is replaced by dialectical materialism. “Its holders then argue that 
reality is in fact of a material or physical character . . . and by saying 
that it is identical with reason or mind . . . imply that the mind is also 
a material or physical phenomenon — or, to be less radical, that if the 
mind should be somewhat different from it then the difference cannot 
be of great importance” (CR. 331). 

Just as King Midas reduced what he touched to gold, so Dr. Popper 
reduces what he discusses to nonsense. Dialectical materialism appears 
to him so absurd only because of the utter absurdity of his exposition 
of “the philosophy of identity”. 

An impartial consideration of the logical character of category- 
statements (of which the philosophy of dialectical materialism consists) 
will show how and why they are at one and the same time “laws of 
thought” (not, of course, in the sense of psychological laws but of 
“normative” laws) and true of the objective world. This has nothing 
whatever to do either with any Hegelian notion of the identity of 
“the rational and the real”, not with any Dr. Popperite notion (for it 
certainly is not a Marxist or materialist one) that “the mind is also a 
physical phenomenon”, or that the distinction between mental and 
physical phenomena “cannot be of great importance”. 

Let us consider once more the stock example of the dialectical law 
or category-statement about quality and quantity. This is “a law of 
thought” — not, of course, in the sense that it states a psychological 
law to the effect that whenever one thinks of a qualitative change one 
must think of a quantitative one, as whenever Mrs. Shandy thought 
of the clock being wound up “the thoughts of some other things 
unavoidably popped into her head” — but in the sense that it states a 
general principle of how to connect the qualitative and quantitative 
aspects of reality. It is also “a law of the objective world”, inasmuch 
as quantitative and qualitative changes take place whether we are 
thinking of them or not, and are connected in the way stated in the 
law. This law can in fact be expressed equally well either way round : 


124 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


one can say that qualitative and quantitative changes are connected, 
and therefore we should always think of them as connected; or that 
we find a necessary connection between the categories of quality and 
quantity, and therefore qualitative and quantitative changes are 
connected. And the same goes for category-statements in general. 

These sorts of stated connections are discovered in the objective 
world — and they certainly would be fancy ones and not real unless 
they were there discovered. They are “abstracted”, just as Engels said. 
And having been so abstracted they are formulated as “laws of 
thought” and tested, not as empirical laws are tested but as category- 
statements are tested — as Engels also implied when he wrote about 
“the science of thought and its laws”. Exactly as Engels said, materialist 
dialectics is “the science of interconnections” or (in his slightly Pick- 
wickian use of the word “motion”) “the science of the laws of motion 
both of the external world and of human thought”. Exactly as 
Lenin said, dialectics is “a law of cognition and a law of the objective 
world”. 

It has often been considered puzzling that by a process of thinking, 
of combining and recombining concepts, we should be able to arrive 
at conclusions which are practically reliable — that by working out in 
our heads what is going to happen we should arrive at a conclusion 
duly verified by what does happen. For example, if an artificial 
satellite is put into orbit we can, simply by calculations, know where 
it is to be found at any moment of time. Is it not strange that things 
should actually and regularly behave according to our ideas of them? 

According to Hegel's . “philosophy of identity” the only possible 
explanation for such a state of affairs is that the material world was 
created by a divine intelligence. Material things correspond to ideas 
of them because they were created in accordance with ideas. And this 
is, indeed, the fundamental standpoint of “objective idealism”. It is a 
sophisticated version of the old “argument from design” by which 
theologians sought to prove the existence of God. How extraordinary 
that the grass feeds the cow and the cow's digestive processes turn it 
into milk to feed us ! This could only happen because God designed it 
that way! But there is another explanation. The cow evolved by a 
process of natural selection in an environment where grass was growing 
and when people came to live in such places they found in the cow an 
animal which they could learn to domesticate as a source of food. 
Similarly, if our ideas correspond to things outside us, there is another 
explanation than that things were specially created to correspond to 


THE NECESSITY OF DIALECTICS 


125 


ideas. It is that we learned by trial and error to make our ideas corre- 
spond to things, because unless they did so our ideas would be useless 
to us, and worse than useless. 

The point of the materialist “philosophy of identity” was put in a 
very clear and simple way by Engels, in Chapter 3 of Anti-Duhring. 
Puzzles arise, he said, from “accepting ‘consciousness*, ‘reasoning*, as 
something given ... in contrast to being, to nature. If this were so, 
it must seem extremely remarkable that consciousness and nature, 
thinking and being, the laws of thought and the laws of nature, should 
be so closely in correspondence. But if the further question is raised: 
what then are thought and consciousness, and whence they come, it 
becomes apparent that they are products of the human brain and that 
man himself is a product of nature, which has been developed in and 
along with its environment; whence it is self-evident that the products 
of the human brain, being in the last analysis also products of nature, 
do not contradict the rest of nature but are in correspondence with it.** 

There is neither inconsistency nor any other sort of “absurdity** in 
the dialectical materialist “philosophy of identity’*. The so-called 
“philosophy of identity” certainly appeared a rather odd one in the 
writings of Hegel, when he asserted that categories existed eternally 
in the realm of the Absolute Idea and were materialised in processes 
in space and time. There is nothing at all odd in it, as propounded by 
Marx. As he explained, “the ideal is nothing else than the material 
world reflected by the human mind and translated into forms of 
thought”. So since the categories of thought are abstracted from the 
material world, and reflect it, there is nothing surprising in universal 
truth about the material world being correctly stated in the form of 
category-statements. By rationally demonstrating “the laws of thought” 
we demonstrate the laws of the objective process reflected in. thought. 

Dr. Popper represents “the philosophy of identity” and dialectical 
materialism as an absurd ideology, trapped out as a “reinforced 
dogmatism” so as to defend itself from every rational criticism. 
Closer examination shows, however, that it is a rational exercise in 
the principles of practical thinking, reinforced only by its demand for 
continual critical test. 

It was no accident at all that it was Marxism, the ideology of the 
modern working-class movement and of communism, which first 
developed the consistent criticism of all idealism and metaphysics, 
found the basis for “the science of thought and its laws”, and demanded 
that every statement and every principle used to guide human practice 


126 


TOWARDS AN OPEN PHILOSOPHY 


should be critically tested and never accepted on authority. It is true 
that there have been, and still emerge from the woodwork, exception- 
ally “orthodox” Marxists who like to set up texts as authorities, and 
consider it detrimental to Marxism that these texts should ever be 
tested (since to test is to question), and still more so that any develop- 
ment of Marxist ideas should take place. But the aim of the eman- 
cipation of humanity from exploitation, and the advance towards 
communism, demands that everything should be tested, and that 
ideas should be continually developed — for its success demands a grasp 
of things as they are, and not as someone may have said they are. 
The true militant is always questioning. He will allow himself to be 
imposed on by no dogmas, whether of the “right” or of the “left”: 
for they are all blinkers preventing him from taking stock of the 
world around. 

And now we may pass on to see how the principles of dialectical 
materialism apply to the understanding of society, of human life and 
human needs, and of the means to satisfy human needs. What sort of 
dogmatism and accompanying misdirection of human affairs does it 
produce? 


PART TWO 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


I 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 

I. THE DOGMATISM OF HISTORICISM 

Historical materialism, the Marxist theory of man and society, is the 
application to social problems of die general theory of dialectical 
materialism. And since dialectical materialism enjoins us to study 
things in their real changes and interconnections, the conclusions of 
historical materialism about social affairs, about the laws of social 
development, and about what we can do now to solve the pressing 
problems of contemporary society, are reached as a result of doing 
precisely that. 

Having stigmatised the general philosophy of Marxism as “rein- 
forced dogmatism”, Dr. Popper proceeds to explain how tills general 
dogmatic approach produces the particular form of dogmatism which 
he finds characteristic of Marx’s social theories — the dogmatism of 
“historicism”. He presumes, reasonably enough, that dogma produces 
dogma — so that with an absurdly dogmatic philosophy there goes an 
absurdly dogmatic theory of man and society. Just as dialectical 
materialism allegedly replaces the scientific study of the different 
aspects of real processes by a dogma that the process as a whole must 
go through the dialectical sequence of “thesis-antithesis-synthesis”, so 
does Marx’s historicism replace the scientific study of social affairs 
by the dogma that society must necessarily pass through a pre-ordained 
dialectical progress from primitive communism through class-society 
to the final communist millennium. But just as Dr. Popper’s inter- 
pretation of dialectical materialism as “reinforced dogmatism” and of 
“the dialectic” as a scheme of “thesis-antithesis-synthesis” is an absurd 
travesty, so is his interpretation of historical materialism as embodying 
what he calls “liistoricist” dogma. 

Dr. Popper defines historicism as “an approach to the social 
sciences which assumes that historical prediction is their principal 
aim, and . . . that this aim is attainable by discovering the ‘rhythms’ 
or the ‘patterns’, the ‘laws’ or the ‘trends’ that underlie the evolution 
of history” (PH. 3). Marx, he assures us, was “a famous historicist” 
(PH. 8). 

Why should one not aim at “historical prediction”? The point is 


130 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


that the historical predictions engaged in by historicists are entirely 
unlike the more modest predictions normally made by the sciences. 
For “ordinary predictions in science are conditional. They assert that 
certain changes (say, of the temperature of water in a kettle) will be 
accompanied by other changes (say, the boiling of the water).” 
Historicist predictions, on the other hand, are “unconditional historical 
prophecies” (Cll. 339). 

Thus historicism considers it “the task of the social sciences to 
furnish us with long-term historical prophecies” (i-OS. 3). It ceases 
to be a science and becomes “a wider philosophical scheme . . . the 
view that the story of mankind has a plot, and that if we can succeed 
in unravelling this plot, we shall hold the key to the future” (CR. 338). 
“Historicism is out to find the Path in which mankind is destined 
to walk” (2-OS. 269). 

Historicism has its own method for “unravelling the plot” and 
discovering the destined “Path”. This is the historical method. “The 
way of obtaining knowledge of social institutions ... is to study its 
[sic] history” (2-OS. 37). “We can obtain knowledge of social 
entities . . . only ... by studying social changes” (2-OS. 7). To know 
what is destined to happen in society one must study the origins and 
development of society, and so discover the “rhythms, patterns, laws 
and trends” which are at work and which will infallibly determine 
the future. 

And historicism has also its practical political application. The 
historicist tries “to understand the laws of historical development. If 
he succeeds in this, he will, of course, be able to predict future develop- 
ments. He might then put politics on a solid basis, and give us practical 
advice by telling us which political actions are likely to succeed or 
likely to fail” (i-OS. 8). “Sociological study should help reveal the 
political future, and . . . could thereby become the foremost instrument 
of far-sighted practical politics” (PH. 42). 

Marx, then, as “a famous historicist”, studied social changes with 
a view to making “unconditional prophecies”. Regardless of the fact 
that genuine science can make only “conditional predictions”, Marx 
thought that his “philosophical scheme” could “put politics on a 
solid basis”. He thought he knew what was fated to happen, and could 
base politics on preparing for it. 

Having thus charged Marx and Marxists with the fallacies of 
historicism, Dr. Popper proceeds to bring three more charges of 
theoretical misdemeanour, which he expounds as companion errors 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 131 

which go with historicist dogma. These are “essentialism”, “holism , ’ 
and “utopianism”. 

“Historicism” is tied up with “essentialism”. For the belief in 
“unconditional historical prophecies”, incompatible with genuine 
science, is dependent on the belief that the “essences” of things unfold 
themselves in an inevitable historical development, so that if one can 
but discover “the essence” one infallibly knows what is going to 
happen. “It is argued that the task of social science is to understand 
and explain such sociological entities as the state, economic action, 
the social group, etc., and that this can be done only by penetrating 
into their essences” (PH.30). 

“I use the name methodological essentialism,” writes Dr. Popper, 
with polysyllabic orotundity, “to characterise the view . . . that it 
is the task of pure knowledge or ‘science’ to discover and to describe 
the true nature of things, i.e. their hidden reality or essence” (i-OS. 3 1). 
According to essentialism, “the best, the truly scientific theories, 
describe the ‘essences’ or the ‘essential natures’ of things — the realities 
which lie behind the appearances” (CR. 104). 

The essence (so Dr. Popper explains the doctrine of “essentialism” 
and its connection with “historicism”) reveals itself in a certain pattern 
of development. For “in order to become real or actual, the essence 
must unfold itself in change” (2-OS. 8). Thus “applying this principle 
to sociology we are led to the conclusion that the essence or the real 
character of a social group can reveal itself, and be known, only 
through its history” (PH. 33). By studying the historical pattern of 
development of society, therefore, one penetrates to the essence of 
society — and having grasped the essence one can then understand the 
necessity of that particular pattern of development, and can infallibly 
predict its continuation. “Change, by revealing what is hidden in 
the undeveloped essence, can only make apparent the essence, the 
potentialities, the seeds, which from the beginning have inhered in 
the changing object. This doctrine leads to the historicist idea of an 
historical fate or an inescapable essential destiny” (2-OS. 7). 

Being guilty of historicism, then, Marx and Marxists could not 
but be also guilty of essentialism. Marxism means that the inescapable 
destiny of man in society is predetermined by the social essence of 
man. By studying human history one can discover what this essence 
is, and so acquire the power of making unconditional prophecies. 

Error, like crime, has its own crazy logic; and Dr. Popper goes 
on to explain that, once guilty of historicism and essentialism, Marxism 


132 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


could not but degenerate further into “holism” and “utopianism”. 
One would almost suppose that Dr. Popper imagines himself digging 
into the very depths of the essence of Marxism. A fine lot of nonsense 
he digs up, and no wonder, for he buried it all there himself. 

“The strongest element in the alliance between historicism and 
utopianism is, undoubtedly, the holistic approach which is common 
to both,” writes Dr. Popper (PH. 74). “Historicism is interested in 
the development, not of aspects of social life, but of ‘society as a 
whole’.” 

We must study “society as a whole”, says the essentialist-historicist, 
and study particular “aspects of social life” only as their development 
is determined by that of the whole. The trouble with this injunction, 
says Dr. Popper, is that “if we wish to study a tiring, we are bound 
to select certain aspects of it. It is not possible for us to observe or 
to describe a whole piece of the world, or a whole piece of nature; 
in fact, not even the smallest whole piece may be so described, since 
all description is necessarily selective” (PH. 77). It is not the develop- 
ment of the whole which determines that of particular aspects, but 
the development of particular aspects, and their complex interaction, 
which determines the development of the whole. 

Historicism and essentialism, demanding a “holistic approach”, 
become thereby involved in “utopianism”. For “holists not only plan 
to study the whole society by an impossible method, they also plan 
to control and reconstruct our society ‘as a whole’ ” (PH. 79). And 
that is utopianism. Thus Marx’s “unconditional historical prophecies” 
about the development of “society as a whole” became a “utopian 
blueprint”. “He predicted, and tried actively to further, a development 
culminating in an ideal utopia” (PH. 74). “Marx saw the real task of 
scientific socialism in the annunciation of the impending socialist 
millennium” (2-OS. 86). 

But unfortunately, utopianism, based on “an impossible method”, 
can never lead to the realisation of utopia. “Even with the best inten- 
tions of making heaven on earth it only succeeds in making it a hell — 
that hell which man alone prepares for his fellow-men” (i-OS. 168). 
Marx’s theoretical misdemeanours have encouraged Communists, 
Dr. Popper subsequently explains, in their nefarious work of suppres- 
sing individuality, instigating violence and tyranny, and perpetuating 
a “closed society”. 

We had best remember now that, with Dr. Popper, we are still in 
Wonderland, where everything is queer and the meanings of words 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


133 


get twisted. As soon as the charge was read the King of Hearts told 
the jury “Consider your verdict”. But that was too much, even for 
the White Rabbit. “Not yet ! Not yet !” the Rabbit hastily interrupted. 
“There’s a great deal to come before that!” There is indeed a great 
deal to be said on the topics expounded in Dr. Popper’s charge. But 
to say it we must leave Wonderland and take a look at how things 
are in the real world, and cease to discuss general philosophical 
principles but rather apply them in the concrete analysis of concrete 
conditions. 


2. MEN MAKE THEIR OWN HISTORY 

According to Marx: “Men make their own history, but they do not 
make it just as they please; they do not make it under circumstances 
chosen by themselves, but under circumstances directly encountered, 
given and transmitted from the past” ( The Eighteenth Brumaire of 
Louis Bonaparte , Ch. 1). 

In other words, men make their own history by their own actions — 
no “fate” makes it for them. But men in their actions respond to 
whatever circumstances they find themselves in. They directly 
encounter circumstances given and transmitted from the past — that is 
to say, created for them by past generations; change these by their 
actions ; then again respond to the changed circumstances ; and so on, 
for as long as mankind endures. 

This may be called “reinforced dogmatism”, but it sounds more like 
reinforced common sense. What are some of the implications, as 
regards human action and its possibilities? 

It means, in the first place, that while men make their own history, 
what they can and cannot do at any place and time depends not 
simply on their own desires and decisions but on the circumstances 
in which they are placed. It is in this sense that they do not make 
their history “just as they please”. Obviously, as Marx said, people 
cannot choose their own circumstances — one does not choose to be 
bom, nor to be born into one set of circumstances rather than another. 
Choice applies to what to do in whatever circumstances one finds 
oneself; and the circumstances limit the choice of action. But because 
of this, circumstances not only limit what men can do, but condition 
what in practice they want to do; people’s desires, aims and ideals 
are conditioned by their circumstances; what one effectively wants 
to do, or would like to see done, takes its start from the circumstances 


134 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


in which the wish is bom. It means, too, that men’s ways of thinking — 
the scope of their ideas, the ways they conceive of themselves and of 
the world about them — are conditioned by circumstances. And lastly, 
it is obvious enough that, while men may choose and decide what 
to do in given circumstances, they cannot choose or decide what 
effects their actions, once embarked upon, are going to have. Men 
can act with the intention of bringing about certain effects; whether 
these effects actually take place, or whether something quite different 
happens, does not depend on the intention of the action but on the 
action itself, and the circumstances in which it was performed. 

It was on no deeper or darker philosophical presuppositions than 
these that Marx and Engels proceeded to consider how, in actual fact, 
“men make their own history”. 

At the start of their first mature work on this subject, The German 
Ideology , they remarked that “the first premise of all human history 
is the existence of living human individuals. Thus the first fact to be 
established is the physical organisation of these individuals and their 
consequent relation to the rest of nature”. Having established that 
fact, they went on to inquire how the innumerable actions of innumer- 
able human individuals could come to make human history. 

The “physical organisation” of human individuals is, of course, a 
consequence of the natural evolution of species; and “their relation to 
the rest of nature” is a further consequence. The unique physical 
characteristics of the human species, namely, the upright stance, hands 
and brain, lead to their unique relation to the rest of nature, namely, 
obtaining their requirements from nature by means of social produc- 
tion. Human psychology is, then, a further consequence — the product 
of individuals with this physical organisation living in society. 

In order, then, to carry on their relation with the rest of nature — in 
other words, in order to live, since organisms live only by obtaining 
their requirements from nature — people devise instruments of pro- 
duction, learn the skills to use them, and enter into social relations of 
production. They evolve their social mode of production, which 
consists of employing certain forces of production and instituting 
definite relations of production in order to deploy the social pro- 
ductive forces and distribute the product. 

This is how the past generations create the circumstances with which 
the next generations have to cope. What they do, by their social 
activity in the physical environment, is in the first place to equip their 
successors with certain forces of production and provide them with a 


fflSTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


135 


physical environment changed and refashioned in various ways by the 
past application of those forces of production. In the second place, they 
setde them in definite relations of production within which the forces 
of production are deployed. Finally, they hand on to them a whole 
heritage of institutions, customs and ways of life, knowledge, ideas 
and culture, and leave them to continue a whole set of undecided 
conflicts and arguments and uncompleted activities. 

In the study of history the successors look back on how the pre- 
decessors managed to make things turn out the way they did — at 
least, that is how history must be regarded if its study is to prove of any 
practical advantage, and that is how Marx and Engels evidently 
regarded it. “All history must be studied afresh, the conditions of 
existence of the different formations of society must be examined in 
detail,” wrote Engels to C. Schmidt (August 5, 1890). And he told his 
correspondent that “our conception of history is above all a guide to 
study”. The materialist conception of history is a guide to study in the 
same way that any other scientific conception is a guide to study. Our 
conception of human physiology, for example, is a guide to study, 
because it tells us what to look for in order to be able to explain how 
the phenomena are brought about — in a case of epilepsy, say, to look 
for the brain lesion responsible for the condition, rather than for the 
evil spirit. And so with the materialist conception of history. Marx 
and Engels pointed out that, whatever people do in society, they can 
only do it on the basis of being mutually involved in a mode of 
production — for without that, they could not live or do anything at 
all. As they change their forces of production, and consequently create 
problems for themselves the solution of which requires changed 
relations of production, so do people modify in various ways the 
character of all the rest of their activity. 

It is because people live by social production that human societies 
have a history different in kind from, say, the history of a community 
of ants. Ants could not, of course, study their own history in any case, 
since they are not physically equipped for studying. However, out- 
side observers could quite well study the history of a" given community 
of ants, and in it would be recorded not only the common round of 
hatching out the eggs, and so on, but also such “historical” events as 
floods and other catastrophes, wars with neighbouring anthills, and 
great migrations of ants. It is a shortcoming of some human historians 
that they study the history of men just as though men were nothing 
but a talkative kind of ants. But it is not only speech and the element of 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


136 

individual consciousness or purposive activity that distinguish men. 
Human history differs from the history of ants by exhibiting a type of 
historical development which is peculiarly human; and this is due to 
the social production by which men live. The mode of production 
changes. Ants always get their living in the same way; but not so 
human beings. People acquire new productive forces, and change 
their relations of production. And this introduces a quite new factor 
into human history. Human history is the history of how men acquired 
and used forces of production, and adapted their relations of pro* 
duction to the requirements of developing their forces of production ; 
it is the history of how men did this, and what activities, difficulties, 
defeats and victories, constructive enterprises and wars, they in- 
volved themselves in doing it. 

Dr. Popper explains that the historicist “sees the individual as a 
pawn, as a somewhat insignificant instrument in the general develop- 
ment of mallkind ,, (i-OS. 7-8). But the materialist conception of 
history, as a way of studying and understanding human history, does 
not mean, as Marx and Engels themselves made abundantly clear, that 
history is made in any other way than by the activities of human 
individuals. It does not mean that what individuals may think and 
do counts for nothing, that they are all mere “pawns”, and that what 
alone counts is the inexorable development of “the different forma- 
tions of society”. For to talk about the “social formation” is simply 
to talk about how individuals, having socially acquired certain pro- 
ductive forces, involved themselves in certain production relations. 
What it does mean is that, to see how the circumstances of the new 
generation were transmitted to them by the old, we have to see how 
the forces of production were developed and how the relations of 
production were managed; and that to see what the generation can 
or cannot do in such circumstances, and how their practical outlook is 
consequently generated, we have to see what can or cannot be done by 
way of preserving or changing both the relations of production and 
the forces of production deployed within them. 

The Marxist materialist conception of history is, then, the scientific 
conception of how the old people bring into being the circumstances 
which the young people are born into and have to cope with. Like 
other scientific conceptions in other spheres, it is of great practical 
value. In the first place, it assists us in making an accurate assessment of 
just what our circumstances are, and dispelling illusions about them. 
In the second place, by the historical study of how social circumstances 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


137 


are brought about we can reach conclusions as to what sort of things 
can and cannot be done to cope with them. 

3. HISTORICAL PREDICTION 

How far, we may now ask, does the study of history enable us to 
predict the future? And what sort of predictions does it enable us to 
make? 

Marxism means making “unconditional long-term historical 
prophecies”, Dr. Popper tells us; and the “principal aim” of Marxists 
in. studying history is to deduce such prophecies from it. 

The principal aim of Marxists in studying history is not to prophesy 
but to understand, and to direct practical action in the light of under- 
standing. “Men make their own history”, said Marx. We study 
history to try to understand how we make it, and consequently how 
to go on making it without illusions that it can be made in some other 
way than that in which it is in fact made. 

Obviously, so far as the past is concerned, history is not predictive 
but descriptive and explanatory. We do not study the events of, say, 
a thousand years ago in order to predict die events of, say, nine 
hundred years ago — for when we study the earlier events we already 
know what the subsequent events were. We study the past sequence 
of events in order to try to discover explanatory generalisations about 
how later events issue from earlier ones. Marx's discovery was that to 
explain the historical sequence we must always, first, examine the 
mode of production and how it develops, and second examine how 
people acted socially in order to adapt their production relations, and 
their institutions and ideas, to their forces of production. 

This descriptive-explanatory approach to the study of history does 
not represent history as the automatic consequence of the operation of 
inexorable “laws” — like, for example, a closed mechanical system in 
which a later state inexorably ensues from the earlier by the operation 
of the laws of mechanics. It is often said that, for the materialist con- 
ception of history, everything happens “according to laws”. If that 
means that the materialist conception of history formulates explanatory 
generalisations about how human society always develops, well and 
good; that is just what the materialist conception of history does do. 
But to suggest that there are “laws” governing human actions such 
that, given certain circumstances, all the ensuing events are uniquely 
determined by those laws, is obviously mere empty talk. What are 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


138 

these laws? Where are they stated? Where is their verification to be 
found? You can read right through the historical works of Marx, and 
of all other competent Marxist historians (and, indeed, of all reputable 
historians, whether Marxists or not), and not meet with any formula- 
tions of any such laws. Such a theory of “laws’’ is in fact a hangover 
from the days when it was thought that the entire material world was 
a closed mechanical system — and it has, needless to say, very little in 
common with the scientific ideas of dialectical and historical material- 
ism. It has to be given up because no one can discover such laws, and 
the idea that there must be such laws is a groundless dogma. 

The historical works of Marx himself, and of Marxist historians 
(as can easily be verified by reading them), do not proceed by trying 
to show how the later events necessarily followed from the earlier ones 
in accordance with inexorable laws, but by showing how people, in 
the development of social production, became involved in certain 
contradictions and problems, and how they acted to resolve those 
contradictions and problems. And the basis is always the adaptation 
of relations of production to forces of production. 

It is to this guiding idea that the materialist conception of history 
owes not only its descriptive-explanatory power as regards the past, 
but its prescriptive power as regards the present. It is a guide to study 
of the present in its emergence from the past, so as to conclude what 
are the historical issues of today and what best to do to develop social 
relations in order to plan social production to satisfy human needs. 
Just that is the object of Communist theory and practice. 

Any social situation contains certain historical issues, or historical 
tasks. And these may be defined by the historian objectively, irrespec- 
tive of the particular terms in which the individuals of the time, 
through their ideological agencies, may present them to themselves. 
“Just as our opinion of an individual is not based on what he thinks of 
himself, so can we not judge of . . . a period ... by its own conscious- 
ness; on the contrary, this consciousness must be explained rather from 
the contradictions of material life, from the existing conflict between 
the social forces of production and the relations of production”, wrote 
Marx, in the Preface to Critique of Political Economy . 

It is not, as everyone knows, the historian’s object to search out and 
record every single event of the past. He is primarily concerned with 
the “historical” events — though just what makes an event historical 
is a point not clarified by all historians. For Marxist historians, the key 
to understanding any period is to discover the main historical issues of 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


139 


that period — and these proceed from and relate to the development 
of forces of production and the adaptation to it of production relations 
and social institutions and ideas. Thus, for a Marxist, the question of 
whether King Valoroso should award the Order of the Cucumber to 
his son-in-law. Prince Bulbo, was hardly an historical issue — even 
though the Court Journal, and historians who base their histories on 
court journals, might regard it as an issue of great importance. The 
historical events — die ones that constitute, so to speak, the fabric of 
history — are those public events which mark a response to historical 
issues and affect the issue. But of course, in a certain sense, any event 
is of interest to historians, because even the most trivial ones illustrate 
the sort of people there were, and their habits, and so are relevant to 
understanding historical events ; and often an accidental concatenation 
of small events can build up an effect which decisively alters the way 
issues are tackled. 

Looking at the overall development of human society from the 
earliest times, Marxism sees it as the progressive posing and tackling 
of a series of issues stemming from the development of productive 
forces, and the adaptation to that development of the relations of 
production. In many cases, as Marx made clear in his Pre-capitalist 
Economic Formations , this adaptation has been unsuccessful, and has led 
to a dead end rather than to further progressive development. The 
thread of human progress can be traced through those communities 
which successfully adapted their relations of production to the require- 
ments of developing their productive forces. The overall history of 
human society is, then, “a law-governed process” in the sense that it 
exemplifies this general law of development. It is not, and could not be, 
a “law-governed process” in the strict-determinist sense that there are 
pre-ordained laws wliich allow nothing to happen except what does 
happen. 

With human affairs, as with other things, a conception of how they 
go enables us to make predictions about future events. But the test of 
the adequacy or otherwise of a conception of how tilings go does not 
lie (as Dr. Popper seems sometimes to suggest) only in waiting to find 
out whether or not predictions are verified. We also test the concep- 
tion of how tilings go by examining the record of how they have 
gone — and “refutations” may be as readily sought in the past as 
awaited in the future. For this reason we can always claim that scientific 
conceptions are pretty well established by what has happened already, 
without having to join Dr. Popper in regarding them all as mere 


140 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


“conjectures” about the future which may well be falsified at any 
moment. This applies to our conceptions of how, say, physical and 
chemical processes go — and also to our conceptions of how social 
processes go. The warranted assertibility (to adopt a useful phrase 
invented and misused by the pragmatists) of our conceptions of how 
things go depends on the thoroughness with which we have investi- 
gated how they have gone. 

Our conceptions are further tested and, if need be, modified, by the 
verification or falsification of the predictions they enable us to make. 
The purpose of predictions is not, however, simply to test our con- 
ceptions. It is to direct our actions. For unless we made predictions 
we could never direct our actions at all. For example, we could not 
direct the making of tea unless we could predict that water boils when 
heated, and that boiling water poured onto dried tea-leaves produces 
tea. In directing our actions, therefore, it is important to possess con- 
ceptions the assertibility of which is pretty well warranted already, so 
that the predictions derived from them may be acted on with a reason- 
able degree of confidence and not be regarded as only “conjectures”. 
To furnish such a conception of human affairs is the aim and claim 
of the materialist conception of history. 

We can and always do rely on being able to make a whole number 
of predictions to direct human activities. We rely on being able to say: 
“If A happens, B will happen”, or “Since A has happened, B will 
happen unless C intervenes”, and so on. We rely, in other words, on 
what Dr. Popper calls “conditional predictions”. These may often be 
usefully expressed, as he has said, in the form of prohibitions: “A B 
cannot happen; hence since A has happened, B will not happen”. Ex- 
perience and study warrant us in making many such predictions about 
physical, chemical and biological processes ; and (as practically 
everyone, including Dr. Popper, agrees) experience and study warrant 
us in making many such predictions about human activities too. 

Does the materialist conception of history claim a warrant, however, 
for any other kinds of predictions — long-term “unconditional” ones, 
as Dr. Popper expresses it? Does Marxism propose to justify statements 
of the form: “So and so will happen, regardless”? Such statements are, 
as Dr. Popper rightly says, foreign to the natural sciences. Does 
Marxism unscientifically propose to introduce them into the social 
sciences? 

Marx’s discovery of the general “law of historical development” 
does lead to a “long-term” prediction. And Dr. Popper rightly says 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION I4I 

that this long-term prediction is regarded by Marxists as of very great 
theoretical and practical importance. The logic of this long-term pre- 
diction is quite simple. In order to go on developing their forces of 
production people have always to adapt their production relations to 
their productive forces. Hence if the present-day forces of production 
go on being developed, the relations of production will be adapted to 
them. The existing capitalist relations fetter production. If production 
is to go on developing these fetters will be removed and socialist and, 
later, communist relations of production established. 

Obviously, this long-term prediction depends not only on “the 
general law” but also on the hypothesis that capitalist relations fetter 
production and that the removal of the fetters of private appropriation 
equals social appropriation. The latter, less general, hypothesis, is 
verified in terms of contemporary history, just as the more general 
hypothesis is verified in terms of universal history. So what is there 
“unscientific” in the consequent long-term prediction? It would be 
absurd to say that only “short-term” predictions are scientific. Scientific 
thought ventures on long-term predictions in other spheres covered 
by scientific hypothesis, so why not in the sphere of human activity? 
Of course, if hypotheses are found to be wrong, then the consequential 
predictions, whether short-term or long-term, have to be modified. 
But in so far as confidence in the hypotheses is warranted, so is con- 
fidence in predictions, long-term and short-term. This goes for Marx’s 
hypotheses like anyone else’s. Of course, those who have a stake in 
maintaining the capitalist system do not like Marx’s long-term pre- 
diction of its displacement. But that is a complication which merely 
introduces extra-scientific disputes into a scientific question. Scienti- 
fically speaking, the logic of Marx’s long-term prediction is im- 
peccable. 

Dr. Popper does not, of course, deny that long-term prediction is 
sometimes permissible in the sciences. But he maintains that the 
conditions for it are not present in the social sciences. “Long-term 
prophecies”, he writes (CR. 339-40), “can be derived from scientific 
conditional predictions only if they apply to systems which can be 
described as well-isolated, stationary, and recurrent. These systems 
are very rare in nature; and modern society is surely not one of 
them. . . . Society is changing, developing. This development is not, 
in the main, repetitive.” 

Of course society develops, and the development is not repetitive. 
That does not mean that there cannot possibly be a discoverable law of 


142 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


development. On the contrary, Marx discovered the law — the law of 
the adaptation of production relations to productive forces. And 
clearly, if this law describes the way society develops, then the deve- 
lopment is non-repetitive. Non-repetitive development does not mean 
that there is no law, nor that the law cannot be formulated in such a 
way that from the analysis of the present stage of development a 
prediction of the next stage can be made. Evidently, therefore, Dr. 
Popper is mistaken in his dogmatic and unsupported statement that 
long-term prediction can apply only to “well-isolated, stationary and 
recurrent systems” . 

His argument depends on a simple confusion between long-term 
prediction and what he calls “unconditional” prophecy. It is quite 
true that only in the case of a “well-isolated, stationary and recurrent 
system” (“very rare in nature”, as Dr. Popper rightly says) could it be 
guaranteed that no outside or non-recurrent factor was ever going to 
interfere in the working of the laws normally governing the system. 
Society is not a system of that kind, and Marx’s long-term predictions 
about society only predict that die continued development of produc- 
tion will bring socialism — because, in the long term, die condition 
for it is the removal of the fetters of private appropriation. People have 
always so far managed to overcome, eventually, obstacles to the 
continued development of their productive forces; and if they go on 
doing so, then socialism will come, and only if socialism comes will 
they be able to go on doing so. That is the prediction. It is conditional, 
not unconditional. It does not say that nodiing can ever possibly 
prevent the advent of socialism. On die contrary, if people should 
destroy their productive forces, along with most of the human race, 
in a nuclear war, 'then many nations may never achieve socialism. 
Again, an invasion of hostile forces from outer space might prevent 
our achieving socialism. We may diink the latter catastrophe unlikely, 
and have confidence in our ability to prevent die former, or even to 
cope with its consequences if it happens — and so live in confident 
expectation that the long-term prediction of socialism will come about, 
because examination of the existing state of affairs shows that the 
conditions for its being brought about are present. That is the practical 
attitude of Communists. But it does not turn long-term scientifically- 
based prediction into unconditional prophecy. 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


143 


4. PREDICTION, PROBABILITY AND INTENT 

The long-term prediction of socialism is a prediction about human 
actions and the results of human actions. In this it differs, obviously, 
from predictions about the operations of natural forces. As Engels, 
perhaps rather tritely, remarked ( Ludwig Feuerbach , Ch. 4) : “In nature 
there are only blind, unconscious agencies acting upon one another. 
In the history of society, on the other hand, the actors are all endowed 
with consciousness, are men acting with deliberation or passion, 
working towards definite goals; nothing happens without a conscious 
purpose, without an intended aim.” The long-term historical predic- 
tion is, then, a prediction about what “men acting with deliberation or 
passion, working towards definite goals” will do, and what results 
will accrue from their doing it. 

It is sometimes suggested that just because men act “with deliberation 
or passion” it is impossible to make any predictions about them. Each 
man decides what to do for himself, or acts from his own private 
passions, so no over-all predictions can be made. That is absurd. We 
all constantly make predictions of the form: “In such and such circum- 
stances, such and such people will act in such and such a way, and such 
and such results will follow”, and if we could not rely on any such 
predictions we could not manage our social lives. 

Predictions about human actions do not imply that human beings 
act, and act on one another, in the same way as non-human or “natural” 
agencies do. They act deliberately, they are moved by passions, they 
form intentions and set themselves goals — and it is these sorts of 
actions, and the results of these sorts of actions, that we predict. 

For example, when a sufficient number of people are brought 
together as wage-workers they start talking together about how to 
improve their conditions, form organisations and formulate common 
demands. They always do this, and we can predict that they will. 
Such a prediction does not imply that the individual workmen are 
“pawns”, whose deliberations and passions count for nothing. On the 
contrary, the prediction is a prediction of their deliberations and 
passions. In such circumstances enough workmen w r ill feel passionately 
fed up and voluntarily organise as to constitute an effective organisa- 
tion which can coerce or at least discount the opposition of those who 
feel contented and do not voluntarily organise. 

Such predictions are (as the above example makes evident) based on 
estimates of probabilities of what will happen as a result of the inter- 


144 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


action of a large number of interdependent variables. The same is true 
of predictions about the behaviour of single individuals. When we 
predict what a certain person will do, we are estimating the probable 
outcome of all the various motivations and counter-motivations he 
experiences. 

Nearly all predictions, whether they concern human beings or not, 
are similarly based on estimates of probability. Thus, for example, the 
prediction that a kettle of water placed on a fire will boil is (as modern 
science has shown) based on the estimate that more heat will pass from 
the fire into the kettle than from the kettle into the fire, and that when 
enough has passed the agitation of die molecules of water in the kettle 
will produce the phenomenon of boiling. Predictions about working- 
class organisation and other human activities depend on the same kind 
of estimates of probability. 

There is nothing especially uncertain or “conjectural” about such 
estimates. On the contrary, it is by such estimates that we guide our 
lives, and, if due care is exercised in arriving at them, they are extremely 
reliable. Such reliable estimates can be arrived at about our own 
actions, as well as about what goes on in the physical environment. 

In the interpretation of the past, it is precisely such estimates of 
probability that explain the overall progressive course of human 
history. Not all communities have developed their forces of produc- 
tion, but some have — and so a progressive overall development has 
taken place, with new relations of production adapted to new forces of 
production, up to humanity’s arrival at its present predicament. With 
so many people carrying on social production for such a long time, it 
was so probable as to be, practically speaking, inevitable that at least 
some would on occasion enter into favourable circumstances when 
they could improve on existing forces of production — and so the 
progressive development took place, and is likely to continue. This is 
the scientific explanation of human progress — what would probably 
happen happened. 

To explain why some particular development — the “classical” 
slave empire, say, or modern capitalism — took place exactly where, 
when and how it did, one has, of course, to ascertain a lot of relatively 
coincidental facts: if something else had happened earlier (as it well 
might), this development could have taken place somewhere else and 
in a different way. But overall it was so probable as to be practically 
inevitable that a great slave empire would develop somewhere, and 
that, later on, capitalism would develop. 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


145 


Moreover, when such developments take place they tend to be 
unique. This is because whoever achieves the development either 
prevents anyone else repeating it, or if others do follow suit the fact 
that it has been done already alters their circumstances and makes 
them do it differently. Thus, for example, the achievement of capital- 
ism in one set of countries prevented a similar development in regions 
which they colonised. Again, the head start which Britain gained in 
capitalist development affected the conditions in which Britain’s com- 
petitors had to operate. Again, the achievement of socialism in the 
U.S.S.R. affects the whole character of the road to socialism in the 
rest of the world. 

The same sort of considerations explain, incidentally, the role and 
the uniqueness of “great men”. When once one individual has come 
to perform a “great man” function, he deprives others of the chance 
of doing the same thing. Napoleon, for example, was unique, not only 
because of his individual personality, which impelled him to the top 
after the French Revolution, but because there could in any case be 
only one emperor of the French. 

In explaining social development and predicting its continuation, 
therefore, the materialist conception of history does not, as a scientific 
conception, need to invoke any inexorable “fate” or “destiny” 
brooding over human affairs and directing them. We conduct our 
affairs without that. And still the conduct of our affairs is, like other 
things, explicable and predictable. 

The same principles which explain how people acted in the past 
explain how they are acting now, and serve to predict how they will 
act in the future. Predictions about human affairs, however, very 
clearly differ from predictions about natural processes, as well as from 
explanations of past affairs, in that the people making the predictions 
are themselves agencies in the processes through which the predictions 
will be realised. To predict something which you yourself are going to 
do — or at least, if not you yourself individually, the people with whom 
you associate and with whose interests you identify your own — is 
equivalent to a statement of intent. For instance, to predict “It is going 
to rain” is simply to state what you expect to happen; but to predict, 
“I am going to put on my raincoat” is a statement of intent. You 
would not predict you would put on your raincoat if you did not 
intend to do so. 

In making such predictions, whether ones like “I shall put on my 
raincoat” or “We shall achieve socialism”, we rely on an analysis of 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


146 

the objective circumstances to which the predicted action is to be the 
response. If that analysis proved mistaken, the predicted action would 
either not take place, or, if it did, would not have the expected results. 
If, for example, my analysis of the weather proves mistaken, I shall 
either not put on my raincoat or, if I do, it will only weigh me down 
and not keep me dry. Again, the analysis of circumstances may be 
mistaken in such a way that the intention expressed is not in the 
circumstances a practicable one. For instance, if I had lost my raincoat, 
the prediction that I would put it on would not be fulfilled; in making 
the prediction I would have simply forgotten that I had lost the raincoat. 

In stating intentions, then, one generally reckons to have reasons 
(based on an analysis of circumstances) for considering the intention 
practical, and for considering that its fulfilment will bring certain 
advantages or avoid certain misfortunes. If one learned that the 
intention was not practical, or that it would not bring the expected 
advantage or avoid the feared misfortune, then one would abandon 
the intention and the prediction would not be fulfilled. 

Evidently, therefore, the fact that predictions about future human 
actions may also be statements of intent does not mean that such pre- 
dictions are not founded on an objective analysis of circumstances ; nor 
does the fact that such a prediction is founded on an analysis of circum- 
stances mean that the carrying out of the predicted action is done under 
the impulsion of fate, and not voluntarily to fulfil a stated intention. It 
is obvious that such predictions can be well founded; and also that, 
however well founded they are, they can only be fulfilled on condition 
that the people whose intentions are expressed in the prediction 
continue to try hard to carry out their intentions. 

The Marxist prediction about socialism exhibits all the above 
characteristics of a prediction which is also a statement of intent. 
In this it certainly differs from, say, an astronomer’s prediction of an 
eclipse. It likewise differs from certain other predictions about human 
affairs — for of course, not all such predictions contain this element of 
being a statement of intent. For example, when Louis XV of France 
made his famous prediction, “Apres moi la deluge” (a well-founded 
prediction which came true), he was simply stating what he expected 
other people to do; and the “fatalistic” character of his prediction was 
due to his (correct) opinion that he and his friends could not stop them 
doing it. Marx’s prediction about socialism, on the other hand, was 
also a statement of intent, and intended for adoption as a statement of 
intent; and the conditions for its realisation included the condition 


mSTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


147 


that it should be widely adopted as an intent, and stuck to — for 
otherwise, socialism would certainly not come about. It could only 
come about by people purposively struggling for it. On the basis of 
the same analysis of circumstances which made Marx voice the in- 
tention of socialism, he concluded that a sufficient number of people 
would adopt it. 

Obviously, this prediction by Marx includes features not to be 
found in such a simple prediction as “I shall put on my raincoat”, 
though it does have in common with the latter the feature of expres- 
sing an intention based on an objective analysis of circumstances. 
For Marx’s prediction predicted what other people were going to do. 
It is a “we” prediction, not an “I” prediction; and of course, every 
“we” prediction is also a “they” prediction. 

In this respect it may be compared with, say, a prediction made by 
the first Everest expedition that “Everest will eventually be climbed”. 
Such a prediction expresses an intention of climbing Everest, coupled 
with a conclusion of the practicability of eventually getting to the top 
and of the desirability of doing so. It relies also on the prediction, based 
on estimates of the probabilities of human actions, that a sufficient 
number of people will always want to get to the top of Everest, and 
will devote enough care to the preparation of adequate techniques as 
to ensure the eventual achievement. 

It may also be noted that the same prediction could be made by 
observers who had themselves no intention of climbing Everest. 
Those observers would note that the intention had been formed, that 
it was practicable, and that a sufficient number of people supported 
it as to ensure its eventual success. But that the prediction can be made 
on good grounds by mere observers does not make it fatalistic. For 
the prediction would never be realised unless there were people who 
intended to climb Everest and who adopted it as a statement of intent. 
Observers could have no conclusive grounds for predicting the 
climbing of Everest unless climbers intended to climb it and them- 
selves predicted, as a statement of their intention, that the climb would 
take place and go on taking place until they reached the top. True, in 
this example observers of the habits of climbers might venture to 
predict that Everest would eventually be climbed, even before any 
climbers had themselves formed the intention of climbing Everest and 
organised an expedition. All the same, the realisation of the prediction 
would depend on the climbers forming the intention of attempting 
that particular climb, and organising to achieve it. 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


148 

It may also be noted, in all these examples, that the objective analysis 
of circumstances on which such predictions are based includes, if the 
predictions are well-founded, a causal explanation of why the intention 
the fulfilment of which is predicted came to be formed and will gc on 
being held. Thus in the case of putting on a raincoat, for example, 
the explanation of the intention is that to go out in the prevailing rainy 
conditions tends to give one a cold. In the case of climbing Everest, 
the explanation of the intention is that climbers find it intolerable to 
be confronted with mountains they have not climbed. And in the case 
of socialism, the explanation of the intention is that under capitalist 
conditions a great many people find intolerable the fetters capitalist 
relations place on the satisfaction of human needs. 

These considerations show that Marx’s “long-term” prediction of 
socialism can claim, just like many simpler and shorter-term predic- 
tions, to be well founded on an objective analysis of circumstances. 
This analysis, is, by the nature of the case, complicated and difficult. 
It requires in practice to be continually developed and checked. And of 
course, if any part of it were shown to be quite wrong, then the 
foundation for the prediction would be weakened, if not destroyed. 
But as originally worked out by Marx, and continued by his successors, 
it does provide a very firm and sound foundation for the prediction of 
socialism. 

In the first place, the prediction is founded on recognition of the 
general law of social development — that production relations are 
adapted to productive forces. Secondly, it is founded on an investiga- 
tion of capitalist production relations and how they fetter productive 
forces. Thirdly, it is founded on the demonstration that socialised 
production, of the sort developed in modern industry, requires social 
appropriation — so that the only way to develop modern socialised 
production to meet social needs is to establish socialist relations of 
production. Fourthly, it is founded on an analysis of the class struggle 
which ensues from capitalist production relations, in which the in- 
tention of achieving socialism corresponds to the class interests of the 
majority of working people — so that there are good grounds to expect 
that in the long run the forces activated by that intention will grow 
stronger in comparison with those opposed to it. Fifthly, it is founded 
on a very practical working out of the principles of the strategy and 
tactics of the class struggle for socialism. 

So as Marx claimed all along, the scientific study of society, its 
history and how men make their own history, provides the foundation 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


149 


for a long-term prediction of socialism. This is not, however, like the 
predictions of astronomers who predict events which are going to 
happen irrespective of human intentions and strivings. From the 
nature of the case, being a prediction of the eventual outcome of a 
struggle in which the makers of the prediction take part, it has the 
characteristics of a political policy and a political propaganda. Marx 
himself cited very good reasons to consider the policy sound, and to 
persevere in it. And these very good reasons (provided they are stated 
properly) serve as very good propaganda for the policy. 

It is further evident from all this that the realisation of the prediction 
of socialism depends on the building of an organisation, activated by 
scientific socialist policy and with sufficient centralisation, unity and 
discipline as to function in a consciously controlled way — in short, 
on a political party of the working class. Marx himself made this very 
clear. And it was underlined by Lenin, especially in his pamphlet, 
What is to be done , where he pointed out that the merely “spontaneous* * 
behaviour of people demanding some improvement in their con- 
ditions could never result in socialism; for that, political organisation 
was required, activated by scientific socialist theory. 

Indeed, we cannot make well-founded long-term predictions about 
social events unless we can at the same time build effective organisation 
intended to carry them out. For without this, the people making the 
predictions would be like architects predicting the erection of some 
building without taking any steps to mobilise a labour force and 
provide it with building machinery. It is, indeed, for this very reason 
that, in the past (and also, for many of our fellow citizens, in the 
present), people have not been able to make well-founded long-term 
social predictions. For the sort of organisation necessary for carrying 
them out could not be projected. They have occasionally hazarded 
long-term predictions, but these were not well founded. Thus, for 
instance, no great confidence can be reposed in the sort of long-term 
predictions at present engaged in by various capitalist economic 
planning agencies if only because in the prevailing capitalist conditions 
the machinery does not exist and cannot be created for effectively 
controlling their realisation. 

The well-founded scientific long-term prediction of socialism 
propounded by Marx was thus a novelty in human affairs. This 
novelty was introduced by him (as one would expect such a novelty 
to have been introduced) when and only when the social conditions 
for its introduction were realised. The formation of the modern 


150 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


working class brought into being for the first time in history the basis 
for mass organisation which could effectively pursue a policy of bring- 
ing relations of production into accordance with the social forces of 
production in a controlled way, guided by the scientific study of the 
structure and mode of development of human society. Naturally, 
therefore, the scientific theory of society, on which the modem 
revolutionary socialist movement relies, was worked out when and 
only when that organisation began to be created ; and not independently 
of the work of creating and directing the organisation, but as an 
integral part of it. This means that for the first time in history men 
have begun to take the future into their own hands, in the sense of 
being able to build an organisation which could so understand the 
issues as to predict where it was going, and go there. 

Such, then, being the logical character of the long-term predictions 
scientifically worked out by Marxist social theory, we can also reach 
some conclusions as to the necessary limits of predictability. 

I have already pointed out that well-founded social predictions are 
not “ unconditional” but conditional, that they are based on estimates 
of probabilities, and that their realisation depends on the existence of 
effective organisation to create the conditions for carrying them out 
and to carry them out. 

In the first place, therefore, we cannot predict anything beyond 
what the organisation can carry out. Marx's predictions concerned 
the work of Communist organisations in bringing about first socialism, 
and then the transition from socialism to communism. It is clear 
enough that, when the latter goal is realised, the communist organ- 
isation will have completed its function. So what people do after that 
will be up to them. We can certainly predict that the principal causes 
of present social ill will by then have been finally removed and that, 
having established social appropriation to match social production, 
people will not go back again to private appropriation. But while on 
these grounds we can express the confident hope that, when com- 
munism is established, people will manage much better than they did 
in the past, or do now, we cannot possibly predict just how they will 
manage, or what exactly they will decide to do, or what new diffi- 
culties they will meet and how they will cope with them. 

In the second place, because of the way social life depends on deve- 
loping and deploying forces of production, prediction is limited to 
what can be done with the forces of production at present under 
development. It is true, of course, that on the basis of existing tech- 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 151 

nology certain predictions can be made about probable technological 
advance in the future. In other words, certain discoveries can be seen 
coming; and this, of course, is the basis for planned research. For 
example, once certain fundamental discoveries of nuclear physics had 
been made the technology of nuclear energy could be seen coming, 
and so research was devoted to its development. So, at the present day, 
we can see coming a very big development of the technology of 
nuclear energy, automation and electronic computers, and space 
travel, and can forecast various ways in which these technologies will 
be used. However, this kind of technological forecasting is limited. 
We cannot possibly predict the content of entirely new discoveries — 
for obviously, if we could predict them we would have discovered 
them already. Hence we cannot predict what new technologies will be 
invented, after the present ones have been more fully developed. And 
so we cannot predict what human life will be like in the event (and 
it is in the long-term the very probable event) of new fundamental 
discoveries. People in the Stone Age could not have predicted the 
discovery of iron. And we remain in a similar position. 

5. NECESSITY AND INEVITABILITY 

Marx “was the first to put sociology on a scientific basis’*, wrote 
Lenin in What the Friends of the People Are , “by establishing the concept 
of the economic formation of society as the sum-total of relations of 
production, and by establishing the fact that the development of such 
formations is a process of natural history.” 

That the evolution of social-economic formations is like natural 
history means that the past course of social evolution is explained like 
natural history. Just as the evolution of species is explained by the 
necessity of organisms being adapted to their environments, so is the 
evolution of social formations explained by the necessity of production 
relations being adapted to productive forces. In social evolution, 
presumably, this adaptation will continue, just as species will continue 
to be adapted to their environments. 

In predicting the future we presume that it will be explicable on the 
same lines as the past. Nevertheless, this does not mean that prediction 
of future social events is like prediction of natural events. For our own 
role in the process of bringing about those events is different. A similar 
distinction must be made, of course, regarding predictions of natural 
events subjected to human interference. 


152 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


Science, which is something which people do, must always take 
into account the relation of the people doing the science to the pro- 
cesses which the science is about. Men make their own history. 
Therefore the relation of people trying scientifically to understand 
social processes to the processes they are trying to understand is 
different from that of the same people to natural processes. And 
therefore, this difference must be taken into account in thinking 
scientifically about social prospects. 

It is true that some people (those whom Dr. Popper calls “histori- 
cists”) try to take what may be called a “god’s eye” view of human 
affairs, and to predict the future of these little creatures crawling over 
the face of the earth as though they themselves and their contem- 
poraries were not engaged in making that future. However, the god’s 
eye view is not the scientific view. Some see in the crystal ball visions 
of utopia, others catastrophe, or unending cycles of decay and re- 
generation. But none of their prophecies are, or can be, well founded — 
because they do not take into account how people actually make 
history, and do not back their predictions with practical proposals for 
an organisation to carry them out. Instead, they imagine themselves 
as looking down on society from a stance outside society — which is as 
absurd as a physicist imagining himself as looking at the physical world 
through an instrument which is not itself physical. 

In his criticisms of “historicism” Dr. Popper justifiably questions 
the assumptions of crystal-gazers. Evidently, his criticisms have no 
bearing on the scientific study of society, and the proposals for and 
predictions of future social activity, made by Marx. Marx did not gaze 
into any crystal. Nor did he imagine himself as looking down on 
society, like a man who watches a carpet being unrolled, and who 
predicts the pattern on the next bits to appear from what he has seen 
of the pattern so far. From studying history Marx concluded that men 
make their history by adapting their production relations to their 
productive forces. He worked out how we can do this today, made 
practical proposals for organisation for doing it — and predicted that 
it would be done. As Lenin said, he “put sociology on a scientific 
basis”, and so put political policy-making on a scientific basis too. 

It is, of course, always possible to make fairly reliable short-term 
predictions of social events from the standpoint of a mere observer, 
by estimating what some people are doing or going to do, and what 
others may do to stop them. If, for example, it looks either as if no one 
can stop them, or as if no one wants to stop them, then a fairly con- 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


153 


fident prediction can be made that what they are doing will be done. 
Marx’s prediction went far beyond this, because it concerned the future 
social-economic formation. Such a prediction can only be scientifically 
grounded when it is grounded, first, on an accurate idea of the general 
conditions governing the evolution of economic formations, and 
second, on proposals for what sort of organisation is required to bring 
the new formation into being and how the organisation should be 
conducted. And that is how Marx’s prediction was grounded. 

Marx did not speak as a prophet or fortune-teller, who tells people: 
This is fated to happen, so prepare yourselves ! He spoke as a practical 
organiser, who says, with good grounds for saying it: Do this — and 
you will win. 

Where, then, is the “historicism” in Marx, which Dr. Popper so 
vehemently censures? Where is the vaunted discovery of “the plot” 
which the moving fmger writes, of “the path” which people willy- 
nilly tread, of “the destiny” which pursues us? And where is the 
“unconditional prophecy”? Only in Dr. Popper’s fertile imagination. 
Marx, the “famous historicist”, was not “an historicist” at all. He was 
only, as Lenin said, “the first to put sociology on a scientific basis”. 

Historicism, as defined by Dr. Popper, is an idealist concept. The 
concept of “the plot” which is unfolded in history and “the path” 
laid down for us, is the concept of a pre-existing idea which is realised 
in time in the material world. It is, indeed, at bottom, a theological 
concept of creation: “in the beginning was the Word”. Those who 
think they can say what the future will be because they think they 
know “the plot” and “the path” are frauds who pretend to powers of 
prophecy not given to other men because they imagine themselves 
to be en rapport with the eternal. Despite his rationalism and empirical 
method, Hegel, the idealist, was certainly “an historicist” in Dr. 
Popper’s sense. In opposing Hegel’s idealism, Marx opposed to 
Hegelian “historicism” the scientific materialist theory of how men 
make and will make history. 

That Marx made use of “the historical method” is undoubted. As 
Dr. Popper quite rightly says, Marx considered that “we can obtain 
knowledge of social entities only by studying social changes”. And 
it is a puzzle to know how else we could “obtain knowledge of social 
entities”. Dr. Popper, however, proceeds to call Marx’s historical 
method “historicist”, and says Marx studied social changes so as to 
discover therein “rhythms, patterns, laws and trends” and so predict 
the future. He makes out that Marx was the man who traces the 


154 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


pattern in the unrolling carpet so as to predict what the next piece of 
the pattern will be like. The prediction, of course, must be quite 
groundless unless one has grounds to believe that the carpet was made 
by a manufacturer who imposed a pattern on it. Human history is not 
at all like an unrolling carpet. 

Marx did not look at history to find the superimposed pattern. 
He studied social changes to obtain knowledge of how men make such 
changes, so as to work out how we can make changes now, and what 
conditions they must fulfil to satisfy our needs. Like any scientist, he 
wanted to find out what are the conditions of our lives and what we 
can do about it. That was Marx’s historical method, and the object of 
his applying it. 

The crunch of this whole argument concerns Marx’s conception of 
“the class struggle” and of the “necessity” and “inevitability” which, 
he maintained, attaches to it and its outcome. Explaining to a corre- 
spondent (J. Weydcmeyer, March 5, 1852) what he claimed to have 
scientifically established by his historical method, Marx wrote: 

“No credit is due to me for discovering the existence of classes in 
modern society, nor yet the struggle between them. Long before me 
bourgeois historians had described the historical development of the 
struggle of the classes, and bourgeois economists the economic anatomy 
of the classes. What I did new was to prove: 

(1) that the existence of classes is only bound up with particular 
historical phases of the development of production; 

(2) that the class struggle necessarily leads to the dictatorship of the 
proletariat; 

(3) that this dictatorship itself only constitutes the transition to the 
abolition of all classes and to a classless society.” 

There you have it, Dr. Popper may say. What did I tell you? Marx 
was an historicist. It may be in fact true that history is “the history of 
class struggles”. And “bourgeois historians” who modestly attempted 
to do no more than describe what happened, and did not aspire, like 
historicists, to be prophets, may have done well to describe those class 
struggles. But Marx goes farther. He asserts that class struggles are 
“bound up with the development of production” and so constitute 
the necessary pattern of history, and that the continuation of this 
pattern will “necessarily” or “inevitably” lead to “the dictatorship of 
the proletariat” and then to “a classless society”. What is this but 
unconditional historical prophecy, derived from a claim to have dis- 
covered the pattern, the rhythm, the plot and the plan of history? 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


155 


Let us examine the plain meaning and implications of Marx's 
statement of his position. 

First of all, Marx in his theory of class struggle drew attention to 
inescapable circumstances in which people have had, and still have, to 
act; and to inescapable issues which they have had, and still have, to 
settle. There is no help for it — there are the circumstances, there are 
the issues, as objective facts of human life which cannot be evaded. 
Because class divisions bring class antagonisms into the way people 
have to get their livelihood, the class struggle has become necessary or 
inevitable, in the sense of unavoidable. And Marx was able to explain 
why this has happened. It is because the production relations into which 
people entered once they began to raise their productive forces above 
the level of the Stone Age have included class contradictions. 

Exactly as Marx said, “men do not make their history just as they 
please, they do not make it under circumstances chosen by themselves". 
They have to enter into relations of production in order to use their 
productive forces with the same necessity as they have to use their 
hands to fashion their implements of production. Such things are, for 
us, necessary, inevitable, unavoidable. To know what are our actual 
circumstances, what are the issues, and what we can and cannot do 
about them, science must distinguish the accidental in our circum- 
stances from the necessary, the avoidable from the unavoidable. Not 
to do so is to draw back from scientific analysis and decline to face 
facts. 

Secondly, having demonstrated the necessity or una voidability of 
the class struggle, Marx concluded that the class struggle provides the 
dynamic whereby historical issues are decided. The given relations of 
production contain the class divisions, and action to change the 
relations of production is action to change the class relations, that is, 
class struggle. 

And finally, his analysis of the capitalist production relations and 
the class struggle under capitalism led to the conclusion that these 
relations and the corresponding class struggle will persist until such 
time as the working classes succeed in winning the political power to 
institute social ownership and social appropriation, which means 
expropriating the capitalist class. That is what he called “the dictator- 
ship of the proletariat". This is the only way to settle the issue of adapt- 
ing production relations to modem forces of production, and when it 
is accomplished there will be “a classless society". 

That “the class struggle necessarily leads to the dictatorship of the 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


156 

proletariat” has the plain meaning that this is the only way in which 
it can be finished. It cannot but go on until that outcome takes place. 
From the very circumstances of its existence the working class cannot 
but continue to oppose exploitation, and the only way it can get rid 
of what it opposes is by winning political power and using that power 
to reorganise social relations. And so, apart from what The Communist 
Manifesto described as “the mutual destruction of the contending 
classes” (which could take place nowadays in a nuclear war), or outside 
intervention (such as an invasion from outer space, or a cosmic catas- 
trophe), the dictatorship of the proletariat and the transition to a 
classless society is the unavoidable, that is, necessary or inevitable, 
outcome. 

It is clear that this theory of the necessity of the class struggle and of 
the dictatorship of the proletariat is no “unconditional prophecy” but 
a straightforward scientific analysis. It is a scientific analysis which 
supplies a programme and a guide to action for the working-class 
struggle, based on sober scientific recognition of the whole social 
situation. To argue that the theory is wrong it would have to be 
argued that the general idea of adaptation of relations of production to 
forces of production is wrong, and that the analysis of capitalist 
relations of production is wrong. But Dr. Popper, with his critique of 
“historicism”, dodges the issue by arguing that the very concepts 
employed by the theory are “historicist” rather than scientific. He can 
do this only by making out that the theory means something different 
from what it says. 

To know the meanings of words as they are used in statements one 
must always take those words and statements in their context, with 
their implications. The secret of the mad tea party type of discussion 
lies in refusing to do this. Certain philosophers have tried to define 
senses of the words “necessity” and “inevitability” which give us 
absolute or “inexorable” necessity in nature and human affairs, and 
absolute inevitability. A model for this was the well-known theorem of 
Spinoza, that “the effect follows from the cause with the same neces- 
sity as the three angles of a triangle make two right-angles”. It is 
evident, however, that the word “necessity” has a different sense when 
we talk about some event “necessarily happening” from what it has 
when we talk about “the three angles of a triangle necessarily making 
two right-angles”. This is evident, for one thing, because for angles to 
add up to two right-angles is not an event ; and for another, because to 
say “so and so necessarily happens” is not incompatible with saying 


fflSTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


157 


“under other imaginable circumstances something else could have 
happened”. 

For discussing what happens, the relevant categories are those of 
possibility and impossibility — and these are the categories employed by 
the sciences, including the science of society. Scientific thinking reaches 
conclusions about what is possible and what is impossible relative to a 
given set of circumstances . On the other hand, “inexorable necessity”, 
“absolute inevitability”, “fate”, “destiny”, and so forth, are absolutes; 
the inexorably necessary is supposed to happen, and “the destined path” 
is inexorably taken, regardless of circumstances. Such absolutes are 
alien to science, and apply only in the fantastic world of false abstraction. 

Of “necessity” it may be remarked that the opposite of “impos- 
sibility” is “possibility” and not “necessity”. In the context of pos- 
sibility, as defmed by science, the word “necessary” has the sense of 
“impossible without” or “impossible unless”. Thus the class struggle 
necessarily leads to the dictatorship of the proletariat because that is 
the only way it can finish, and because the class aim of emancipation 
from exploitation is impossible to realise without establishing first a 
system of political power to abolish exploitation. 

Successful politics, then, demands the appreciation of necessity f that 
is to say, of the necessary conditions without which the possible cannot 
be achieved, but with the satisfaction of which it will be achieved. 
And this appreciation is afforded by social and political science. The 
essential teaching of Marxism for working-class politics is that emanci- 
pation from exploitation and class struggle can only be achieved 
through the dictatorship of the proletariat. Marx was talking about 
unavoidable conditions of human action, about the only ways in which 
unavoidable issues can be finally settled. 

In the light of these considerations about necessity and inevitability, 
and the preceding analysis of the logical character of scientific social 
prediction, we can now, I think, detect the further misunderstanding 
which Dr. Popper perpetrates when he concludes that Marx’s “histori- 
cism” was in contradiction to what he calls Marx’s “activism”. Dr. 
Popper says that to speak of what the class struggle “necessarily” leads 
to, and to make a long-term prediction, is incompatible with the 
“activist” point of view which promotes organisation for realising 
the prediction and admits that without the organisation the prediction 
will not come true. For if something is fated to happen, or will happen 
with inexorable necessity, why advocate going to any trouble to 
make sure it does happen? 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


158 

“The historicist method”, writes Dr. Popper, “implies . . . that 
society will necessarily change . . . through stages predetermined by 
inexorable necessity.” Hence “it teaches the futility of any attempt to 
alter impending changes; a peculiar variety of fatalism. . . . Admit- 
tedly, die ‘activist’ exhortation ‘The philosophers have only inter- 
preted the world in various ways: the point, however, is to change it’, 
may find much sympathy with historicists. . . . But it is in conflict with 
the most significant doctrines of historicism. For as we now see, we 
may say: ‘The historicist can only interpret social development and 
aid it in various ways; his point, however, is that nobody can change 
it.’ ” (PH. 51-2). 

Dr. Popper begins by merely begging the question, since, as we have 
already seen, Marx’s method was not “historicist”, nor did his con- 
clusions imply that historical necessity is “inexorable”. But he ends 
widi sheer nonsense. When Marx said “the point is to change it” 
he clearly meant that the point is, by understanding the way changes 
operate, to bring about controlled changes. He did not mean to change 
the ways things change. It is quite true that nobody can change the 
basic ways human beings have to set about their affairs — we cannot 
“change social development” in such a way as to do by will-power or 
magic things which hitherto we have done with our hands; nor can 
we change it in such a way that we do not have to adapt relations of 
production to forces of production; nor, when modern forces of 
production are fettered by capitalism, can we change this situation into 
one in which capitalist relations cease to act as fetters. But this does not 
imply that we cannot “change the world” in a controlled way, if 
once we arrive at an objective analysis of circumstances and of the 
means and limitations of our actions. It does not mean that we cannot 
with the aid of scientific analysis effectively organise to “make 
history”; though it does mean, of course, that we still cannot “make 
it just as we please”. But no one but a fool would think that either 
individually or collectively people have power to do “just as they 
please”. 

As regards the “peculiar variety of fatalism”, the judgment about 
whether a scientific analysis of social circumstances implies “fatalism” 
and “the futility of any attempt to alter impending changes” depends 
entirely on one’s point of view and what changes one wants to make or 
prevent. From the point of view of someone who proposes to rise on 
the wings of a dove, the Newtonian theory of gravitation no doubt 
propounds “a peculiar variety of fatalism”. It says you just can’t do it. 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


159 


From the point of view of the capitalist class, Marx's theory is certainly 
“fatalistic”. It says: You cannot contrive a managed capitalism, you 
cannot do away with the class struggle, you cannot keep the system 
going indefinitely. It does not go so far as to say, You can do nothing 
to block socialist advance; but it does say, You can never block it once 
for all, but will have to keep on blocking it until finally it blocks you. 
As a further offence against capitalism, it offers practical advice to 
socialists as to how to demolish capitalist blocks. From the point of view 
of the working class, on the other hand, it is not “fatalist” at all. It 
explains the situation, says what to do, and predicts that it will be done. 

Dr. Popper’s critique does no more than voice the natural dis- 
satisfaction of capitalist apologists with an objective analysis of capital- 
ism and its possibilities of development. Any scientific analysis is bound 
to be “fatalistic” from the point of view of those interested in doing 
what cannot be done. 


6. SCIENCE AND UTOPIA 

After what has been said about “historicism”, it is perhaps unnecessary 
to add much more in relation to Dr. Popper’s further allegations about 
“essentialism”, “holism” and “utopianism”. 

According to Dr. Popper, Marxist science claims to discover and 
describe the “hidden reality or essence” which “must unfold itself in 
change”. Well, Marxist science certainly does claim to discover and 
describe processes going on amongst men in society, relations into 
which men enter with nature and with one another, which men cannot 
avoid entering into and conducting, and which do, inevitably, whether 
men are aware of it or not, determine the character of the social 
changes they make and condition their conscious activities. In this 
respect, however, the discoveries of Marxist science about men are no 
different in kind from the discoveries of any other empirical science 
about anything else. 

Chemists, for instance, observing chemical phenomena, and wishing 
to explain them, try to discover processes and relations which deter- 
mine and condition the phenomena. They try to discover “what is 
really happening” when those phenomena happen. In this sense 
chemistry (like all other branches of natural science) certainly claims to 
discover “the hidden reality” or, as Dr. Popper has also expressed it, 
“the realities which He behind the appearances”. But no one accuses 
chemists of “essentialism”. 


i do 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


Marx said that men always enter into relations of production in order 
to deploy their forces of production, that this has involved them in 
class struggles, and that “history is the history of class struggles’*. This 
is how men carry on. Indeed, it is how men inevitably or necessarily 
or “essentially” carry on, in view (as Marx and Engels said) of “the 
physical organisation of the individuals and their consequent relation 
to the rest of nature”. This fact was “hidden”, and it required some 
research to uncover it. It was a scientific discovery, like other scientific 
discoveries. It was no more a product of “methodological essentialism” 
than any other scientific discovery. It was no more a discovery of “the 
hidden essence” than any physical, chemical or biological discovery 
discovers “essences”. Marx was not concerned with “essences” but 
with real relations of human individuals, which, as he and Engels said 
in The German Ideology, “can be verified in a purely empirical way”. 

Finally, we come to “holism” and “utopianism”. According to 
Dr. Popper, “holism is interested in the development, not of aspects 
of social life, but of ‘society as a whole’ ”, and considers that one can 
only properly understand particular “aspects” by seeing how they are 
determined by “the whole”. And “utopianism” is bound up with 
“holism”, because “the utopian” does not aim at changing particular 
“aspects” but “the whole”. 

Marx was certainly “interested in the development of society as a 
whole”. He was interested “in the development of society as a whole” 
in the same way as a biologist, for instance, is interested in the develop- 
ment of the organism as a whole. That does not make either the 
Marxist or the biologist into a “holist”. Neither is interested in the 
“the whole” to the exclusion of “the aspects”, for each knows per- 
fectly well that “the whole” is the product of the complex interactions 
of the parts. 

The biologist understands the organism as a complex of interrelated 
living cells, and similarly the Marxist understands society as a complex 
of interrelated living individuals. The living parts live in inter- 
relation. Of course, it is their mode of interrelation which determines 
the overall character and behaviour of the whole, of the organism or of 
the society. And at the same time, the ways in which the parts are 
interrelated, and interact and function, as parts of the whole, deter- 
mines the specific character and properties of each part. A cell which is 
a cell of some organism is a bone cell or a nerve cell or a muscle cell, 
and so not the same as a cell that lives all on its own; just as an in- 
dividual person gets his individuality from his being bom into, 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION l6l 

educated in and functioning in a society, and would not have this 
individuality outside society. An organism is not formed by fully- 
fashioned. individual cells, each complete independently of the organ- 
ism, coming together to form an organism; nor is a society formed by 
fully-fashioned individuals, each a complete human person in- 
dependently of social life, coming together to form a society. Further, 
just as the organism grows and changes by a process of all the cells 
functioning and relating themselves to one another to obtain the means 
of life from the environment, so does society grown and change by a 
process of all the individuals functioning and relating themselves to one 
another to obtain the means of life. 

Marx’s investigation of society led him, however, to conclude that a 
society is nevertheless in important respects not much like a biological 
organism. The individuals who make up society are human organisms, 
so naturally the relations they enter into as human organisms obtaining 
their means of life by social production are of an entirely different 
kind from those the cells of a living organism enter into as cells of 
that organism. His views about society were arrived at by investigating 
the relations individuals enter into in forming a society, and not 
deduced from some abstract comparison of societies with organisms. 

His analysis of the social process, that is, of the relations individuals 
enter into in order to obtain the means of life, and of the consequences 
of their entering into those relations, led him to the conclusion that, to 
“change society”, the key thing to do is to change the relations of 
production in adaptation to productive forces. He concluded that then, 
when that is done, “with the change of the economic foundation the 
whole immense superstructure is more or less rapidly transformed”. 
And this conclusion, a consequence of the analysis, is verified by the 
facts of history — a verification which thus verifies the analysis of which 
it is the consequence. 

In what way is this conclusion from a normal type of scientific 
analysis either “holist” or “utopian”? Marx did not say that one must 
first change “the whole”, and that only by that means could one 
change “the aspects”. Of course, it is as absurd or utopian to seek to 
change “the whole” without studying and doing something about 
“the aspects” as it is to seek to “understand the development of the 
whole” without studying the aspects in their complex interrelation- 
ship. What Marx did do, and what Marx did say, was precisely what 
normal scientific method requires us to do and say. He studied the 
various aspects of society to find out how the whole is constituted and 


1 62 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


develops ; and out of this study he discovered what are the key relations 
determining overall development, and said that, to change society, 
one must concentrate on finding how to change those key relations. 

On die other hand, it is not very difficult to see diat the opposition 
which Dr. Popper has inferred, between Marx’s alleged “holism” on 
the one hand, and the alleged “anti-holism” of science, is an absurdity. 
Societies have in fact in common widi living organisms the feature diat 
in each diere occur certain kinds of “life process” (for example, the 
circulation of the blood in animals, and the processes of economic 
exchange in commodity-producing societies), die disruption of which 
is followed by die death or distintegration of die whole. It is essential 
in any sort of scientific account of processes of this description that the 
given process should be studied “as a whole” — to find out, that is to 
say, how the parts interact in order to produce the whole process, and 
why, if the whole disintegrates, die parts can no longer exist as be- 
fore, being no longer parts of die whole. This entails, in particular, 
investigating the mechanisms of “feed-back” by which what happens 
in one part produces effects which react back on other parts, so as to 
keep the whole intact. Clearly, such feed-back processes are character- 
istic of the organism or of the society “as a whole”, and cannot be 
studied except in the context of studying how “die whole” is main- 
tained and develops. When Marx studied capitalist society, examining 
at one level the processes of the circulation of capital, and at another 
level those of the class struggle, he was studying how the “life process” 
of society goes on under capitalism, was discovering the disruptions it 
undergoes, and accordingly working out proposals as to what should 
be done and what changes should be made in order to enable social 
production and consumption to continue widiout these sorts of 
disruptions. 

So when we examine Marx’s methods, ideas and conclusions, we 
find that all Dr. Popper’s clamorous allegations about “historicism”, 
“essentialism”, “holism” and “utopianism”, which have so gready 
impressed so many people whose prejudices made them want to be 
impressed, are sheer misrepresentation and mydiology. In telling us 
what Marxism means, Dr. Popper produces only a very stupid 
travesty of Marxism. This, he asserts, amounts to a “devastating 
criticism” and destroys all the scientific pretentions of Marxism once 
for all. 

Certainly, the Marx whom Dr. Popper puts up to prosecute for 
ideological errors in Wonderland shows very litde understanding of 


HISTORICISM AND HISTORICAL PREDICTION 


I63 

the concepts or methods of the sciences. But as we have seen, and as 
we shall see again and again in what follows, the real Marx is perfectly 
conversant with the methods of science and with various scientific 
truths which Dr. Popper proclaims with the intention of confounding 
him; and the real Marx drew scientific conclusions which Dr. Popper, 
for all his parade of a truly scientific oudook, only misrepresents and 
evades. It is in these misrepresentations and evasions contained in 
Dr. Popper’s refutations of Marxism that misunderstandings about the 
character of scientific method and of scientific conclusions are to be 
found. As for Marx, he approached the investigation of social phe- 
nomena, and the proposal of social remedies, in a thoroughly scientific 
manner. 


2 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 

I. PROBLEMS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE 

Marx applied the normal methods of scientific inquiry to the study of 
human society, and formulated the fundamental hypotheses under- 
lying all social sciences. . His credentials are similar to those of any other 
foundation-layer in other sciences. His propositions can all be tested 
and, far from propounding a theoretical system to answer all questions 
and account for everything finally and completely, he began an 
investigation for others to carry further. 

But that Marx applied scientific method, already well established 
for the study of nature, to the study of society, does not mean that he 
set about the job as though there were no difference between studying 
natural and social processes. For different kinds of processes different 
techniques of inquiry have to be devised, with different kinds of 
hypotheses and appropriate methods for testing them. Social processes, 
unlike mechanical, physical, chemical or biological processes, are 
the results of self-conscious agents “acting with deliberation or 
passion’. Possibly one may study how deliberations and passions are 
engendered in individuals as one may study how, say, chemical reac- 
tions are engendered. But the way in which the actions of human be- 
ings make up the processes of society precludes the systematic investiga- 
tion of the latter by artificially setting up experiments, as is done in, say, 
chemistry. As Marx said in the Preface to Capital , here “neither 
microscopes nor chemical reagents are of use. The force of abstraction 
must replace both”. 

Moreover, not only do the phenomena investigated thus differ in 
the way they are brought about, but there is the further difference 
that to investigate social activities is itself a social activity and introduces 
a new factor into the phenomena investigated. Physicists have had to 
reckon with the fact that to investigate electrons a beam of electrons is 
employed, so that die investigation interferes with what is in- 
vestigated. Nevertheless, to use electrons to investigate electrons does 
not alter the ways electrons behave by creating for them the power to 
do what they otherwise could not do. When people, on the other hand, 
gain knowledge of dieir own social relations and their mode of 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 165 

development, that gain of knowledge is the gain of a new power for 
changing and developing their social relations. 

That Marx succeeded where others had failed in finding how to 
study society scientifically was due, amongst other things, to his 
recognition that studying social processes is not at all the same thing as 
studying natural processes. 

In his observations about scientific method Dr. Popper has very 
righdy and properly pointed out that the old idea of empiricist 
philosophers, that science proceeds simply by accumulating “observa- 
tions” and then making “inductions” from observations, does not 
correspond to the logic of scientific inquiry. That is not how science 
proceeds, or could proceed. “Science starts from problems, and not 
from observations,” he writes. “The conscious task before the scientist 
is always the solution of a problem through the construction of a 
theory which solves the problem . . . every worth while new theory 
raises new problems . . . the most lasting contribution to the growth of 
scientific knowledge that a theory can make are the new problems 
which it raises, so that we are led back to the view of science and of the 
growth of knowledge as always starting from, and always ending with 
problems — problems of an ever-increasing depth, and an ever-increas- 
ing fertility in suggesting new problems” (CR. 222). 

As I said at the beginning of this book, Marx laid the foundations 
of social science by finding the right problems to tackle. To find the 
problems of science is also to define the subject-matter of science. 
Formulating the problems, Marxism at the same time enables us to 
define the subject-matter of the inquiry. It thus becomes a true 
scientific discipline. 

Human society consists of nothing but interrelated human indivi- 
duals. So naturally, social science is an inquiry into what human 
individuals do, and how they are able to satisfy their needs in their 
social intercourse. But the problems and subject-matter of social 
science are not those of the physiology and psychology of human 
individuals, their individual activities and reactions. Individuals create 
and sustain society by entering into social relations with one another, 
and it is the social relations which are the subject-matter of social science 
and set its problems. 

Dr. Popper has criticised under the name of “psychologism” the 
view that the fundamental question for social science is to understand 
the psychology of human individuals, and that all social phenomena 
are direct effects of psychological causes. Crude examples of psycho- 


1 66 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


logism are the theory that individuals need a father-figure, and so we 
get monarchies; and are aggressive, and so we get wars. The fact is 
that social phenomena, such as monarchies and wars, are consequent 
upon the social relations into which individuals have entered. Indeed, 
individuals acquire their human individuality only in social relations, 
and behave differently in different social relations; though naturally, 
as Marx and Engels also pointed out, to explain the social relations 
and what people do in them we must always take into account “the 
physical organisation of the individuals and their consequent relation 
to the rest of nature”. 

“Perhaps the most important criticism of psychologism is that it 
fails to understand the main task of the explanatory social sciences”, 
writes Dr. Popper (2-OS. 94). “This task is . . . the discovery and 
explanation of the less obvious dependencies within the social sphere.” 
He justly praises Marx for opposing psychologism. But what he fails 
to note is that, opposing psychologism, Marxism has well defined 
“the main task of the explanatory social sciences”, leading to “the 
discovery and explanation of the less obvious dependencies”. 

The main task of the explanatory social sciences is to describe and explain 
social relations , in abstraction from individuals who enter into them. 
The dependencies discovered and explained are the dependencies of 
social relations. Clearly, to speak of social relations is to speak of what 
numbers of unspecified individuals do in association. A social relation 
is a relation of individuals. But to describe social relations does not 
require specification of the individuals who enter into them, and 
social relations persist while individuals come and go. 

This shows, incidentally, why Marx spoke of “the force of abstrac- 
tion” as replacing, in social science, microscopes and chemical reagents. 
A relation cannot be laid out under a microscope, nor can it be separated 
out and put to work like a chemical reagent. To study social relations 
independent of the individuals who enter into them requires “the 
force of abstraction”. Dr. Popper himself recognises this. “In the social 
sciences ... we cannot see and observe our objects before we have 
thought about them”, he says. “For most of the objects of social 
science, if not all of them, are abstract objects . . (PH. 135). Marx 
put it rather more clearly — but the point is the same. 

As we have seen, Marx’s fundamental propositions for the social 
sciences were arrived at by asking what is the necessary condition for 
people to enter into social relations at all. People must socially produce 
their material means of life, and enter into relations of production 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


167 

corresponding to their social forces of production. Having reached 
that conclusion, he went on to study how people change their relations 
of production, and this entails the study of the interdependencies of 
social relations in processes of social change. The key problems for 
social science, he showed, are not problems of the actions and motiva- 
tions of individuals but of the formation and interdependence of 
social relations. Social relations change and develop. The problem of 
how the change and development is brought about and of the laws 
which govern it, the main problem of the scientific understanding of 
society and its history, is the problem of analysing and sorting out the 
interdependence of social relations. The laws regulating society and 
its development are expressed as generalised statements of such 
interdependence. 

Social science thus abstracts from individuals and deals with social 
relations. It is not concerned with individual but with aggregate 
humanity — with the consequences of the interactions of large numbers, 
and not with the individual peculiarities of this and that person. The 
laws which it formulates, therefore, to the effect that some social 
relations depend on others, which are laws governing all change in 
social relations, are laws applying to aggregates of individuals, not to 
the individuals who make up the aggregates. And (as I have already 
said) the predictions which it enables us to make are predictions about 
the overall consequences of large numbers of individual interactions. 

All this seems, in principle, not only fairly clear but also in fair 
accord with Dr. Popper’s own justified remarks about scientific 
method. Dr. Popper, however, now proceeds to some further criticism 
of Marx’s allegedly “historicist” views about the laws governing 
social processes. 

According to historicism, he says, ‘ ‘sociological laws, or the laws of 
social life, differ in different places and periods” (PH. 5). Consequently 
“the only universally valid laws of society must be the laws which 
link up successive periods. They must be laws of historical develop- 
ment which determine the transition from one period to another” 
(PH. 41). Historicists, of whom Marx was a famous one, think they 
have found the one great law which determines social development — 
and this law is an “evolutionary” law, which says that social develop- 
ment follows a certain course in the sequence of periods and the 
transition from one period to another. 

Such a claim, says Dr. Popper, is very easy to refute. “Can there 
be a law of evolution?” he asks. “I believe that the answer to this 


1 68 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


question must be ‘No’, and that the search for the law of the ‘unvarying 
order’ of evolution cannot possibly fall within the scope of scientific 
method, whether in biology or in sociology. My reasons are very 
simple. The evolution of life on earth, or of human society, is a 
unique historical process. Such a process, we may assume, proceeds 
in accordance with all kinds of causal laws, for example, the laws of 
mechanics, of chemistry, of heredity and segregation, of natural 
selection, etc. Its description, however, is not a law, but only a singular 
historical statement. Universal laws make assertions concerning some 
unvarying order . . . i.e., concerning all processes of a certain kind . . . 
But we cannot hope to test a universal hypothesis nor to find a natural 
law acceptable to science if we are for ever confined to the observation 
of one unique process. Nor can the observation of one unique process 
help us to foresee its future development” (PH. 107-8). 

But these remarks have no more relevance to the “sociological 
laws” or laws of “social evolution” discovered by Marx than they 
have to the laws of organic evolution discovered by Darwin. 

Darwin’s explanatory theory about organic evolution did not 
consist in propounding “the law” that organic evolution “invariably” 
or “universally” proceeds from marine invertebrates, through fishes, 
reptiles and mammals, to man. Of course, organic evolution on the 
earth is a unique process, so there cannot be a “universal law” that it 
“always” proceeds in one “unvarying order”. Darwin’s explanatory 
theory was the theory of natural selection, which explains how the 
unique evolution has taken place. Similarly, Marx’s explanatory theory 
about social evolution did not consist in propounding the “law” that 
society always develops from primitive communism, through slavery 
(not to mention the Asiatic, Slavonic, Germanic and other odd modes 
of production) to feudalism and capitalism. Society has not always 
developed like that, it has only happened once. His explanatory theory 
was a theory about the interdependence of social relations, with the 
basic dependence of production relations on the forces of production 
and of other relations on production relations, which not only explains 
how the unique evolution has taken place but how to continue it in the 
direction of satisfying human needs. Marx’s theory showed cogently 
enough why social organisation had to start at the level of primitive 
communism, how private property developed and what effects it had, 
why certain conditions had to be achieved before others could be 
entered into (for instance, why feudalism had to precede capitalism), 
and, finally, that we can only solve the contradictions of capitalism 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 169 

by advancing to socialism. But as usual, Dr. Popper refutes Marx by 
making out that Marx talked “historicist” nonsense. 

Having done so, however, Dr. Popper proceeds to talk nonsense 
himself. Because social evolution is a unique process, he concludes 
that * 'history is characterised by its interest in actual, singular, or 
specific events, rather than in laws or generalisations ,, , and that this 
distinguishes “historical” from “theoretical” or “explanatory” 
sciences (PH. 143). The historian, interested in one unique sequence, 
cannot hope to find any “universal law” governing the sequence. 
But why ever not? The historical sequence is in fact governed by the 
law that people always adapt their relations of production to their 
forces of production. Why should not historians be interested in such 
a law? It is universally true, and without it they cannot explain the 
sequence but only describe it. 

Finally, if one takes into account the laws which Marx actually 
discovered (as distinct from those which Dr. Popper invents in order 
to refute), it is evident that the idea that “sociological laws differ in 
different places and periods” and that “the only universally valid laws 
of society must be the laws which link up successive periods” is as 
nonsensical as all the rest of Dr. Popper’s infelicitous lucubrations. The 
basic law which Marx formulated is always valid, whether in the 
development of a single “period” or in the transition from one to 
another. Of course, when a specific set of social relations come into 
being there are interdependencies between them which do not operate 
in other circumstances, when those relations are not present (for 
instance, under capitalism there are laws about, say, costs and profits 
which came into operation only when capitalist relations began to be 
formed). However, that means that “the laws which link up successive 
periods”, far from being “the only universally valid laws”, operate 
only in the specific link-up (for instance, the specific laws in operation 
in the transition from feudalism to capitalism are peculiar to that 
specific transition). 

The way in which a unique unrepeatable irreversible process of 
development can happen in accordance with universal laws is really 
quite simple. It does not mean, as Dr. Popper makes out Marx “the 
famous historicist” meant, that the process “always” follows a certain 
order. That is obviously nonsense, for if it only happens once then it 
does not “always” happen. The order of the process, the order in 
which stage follows stage, the necessity of one stage preceding or 
being followed by another, is the consequence of the working out of 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


170 

the laws — it is what the laws explain and so is not itself “the law”. 
The laws are of the form that certain relations always depend on 
certain other relations. Whatever relations are formed, their laws 
always operate. According to Marx’s theory of “sociological laws” 
relations of production depend on forces of production; people 
change their forces of production in the development of their pro- 
ductive intercourse with nature, and so change their relations of 
production ; and so the unique irreversible stage-by-stage development 
of social-economic formations of human society takes place. This 
makes good scientific sense and is empirically verifiable in terms of 
what people do. 

No more than the operation of sociological laws means that every 
social event and social change is predetermined or “fated”, does it 
mean that people are moved about like “pawns” in the grip of historical 
necessity. On the contrary, as Engels said, and as we know from 
experience anyway, “nothing happens without a conscious purpose, 
without an intended aim”, and people face choices and act of their 
own volition. But relying on certain productive forces, to live by 
which they have entered into certain production relations, what 
people do and can do — what they intend to do and what actually 
comes of their doing it — is conditioned by the relations into which 
they have entered with nature and with one another for obtaining 
their means of life, and the interdependencies of these relations. That 
is an objective condition of life from the limitations of which we 
can no more escape than we can from the limitations of our mortal 
bodies. But the better we understand such objective conditions, the 
less do they appear as limitations. The better we understand what 
cannot be done the better do we understand what can be done, and 
how to do it. 

Speaking of the conscious volitional character of human actions, 
Engels went on to say (Ludwig Feuerbach , Chapter 4), that nevertheless 
“that which is willed happens but rarely; in the majority of instances 
the numerous desired ends cross and conflict with one another, or 
these ends themselves are from the outset incapable of realisation or 
the means for attaining them are insufficient”. Consequently “the 
many individual wills active in history for the most part produce 
results quite other than those they intended — often quite the opposite; 
their motives therefore in relation to the total result are likewise only 
of secondary significance”. 

To explain what happens in history it is not enough to say that 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


171 

people act from certain motives. Their actions are, of course, motivated; 
and the explanation of what happens includes the description of the 
motivations. But motives “cross and conflict” and, as it works out, 
what happens is, more often than not, what no one intended. To 
explain both human motivations, and the results, both intended and 
unintended, of their motivated actions, it is also necessary to take 
into account the interdependence of social relations, which exhibit 
laws quite independent of anything people may intend or think. 

In remarking that the task of the social sciences is “the discovery 
and explanation of the less obvious dependencies within the social 
sphere”, Dr. Popper proceeds to conclude that “the main task of the 
social sciences ... is the task of analysing the unintended social 
repercussions of intentional human actions” (2-OS. 95; he must 
think this definition definitive, for it is repeated in italics in CR. 
34 2 )- 

This conclusion only illustrates once again Dr. Popper’s unfortunate 
tendency to talk nonsense. Why ever should the task of the social 
sciences be restricted to tracing the unintended social repercussions of 
intentional actions? For the better we can discover and explain “the 
less obvious dependencies within the social sphere” (dependencies of 
social relations), the better can we judge what can and cannot be 
done, and so the less will the social repercussions of our intentional 
actions be unintended. Put together, Dr. Popper’s two definitions of 
the task of the social sciences make nonsense. For success in carrying 
out the first task eliminates the second. 

In studying the laws of development of society (or “dependencies 
within the social sphere”), and pointing out that their operation 
explains the results of human actions irrespective of intentions, Marx 
and Engels made it quite clear that, once these laws are understood, it 
becomes possible to project plans of action, based on an objective 
analysis of circumstances, in which the results will be brought more 
and more, in a controlled way, within the scope of the intentions. As 
with other sciences, success in social sciences increases our power to 
fit our intentions to our capabilities and to bring about what we 
intend. All knowledge is power. It follows that knowledge about our 
own social activities makes possible a change in the character of our 
social activities. When we have enough of it, and have built an 
organisation for using it, we can base our intentions on knowledge of 
our circumstances and needs, and carry them out. 


172 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


2. SOCIAL SCIENCE AND POLITICS 

Politics, it has been well said, is the art of the possible. This description 
of politics makes it clear how social science applies in politics. For in 
science we discover what is possible and what is not, and how what is 
possible gets brought about. In social science, the study of social 
relations, we discover the conditions and possibilities of human action 
in the management of social life. We discover how given social 
relations limit possibilities. We discover the conditions for changing 
social relations and what possibilities such changes open up. We 
discover how social relations establish class distinctions and divergent 
or antagonistic class interests, and what possibilities there are for the 
pursuit of those interests. 

Politics is a social activity — an art or a science or however one likes 
to describe it — which certain people undertake in definite social 
circumstances on behalf of definite interests. It is concerned with 
government, with the management of people by means of the control 
and direction of institutions. 

In politics divergent interests are pursued. It is a struggle between 
political rivals, each with his own policy or his own politics. And, 
underlying all other political divisions, there are always the divisions 
of class interests. For the most part politics consists of a complicated 
game of move and counter-move, in which each party seeks some 
immediate advantage or to avoid some immediate danger; and while 
all parties may claim a far-sighted vision of what they will achieve in 
the future, in practice they simply follow their noses as they smell out 
where their interest lies. The political struggle is waged in the name of 
all kinds of principles, ideals and universal ends. But in effect each party 
pursues its particular sectional interest. As Marx caustically observed 
in The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (Chapter 3) : “As in private 
life one differentiates between what a man thinks and says of himself 
and what he really is and does, so one must distinguish still more the 
phrases and fancies of parties from their real interests, their conception 
of themselves from their reality . . . Thus the Tories of England long 
imagined they were enthusiastic about Monarchy, Church and the 
beauties of the old English Constitution, until the day of danger wrung 
from them the confession that they are only enthusiastic about 
rent. 

Political parties, in the form of more or less permanent organisa- 
tions with membership, officials, programme and rules, are products of 



SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


173 


modem democracy. Combinations of place-seekers are as old as 
government itself. But with democratic institutions, rulers and would- 
be rulers had to do more than gang up together in order to rule. In 
many cases they have felt and (judging from television performances) 
some continue to feel the same disdain for the electorate as Shakespeare 
depicted Coriolanus as feeling when he had to “stand here and beg 
of Hob and Dick” and wished the plebs would “wash their faces and 
keep their teeth clean”. But more astute than Coriolanus, they have 
managed to build party organisations to nominate rulers, campaign 
for support of them, and make Hob, Dick and their wives think their 
views are being consulted. 

Parties are not necessarily formed with the open intention of promot- 
ing the interests of any one class. But they can be neither stable nor 
long-lasting except as political organisations of a class. A party which 
no interest could regard as its own would stand little chance in politics 
compared with the parties of each interest. For only when the ideas of a 
party and the policies it carries out correspond near enough to a class 
interest is the support forthcoming to maintain the party organisation. 
A party is kept up by a class interest, and bases its practical calculations 
of policy on the promotion of that interest in interaction with others. 
Hence the complicated interplay between politicians concerned with 
office and citizens concerned with the uses to which the power of 
office is put, leads to the result that a class sets up its own political 
parties, and political parties act as the political representatives of 
classes. By means of politics a class promotes its economic interest, and 
by the control of political power establishes and augments its economic 
power. 

In these conditions Marx and Engels stated, as long ago as 1850 in 
the Address of the Central Committee to the Communist League , the need 
“to establish an independent . . . workers' party and make each section 
the central point and nucleus of workers' societies in which the 
attitude and interests of the proletariat will be discussed independently 
of bourgeois influences”. 

The object of political parties is power — to hold office in the power- 
institutions so as to carry out a policy. Without a political party a class 
cannot win power. Various organisations which work for the economic 
interest of a class, or which in connection with this or that item of 
public policy aim at bringing pressure to bear on those who hold 
power, or which undertake ideological and cultural work, are of vital 
importance in the life of a class. But their action is dispersed and, with- 


174 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


out a political party, does not add up to a struggle for power. So a 
class which is to come to power, and so be able to transform society in 
its own image and in its own interests, must organise politically. 
Accordingly in Rule 7 a of the First International, drafted by Marx 
and adopted at The Hague Congress in 1872, it was laid down that “in 
its struggle against the collective power of the possessing classes the 
proletariat can act as a class only by constituting itself a distinct political 
party, opposed to all the old parties formed by the possessing classes”. 

Politics is often described as a dogfight: the introduction of science 
into this dogfight was a consequence of the birth of the working-class 
movement and of socialist politics. The working-class movement 
brought something new into politics, because it meant that for the 
first time the masses of working people could constitute a permanently 
organised political force in opposition to their rulers, and this in turn 
meant new forms of democratic organisation and new ideas of demo- 
cratic government. To begin with, the working-class organisations 
tended to seek no' more than immediate demands for improved work- 
ing and living conditions, and to support one or other of the traditional 
ruling parties in pursuit of these. But with working-class organisation, 
itself the natural product of the development of modem forces of 
production, the aim became practical of finally doing away with all 
exploitation of man by man, and planning social production for the 
satisfaction of the needs of all. 

So the science of socialism was evolved, to demonstrate the practi- 
cality of this aim and the means to achieve it. The working-class 
movement could not successfully pursue its long-term interest unless 
it based its politics on science. 

The theory of scientific socialism had to be worked out and its 
fundamental principles stated; then to be learned, studied, applied, 
tested in practice and developed. The working out of the theory can be 
said to have been commissioned by the newborn working-class 
movement, in as much as it was that movement that needed the theory 
and groups of workers began to discuss the problems of revolutionary 
policy and organisation. But the synthesis of vast data drawn from 
experience into a scientific theory could not emerge as it were sponta- 
neously out of the mass movement itself, since it required long and 
exacting work of scientific research. This work could only be done by 
scholars, by intellectuals. The men who originally worked on the 
theory did not themselves work in factories or mines. But they could 
do the job only because they were aware of what went on in factories 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


175 


and mines, and devoted their activity entirely to the cause of the 
workers’ movement with which they identified themselves. They were 
able to create the theory of scientific socialism because, first, they were 
from the outset concerned with the injustices and contradictions of 
society as they found it and were resolved to fmd a solution; second, 
they could draw on the past heritage of progressive science and 
philosophy and could see at the same time the insufficiency of past 
ideas to the present problems; and third, they recognised in the 
working-class movement the movement of the future. The founders 
of scientific socialism were not separate from the working-class 
movement, teachers who stepped in to give instruction, but workers 
in it and leaders of it. They worked out the theory for the movement, 
introduced it into the movement, and then fought for its acceptance 
and understanding. 

Scientific socialism, like other scientific theory, can only be 
developed in its use. Its development could take place only in the 
working-class movement, and the movement could only become 
united and capable of achieving political power when it had made the 
theory of scientific socialism its own. A political party is the only 
organisation which can thus carry science into the movement. And 
only by doing so can a political party provide the political leadership 
for the mass movement to win power and build socialism. 

A working-class party should consciously set out to serve the 
interests of the class. As Marx and Engels made clear in The Communist 
Manifesto , this does not mean, in the case of a party capable of leading 
the class to win power, that it bases its policy on nothing but the 
clamour of immediate and sectional demands, but that it “brings to 
the front the common interest” and “in the movement of the present 
takes care of the future of the movement”. 

The party’s standpoint is a class standpoint. It does not claim to adopt 
a god’s-eye point of view in forming its judgments, but the point of 
view of the working class. This does not mean, however, that the 
party accepts the ideas of workers, whatever they may be. On the 
contrary, many ideas in workers’ heads are implanted there by their 
rulers, or are merely the crude reflections of degrading conditions of 
life and help to perpetuate them. So the workers’ party must try to 
lead workers to change their ideas. For Marxism, a class standpoint in 
ideas is not the mere echo of the ideas which most members of a class 
happen to entertain at a particular time and place. A class standpoint in 
ideas means developing ideas in conformity with the objective require- 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


I76 

ments of the class for developing its way of life, its means of liveli- 
hood. 

In The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (Chapter 3) Marx 
explained that “the relation between the political representatives of a 
class and the class they represent” consists in the fact that the former 
work out in their ideas “the same problems and solutions to which 
material interests and social position drive the latter practically”. In 
the case of the political representatives of the small-trading class, about 
whom Marx was writing, he concluded that this meant that “in their 
minds they do not get beyond the limits which the class does not get 
beyond in life”. In the case of working-class ideas it is not so much a 
matter of not getting beyond limits as of getting beyond them. 
Whether most workers know it or not, the “problems and solutions 
to which material interests and social position” drive the working 
class are problems of escaping from exploitation and solutions by 
making social production serve social welfare. And these are the 
problems and solutions which the political representatives of the class 
have to work out in ideas. Whereas the other classes are driven to try 
to keep inside the limits within which they live, and their political 
representatives wear blinkers so as not to see beyond them, the work- 
ing class is driven to try to get out of the limits within which it lives, 
and the job of its political representatives is to think out the corres- 
ponding problems, the solution of which demands the strict metho- 
dology of science. 

Marx maintained, then, that a successful political party of the 
working class must make itself the bearer of scientific socialist theory, 
and must preserve it, work it out and introduce it, and the practice of 
being guided by it, into the entire working-class movement. Thus it 
must become the vehicle for achieving what he maintained was the 
first essential for the victory of socialism — the combination of scientific 
socialism with the mass working-class movement. 

Scientific inquiry always discloses possibilities for human action. For 
those interested, it tells how to do things they did not know how to do 
before. It makes possible practical achievements scarcely dreamed of, 
because it discloses the actual conditions for these things being brought 
about and how to bring them about. 

Marxist science shows the working classes how it is possible to achieve 
emancipation . This was not known before social relations were in- 
vestigated scientifically and the laws of development of society 
disclosed. Marxist science shows the necessary conditions for emancipa- 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


177 


tion — and one of the conditions is that the movement should base its 
practice on scientific theory and that “socialism should become a 
science”. 

Marxism shows further that the emancipation movement of the 
modem working classes is the final phase of a series of class struggles 
which began when the development of property first divided society 
into antagonistic classes. Summing up the conclusions of The Com - 
munist Manifesto in his Preface to the 1888 English edition, Engels 
wrote: “The history of class struggles forms a series of evolutions in 
which, today, the stage has been reached where the exploited and 
oppressed class — the proletariat— cannot attain its emancipation from 
the sway of the exploiting and ruling class — the bourgeoisie — without, 
at the same time, and once for all, emancipating society at large from 
all exploitation, oppression, class distinction and class struggles.” 
Emancipation has its necessary conditions, and its practical possibility 
can only be realised if action, based on scientific appreciation of 
necessity, observes them. One such condition is the waging of class 
struggle. Another is to carry on the struggle to the point where “all 
exploitation, oppression, class distinction and class struggles” are 
deliberately removed. 

Marxist science, then, applies in politics because it works out how to 
win working-class emancipation and thereby emancipate the whole of society. 

Now of course, a scientific demonstration is — a demonstration. If 
it is valid it is valid not only for some people but for everyone, just 
as if a statement is true it is true, whether anyone chooses to believe 
it or not. Nevertheless, it is only for the working classes that Marxist 
science demonstrates how to win emancipation, because they are the 
people who need it and are interested in it. That does not mean that 
it true only for one class and not for another. It is true for anyone, but 
not everyone is interested in this truth. It shows the possibility to those 
interested in it and whose action is required to realise it. What Marxism 
says is as true for the ruling classes as for the working classes, as the 
former occasionally find to their cost. But while it shows the working 
classes how to do away with exploitation, far from showing the 
ruling classes how to perpetuate exploitation it shows that to do so is 
impossible — and this truth is not and cannot be acceptable to them. 
Naturally, therefore, social science , with its applicability in politics , 
becomes a “class” science. This is another and very important way in 
which, as Marx well understood, it differs in its methods and applica- 
tion from the natural sciences. 


178 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


3. CONDUCT AND AIMS OF MARXIST POLITICAL PARTIES 

According to Dr. Popper, Marxism applies (or claims to apply) in 
politics by demonstrating, not what it is possible to do, but what must 
inevitably take place. Dr. Popper's Marxists base politics on prophecy. 
They are a kind of political astronomers. For just as astronomers might 
say: “There is going to be an eclipse of the sun, so turn on the lights", 
Dr. Popper’s Marxists say: “The revolution is coming, so close the 
ranks." 

But in politics one has to reckon, first and foremost, with facts, with 
actual circumstances and their practicalities. The object of politics is to 
alter circumstances. What Marxists actually base politics on is a 
scientific analysis of the circumstances in modern society. Marx 
scientifically investigated the character of capitalist exploitation and 
its effects, thus demonstrating the issues of the class struggle in modem 
society and the real and practical possibilities and alternatives for the 
alteration of our circumstances which this poses. Either capitalism 
continues with all its consequences in the perpetuation of poverty, 
conflicts, oppressions and wars, or the working class carries on its 
class struggle to the point of overcoming capitalism and building 
socialism. Marxism scientifically demonstrates the necessary conditions 
for the latter. Emancipation from all exploitation and class struggles 
can be achieved, and can only be achieved, through the dictatorship 
of the proletariat. And so Marxism further works out the practical 
strategy and tactics of the struggle for working-class power and 
becomes the guiding theory of revolutionary political parties. 

Dr. Popper regards as highly unscientific the Marxist way of 
understanding politics in terms of class struggle. Leaving the classes 
out of account, he presents politics instead in simple terms of “power" 
and control of power. Some people acquire power over others, so as 
to act as rulers ; and politics is a matter of the acquisition of this power, 
and of its use and the control of its use. Men almost invariably abuse 
power unless their use of it is controlled. The most important thing in 
politics is therefore to control the use of power, for the ruled to find 
how to control the rulers so as to stop abuses of power. Democratic 
politics is, he says, the politics of the control of the rulers by the 
ruled. 

From this point of view, he expatiates in scarifying terms about the 
political consequences of the Marxist error of basing politics on 
prophecy. Marxists believe themselves destined to come to power. 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


179 


They therefore brush aside all questions of the democratic control of 
power and advocate dictatorship. If they succeed in their violent 
endeavours to achieve what they believe to be the decree of destiny, 
what happens is that a group of men, or perhaps a single “strong 
man”, is put into power and all control over power collapses. But as 
Lord Acton warned: “All power corrupts, and absolute power 
corrupts absolutely.” What we inevitably get is a violent dictatorship, 
or tyranny. There ensues “the rule of the strong man” (2-OS. 151), 
who proceeds forcibly “to control and stereotype interests and beliefs” 
(PH. 90), sets up “the Inquisition, the Secret Police” (i-OS. 200), and 
“civilisation disappears” (CR. 344). 

I shall discuss in subsequent chapters, and in some detail, questions 
about democracy and dictatorship, and about the democratic principles 
concerning the conduct of popular organisations and their control over 
state power for the purposes of the dictatorship of the proletariat, 
which are implied by Marxism contrary to what Dr. Popper alleges. 
Here it may suffice to say that Dr. Popper talks of “power” and 
“control of power” in abstraction from the actual conditions of class 
interests and class struggles under which power is acquired, exercised 
and controlled. Marxism, on the other hand, in the discussion of 
political as of all other questions, undertakes “the concrete analysis of 
concrete conditions”. Dr. Popper adopts a very abstract conception of 
political power, as the power of some individuals (the rulers) over 
other individuals (the ruled). He opposes this as “science” to Marx’s 
political analysis of class struggles, which he calls “prophecy”. Such a 
comparison only demonstrates Dr. Popper’s own disregard for scientific 
method when it comes to discussing politics. 

According to Marx, politics in class-divided society is class struggle. 
Political parties represent the interests of classes, and the control and 
acquisition of power by political parties serves class interests. A work- 
ing-class party must seek to win political power, and to organise 
control over power and use power to reconstitute society on the basis 
of socialism. Working-class political parties can and must lead the 
masses of the people to the building of a new world, in struggle against 
the old. Their politics consists in giving political leadership in the 
struggle to end exploitation of man by man. 

By and large, this is what political parties that base their policies on 
Marxism have done and are doing. Marxists have hammered out in 
practice guiding fines for the conduct of effective working-class parties. 
The party must not only educate people in socialist ideas, but cam- 


i8o 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


paign for socialist policies, agitating on the job and in the localities 
against every injustice, giving practical leadership in mass organisation; 
and when power is won, the party becomes itself the leading mass 
organisation through which power is both exercised and controlled. 
The party must train up the leading personnel, the individual leaders, 
whom the movement can trust in the fight against the exploiting 
classes, and whom it can entrust with office when the power of the 
exploiting classes is broken. 

Dr. Popper expresses strong objections to the activities of Marxist 
political parties — though naturally enough, none of his objections is 
new. According to him, any political party that bases its policies on 
Marxism is outside the pale in a civilised community. The tolerance 
which democrats in principle extend to the expression of opinions 
should never be stretched to countenancing the subversive activities of 
Communists. For “in a democracy the full protection of minorities 
should not extend to those who violate the law, and especially not to 
those who incite others to the violent overthrow of the democracy” 
(2-OS. 161). Communists, believing that their own dictatorship is 
decreed by fate and will represent the consummation of mankind’s 
historical destiny, care nothing for laws and proceed lawlessly and 
violently to attempt to fulfil what they consider to be their historical 
mission. Worse still, if such parties get into power they proceed to 
“stereotype interests and beliefs” and to introduce “the Inquisition, 
the Secret Police”. They ought to be firmly put down. 

We must, of course, plead guilty to opposing laws which protect 
exploiting classes. But as for lawlessness and violence, to establish 
socialism does not entail replacing law by lawless violence but the 
reform of laws. Again, in building a socialist society “interests” will 
certainly be “stereotyped” to the extent that the diversity of interests 
as between capitalists and wage-workers, and as between competing 
capitalists, will disappear and a greater community of interests will 
emerge. Through education and propaganda the authorities must 
certainly endeavour to propagate beliefs corresponding to socialist 
interests and to oppose beliefs counter to them. And a police force 
must certainly be maintained strong enough to defend the socialist 
regime against attempts to disrupt or overthrow it. The objections, 
however, are to fighting against exploitation, to laws which prohibit 
exploitation, to opposing cherished beliefs of the old order accustomed 
to the full protection of the establishment, and to taking police measures 
to protect the new. 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


181 


But at the same time as he echoes all the customary execrations of 
anti-Communist propaganda, Dr. Popper still contrives to preserve an 
air of scientific objectivity. He does not say that Communists are evil- 
minded persons intent on getting power for themselves and injuring 
their fellow men. On the contrary, he stresses again and again that 
many Communists are sincere and mean well, and that their aim is 
universal happiness. The evil happens because the actual effects of 
acting on Communist principles are vastly different from Communist 
intentions. They intend to bring “heaven on earth”, but “only succeed 
in making it a hell”. The critique of Marxism is a case of “analysing 
the unintended repercussions of intentional human actions”. Quite 
inevitably or, at all events, by the objective sequence of cause and 
effect, the effect of basing politics on Marxist theory is that the actions 
taken bring evil consequences. 

The effect of Marx’s alleged belief in historical destiny, Dr. Popper 
suggests, is to make Communists think themselves infallible, chosen by 
fate to fulfil a mission and destroy every opponent. Communists will 
therefore listen to no criticism, pity no suffering, and spare no violence 
to attain their ends. They scorn all methods of democracy which entail 
consultation, discussion and paying attention to what other people say, 
and instead favour and themselves fall victims to the open terrorist 
dictatorship of a Communist “strong man” or group of power- 
hungry leaders. 

That, he evidently thinks, is what happened in the Soviet Union — 
an awful warning to the rest of mankind. There a “strong man” was 
placed in supreme power. Stalin’s word was law, and any criticism of 
his policies, and even the least doubt, was treated as a hostile act. His 
secret police engaged in arbitrary arrests, imprisonment without trial 
or the rigging of trials, cruelties, tortures and executions. 

That all was not well in the Soviet Union, and that evils were 
perpetrated by Communists, causing great and unnecessary suffering 
to thousands of individuals, is an established fact. Dr. Popper would 
give us to understand that such evils are inevitable . It is he himself, 
indeed, with his “unforeseen consequences”, who tries to confound 
us with a doctrine of inevitability — the inevitability of the disappoint- 
ment of revolutionary socialist hopes which, if they are not crushed 
by defeat, are even more completely frustrated by the tyranny which 
inevitably takes over after a revolutionary victory. But of course, 
Dr. Popper is no “bistoricist”. He only makes a “conditional 
prediction”: If you put a ketde on the fire it will boil, and if you let 


182 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


Marxists get into the government they will turn it into a bloodthirsty 
tyranny. 

What Marxists derive from the Marxist theory of social relations 
and of how social changes are brought about is, however, a practical aim 
for political action, and the strategy and tactics of political struggle, 
derived from knowledge of the necessary conditions for realising the 
aim. Socialism is presented by Marxism as a political programme. 
And Marxism is scientific socialism because it works out the socialist 
political programme on the basis of an objective review of facts, and 
not of any mythology about the destiny of mankind ; and because it 
makes proposals for satisfying real interests rather than for realising a 
utopian ideal. 

Marx and Engels said that “history is the history of class struggles”. 
This statement, true of history ever since class divisions appeared in 
human society, is incompatible with any “historicist” doctrine about 
events moving with inexorable necessity in accordance with a pre-set 
pattern. For class struggles are waged by human individuals, in the 
conditions of the social relations in which they find themselves. As 
Marx and Engels recognised whenever they set themselves to describe 
any actual class struggle, the actual events proceed from the action of 
the personalities and passions of the individuals engaged in them, 
conditioned by and operating in the given circumstances of the time. 
As for the role of working-class parties in events, what they do is 
affected by their circumstances and stage of political development, 
including their illusions, mistakes, uncertainties, fears and fanaticisms, 
and not by decrees of destiny of which they have been vouchsafed 
infallible knowledge. How well they succeed in their aims, and what 
mistakes they commit and setbacks they experience in pursuit of them, 
is decided by a multitude of human causes, which historians can trace 
out if they look for them. 

To win through to emancipation, people must organise and must 
learn from experience. From this element of political necessity comes the 
vital role of working-class political parties. First, the party must become 
the well-organised leadership of the whole movement. It must lead, not 
by continually disputing the right to exist of other parties and by 
establishing a political monopoly (for, as The Communist Manifesto 
declared, “the Communists do not form a separate party opposed to 
other working-class parties”), but by virtue (as the Manifesto expressed 
it) of “clearly understanding the line of march, the conditions, and 
the ultimate general results of the proletarian movement”. Second, the 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


I8 3 

party must concentrate in itself the lessons of the movement’s experience , 
so that through it the whole movement learns by experience and learns 
from mistakes . Only in a political party does the movement create 
leadership and a leadership that learns systematically. 

Marxists have always been at great pains to examine and to classify 
the various types of mistake to which working-class political parties 
may be prone. A party may sell out the workers’ interests by com- 
promising with exploiting classes, even to the extent of upholding 
their interests against those of the workers ; on the other hand, it may 
be so “ uncompromising” that, proclaiming mere revolutionary 
phrases, refusing to take circumstances into account, neglecting to 
build solid organisation and to find allies, it leads the workers to 
defeat. A party may give up or “revise” the theory of Marxism about 
the class struggle and the dictatorship of the proletariat; on the other 
hand, it may turn it into a mere dogma, into a mere set of formulas 
supposedly applicable in the same way at all times and in all circum- 
stances. Again, a party may lead the workers of one nation into 
conflict with those of another by placing what are represented as 
national interests before those of the common interests of all working 
people; on the other hand, it may alienate itself from its own people 
by not recognising, or even despising, their national interests and 
sentiments. There are examples enough of all these sorts of mistakes. 
They arise from the difficulties and dilemmas of the actual conditions 
of practical struggle. 

It is natural enough (and one might say, indeed, inevitable) that 
when Marxist parties make mistakes and get into difficulties their 
enemies are quick to proclaim that whatever evils ensue are all the 
fault of Marxism, and go on proclaiming it for years afterwards. More 
than that, when Marxist parties proceed to put right their mistakes, 
their enemies see the chance of scoring a further point and exclaim : 
Aha, you admit then that your Marxism did you no good and only 
led you into errors ! 

So it was with the abuses of power, accompanying some mistakes 
in economic policies, which took place in the Soviet Union under 
Stalin’s leadership. No Communist and no Marxist is going to make 
excuses for the evils that then took place. There took place distortions 
of Marxist theory, mistakes in economic management, bureaucratic 
brutalities, arbitrariness and crimes in methods of government, which 
hindered not helped the building of socialism. They could not have 
taken place except as a result of abuses of power by individuals, 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


184 

violations of the rule of law, and violations of the democratic conduct 
of revolutionary organisations, including the leading one, the Com- 
munist Party. Dr. Popper censures them no more severely than was 
done subsequently at the Twentiedi Congress of the Communist 
Party of the Soviet Union. But unlike the Marxists, he makes no 
attempt at analysing in what exactly these evils consisted, how they 
came about, or what was the remedy. He leaves out of accoimt every 
consideration about how violence of every kind is instigated and 
organised on a mass scale by fascism and imperialism, and instead 
denounces violence as the inevitable consequence of the Marxist 
doctrine of dictator ship”. He then concludes that the universal 
remedy is ‘‘democracy” on the model of the frequently violent and 
dictatorial practice of the so-called “free world”. 

He may perhaps claim credit for denouncing bad practices for 
which M?;xists were responsible at a time when Marxists failed to 
denounce or to remedy them. Let him ! Marxists claim credit for the 
fact that, amid bitter struggle against both internal and external 
enemies, socialism was built in the Soviet Union and established on a 
firm foundation which completely confoimds all the prognostications 
of anti-Marxists. Outside the Soviet Union we claim the credit that 
we gave the one socialist country unstinting support, opposed its 
enemies and refused to join them, and fought the injustices, oppressions 
and violence of capitalism even though this involved us in the guilt 
of injustices, oppressions and violence on our own side. Finally, 
Marxists claim credit for setting to work to get evils which took place 
under socialism put right — not by the method which many have 
advised as the remedy for “tyranny”, namely, overthrowing socialist 
government, but by bringing the methods of socialist government 
into line with the teacliings of Marxism. This reforming process is still 
going on hi the Soviet Union, though not smoothly or without con- 
flicts, setbacks, errors and injustices. 

Dr. Popper apparently regarded malpractices in the Soviet Union, 
at the time he wrote The Open Society and its Enemies and The Poverty 
of Historicism f as verifications of his assertion that Marxism means 
tyranny. The exposure of these malpractices at the Twentieth Congress 
of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union might then be regarded 
as a final verification from evidence presented by Marxists themselves. 
But Dr. Popper has insisted that what counts is not verification but 
falsification. And what has actually happened has finally falsified his 
allegations. He could cite various facts as “confirmations” of his 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


185 

assertion that Communist government is tyrannical. The actual 
development of socialism and the struggle for socialism falsifies it. 
And the actual teachings of Marx likewise falsify his allegations that 
Marxism is a doctrine of historical destiny which advocates violence 
and tyranny. 

A rational judgment on Marxist politics can only be reached by 
taking cognisance, among other things, of the history of Marxist 
parties — what they have done and are doing. Insisting on the fallacy 
of “the historical method”, Dr. Popper seems to prefer to base his 
judgment rather on a sweeping assessment of what he takes to be the 
essence of Marxist teachings. Essentially, he says, Marxism is dogmatic 
and anti-democratic. As he himself has explained is usual with judg- 
ments about “essences”, he then contrives to argue in a way to evade 
falsification. If a Marxist party is guilty of wrong doing, it is said to 
be acting in character ; if it does well, then it is merely acting out of 
character. 

Yet the way Marxist parties actually behave and develop gives the 
lie to what he says about Marxist politics. He in fact cites very little 
about what Marxist parties have actually done to prove his points. 
His chief citation is worthy of a passing remark, however. He deals 
at some length with the policies of Marxist parties towards fascism 
at the time of the rise of Hitler to power in Germany, and informs us 
that “the Communists did not fight when the fascists seized power” 
because they thought the fascist dictatorship “could only bring the 
revolution nearer . . . After all, since the revolution was bound to 
come, fascism could only be one of the means of bringing it about” 
(2-OS. 164-5). 

Admittedly, a certain amount of “falsification of history” has on 
occasion been done by Marxists themselves, for polemical purposes 
(though such polemics do not advance the cause of Marxism). Bad 
as this was, it bears little comparison with the falsification of history 
by anti-Marxists, of which the above citation provides an example. 
The Marxist method of studying what happens puts the record 
straight, where it is falsified by anti-Communist propaganda. 

The history of the international labour movement shows that the 
progress of Marxist parties is by no means the triumphal progress of 
the infallible “Party Line” which might be deduced from the doctrine 
of historical destiny Dr. Popper tries to foist onto us. There are many 
mistakes and many setbacks, as might be expected in real life. At the 
same time, the Marxist view that “history is on our side”, or that 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


18 6 

Marxist parties are indestructible and sure to win in the end, is justified 
by the actual conditions of class struggle in the modern world. For 
in general, what is necessary to be done gets done in the end. And in the 
conditions of capitalism, the development of revolutionary parties 
and the persistence of their activities up to the eventual abolition of 
exploitation of man by man is a necessity. To oppose exploitation, to 
oppose oppression, to oppose war, to oppose the threat of nuclear 
war today, and to carry on economic and political struggle until 
society is so ordered as to be able to use human resources for human 
welfare, is a necessity. We must organise for these purposes. If mistakes 
are made, they must be put right. If defeats are sustained, the struggle 
must still go on. 

So it is that in the European labour movement the dominance of 
reformist policies has of necessity been countered by the rise of genuine 
revolutionary parties, the Communist Parties. The victory of the 
Russian Revolution was a decisive factor leading to the growth and 
consolidation of the international Communist movement, and to the 
development of the great movement for liberation from imperialism 
throughout the colonial world. Conditions are always changing with 
time, however. And they are not the same now as they were before 
the Second World War. We have to frame new policies accordingly. 
In this connection deep divisions and splits appear over policies — 
including, at the moment, a division within the world Communist 
movement, turning to a great extent on questions of peace and the 
coexistence of socialism and capitalism, on methods of transition to 
socialism and the strategy of the anti-imperialist national liberation 
movement. 

There never was and there is not now a ready-made “doctrine” to 
cling to, nor a leadership appointed by destiny to lead us on a straight 
path and preserve us from error. What has to be relied on, now as 
always, is the development of clear-headed scientific thinking about 
policies, taking circumstances and changes of circumstances into 
account. From this we have to build up the unity in action of 
the left. On democratic counsel and organisation to build competent 
revolutionary parties chiefly depends the destiny of mankind — 
the overcoming of exploitation of man by man and, as Marx 
put it, the duration and severity of “the birth pangs” of a new 
world. 

The point is that the capitalist mode of production, with capitalist 
economic and political power, cannot but engender a struggle against 


SCIENCE APPLIED TO POLITICS 


I87 

it by exploited classes; that this struggle has got to find leadership; 
that Marxism embodies scientific principles of leadership; and 
that therefore what has to be done is build Marxist parties and out 
of hard and often bitter experience develop Marxism in theory and 
practice. 


3 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 

I. HAS CAPITALISM DISAPPEARED? 

Marxism applies in the practice of the working-class movement as a 
practical policy for breaking the fetters capitalism puts on social 
production and developing production to the full to meet human 
needs. Dr. Popper, however, not only calls science prophecy and a 
practical political policy utopia, but adds that there is no longer any 
point in wanting to abolish capitalism because it has ceased to exist 
anyway. His criticism thus devastates at all points. Marx is shown to 
have been a singularly unfortunate prophet, because the evils whose 
destruction he prophesied have long since been quietly removed by 
means quite other than fire and brimstone. 

“We must be on our guard”, Dr. Popper writes, “against . . . the 
Marxist prejudice that socialism or communism is the only alternative 
and the only possible successor to capitalism. Neither Marx nor anyone 
else has ever shown that socialism ... is the only possible alternative 
to the ruthless exploitation of that economic system which he first 
described a century ago and to which he gave the name ‘capitalism*. 
And indeed, if anybody were attempting to prove that socialism is the 
only possible successor to Marx’s unrestrained capitalism, then we 
could simply refute him by pointing to historical facts. For laissez 
faire has disappeared from the face of the earth, but it has not been 
replaced by a socialist or communist system as Marx understood it” 
(2-OS. 140). The “unrestrained capitalism” which Marx denounced 
has, says Dr. Popper, “given way ... to our own period of political 
interventionism, of the economic interference of the state”. For “all 
over the earth, organised political power has begun to perform far- 
reaching economic functions”. 

Marxists have for long maintained that in the normal course of 
economic development capitalism passes from an earlier condition of 
free competition to a stage of monopoly or state-monopoly capitalism, 
which was entered into by the older capitalist economies from the 
beginning of this century. This account of normal capitalist economic 
development is founded on Marx’s own account of the processes of 
centralisation and concentration of capital, and of the development 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


I89 

of the finance and credit system, under conditions of free competition, 
as a result of which free competition gives rise to monopoly. A 
marked feature of monopoly capitalism, according to Marxist views, 
is “the economic interference of the state”, which Dr. Popper 
nevertheless tells us is now supplanting what Marx earlier described 
and denounced as capitalism. 

Dr. Popper evidently thinks that all Marx achieved in Capital was 
to describe, fairly faithfully, the “unrestrained capitalism” of a century 
ago. Marx did indeed describe it. He described how men and women 
worked a twelve- or fourteen-hour day under unhealthy conditions in 
factories, while the owners engaged one another in cut-throat com- 
petition. Today die scene has changed. In many industries there is a 
forty-hour week (with plenty of bonus earnings and overtime at 
time-and-a-half or double time), health and safety regulations are 
enforced and, far from there being lots of competing individual 
masters, industries are dominated by a few great corporations. No 
longer do capitalists sit jingling their moneybags in dingy counting 
houses, where portraits of Grandfather Nathaniel and Great-uncle 
Ebenezer look down with grim approval upon the squalid scene, but 
members of a managerial elite play the power-game in spacious 
apartments decorated with works of abstract art. Hence, says, Dr. 
Popper, what Marx described no longer exists, and his entire analysis 
is of no more than historical interest. Marx takes his place with 
Charles Dickens as one of the great Victorians who, in their time, 
goaded the public conscience by exposing social evils, but now gladden 
the philistines with the sense of satisfaction that things are not like 
that with us. 

But what Marx achieved in Capital was not simply a description of 
industrial conditions which soon became out of date as conditions 
changed. Marx laid bare the social relations which develop under 
capitalism, the capitalist relations of production , the mode of exploiting 
wage-labour on which the whole economic structure depends. He 
extracted these relations from the total mass of social activities in the 
midst of which individuals are related by them — extracted them not, 
as he put it, by means of chemical reagents or by fixing them under a 
microscope, but by “force of abstraction” — and showed what they 
are and what they lead to. 

Marx made a most careful analysis of the production relations which 
develop when goods are produced as commodities. As Lenin pointed 
out in What the Friends of the People Are , “this analysis is strictly 


190 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


confined to the relations of production between the members of 
society. Without ever resorting to factors other than relations of 
production to explain the matter, Marx makes it possible to discern 
how the commodity organisation of society develops, how it becomes 
transformed into capitalist economy . . and, we may add, how the 
capitalist relations of production persist when laissez faire gives place 
to ‘ ‘inter ventionism”. “While explaining the structure and develop- 
ment of society exclusively in terms of relations of production,” 
Lenin continued, Marx “went on to trace the superstructure corres- 
ponding to these relations of production . . . Capital exhibited the 
whole capitalist social formation to the reader as a live thing.” 

True, it has not so exhibited it to Dr. Popper, because Dr. Popper 
prefers his own interpretation of what Marx was about. But Marx’s 
analysis of capitalist production relations shows how the economic 
and political conditions of a century ago developed, and it also shows 
how they have changed into the economic and political conditions of 
contemporary capitalism. It shows that it is still capitalism. That in 
the capitalist economies laissez faire has been largely replaced by 
“interventionism”, while “a socialist or communist system as Marx 
understood it” has not yet everywhere succeeded capitalism, is a 
very well-known fact. And something of the sort was predicted by 
Marx himself in Capital — a prediction Dr. Popper has chosen to 
overlook. In his mature years Marx recognised quite clearly that his 
youthful hopes that “the ruthless exploitation of that economic system 
which he first described” would be quickly overthrown were founded 
on an underestimation of the staying powers of the exploiters — though 
even so he might admittedly have been distressed to learn that they 
would keep going for as long as they have done. The “interventionism” 
of which Dr. Popper writes — economic interference by a state in 
which the big capitalists retain pretty firm control — is one of the 
principal means by which they have kept going, for they could 
hardly have succeeded without it. 

But that in the development of capitalism laissez faire is replaced 
by “economic interference of the state” does not imply either that 
capitalism has disappeared or that socialism is not “the only possible 
successor” to capitalism. On the contrary, as many Marxists, from 
Marx onwards, have observed, the fact that the increasing socialisation 
of the forces of production drives capitalists themselves to accept 
forms of public control only shows how necessary it is to convert the 
means of production into social property, and will, in the end, facilitate 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


191 

that process. Thus Marx wrote in Capital (Vol. 3, Chapter 27) that 
capital becomes “directly endowed with the form of social capital as 
distinct from private capital, and its undertakings assume the form of 
social undertakings as distinct from private undertakings. It is the 
abolition of capital as private property within the framework of 
capitalist production itself”. In this, he said, the functions of manage- 
ment become separated from ownership, and this in turn “is a necessary 
transitional phase” towards the conversion of capital “into the property 
of associated producers, as outright social property”. 

What does this change amount to? It was predicted and described 
with rather remarkable accuracy by Engels in Anti-Duhring (Part 3, 
Chapter 2). 

The “pressure of the productive forces, in their mighty upgrowth, 
against their character as capital,” he wrote, “. . . forces the capitalist 
class itself more and more to treat them as social productive forces, in 
so far as this is at all possible within the framew r ork of capitalist 
relations”. It brings about “that form of the socialisation of huge 
masses of means of production which we find in the various kinds of 
joint-stock companies ... At a certain stage of development even 
this form no longer suffices; the official representative of capitalist 
society, the state, is constrained to take over their management.” And 
increasingly, “the social functions of the capitalists are carried on by 
salaried employees”. 

But as Engels went on to say, this disappearance of laissez fair e 
does not mean the disappearance of capitalism. “Conversion into 
either joint-stock companies or state property does not deprive the 
productive forces of their character as capital. In the case of joint- 
stock companies this is obvious. And the modern state, too, is only 
the organisation with which bourgeois society provides itself in order 
to maintain the general external conditions of the capitalist mode of 
production against encroachments either by the workers or by 
individual capitalists. The modern state, whatever its form, is essentially 
a capitalist machine . . . The more productive forces it takes over, the 
more it becomes the real collective body of all the capitalists, the 
more citizens it exploits. The workers remain wage workers . . . the 
capitalist relation is not abolished.” 

The point is that the capitalist mode of production is one in which 
investments of privately-owned capital in enterprises employing wage- 
labour yield a profit to the capitalists, from which ever greater 
accumulations of privately-owned capital accrue. In order to preserve 


192 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


the conditions in which the capitalist mode of production can continue 
to function, it is necessary that not only wage-workers but capitalists 
too should be subjected to various kinds of direction and constraint. 
It is this which is provided by “the econo mic interference of the 
state”. But the fact that “organised pohtical power has begun to 
perform far-reacliing economic functions” does not mean that 
capitalism has disappeared but that, on the contrary, it is being preserved. 
And it is preserved for so long as the “interventionist” state remains 
“essentially a capitalist macliine”. 

It is clear, then, that Dr. Popper’s contention that the advent of 
“pohtical interventionism” refutes “the Marxist prejudice that socialism 
or communism is the only alternative and the only possible successor 
to capitalism” is simply another case of his refuting Marxism by 
making it mean sometliing other than what it says. Marx and Engels 
never said that “the only alternative” to laissez faire or “unrestrained 
capitalism” was “socialism or communism”. They said very clearly 
indeed that it would have to be replaced as capitalism developed by 
“pohtical interventionism” or “the economic interference of the 
state”. This is exactly what has happened, so what has happened has 
confirmed and not refuted Marx’s predictions about the development 
of capitalism. 


2. THE LABOUR THEORY OF VALUE 

Marx’s account of capitalist production relations exhibits the relation 
which people enter into with one another when they produce and 
exchange commodities , and when, in a commodity-producing society, 
some, as wage-earners, are forced to sell their own labour-power as a 
commodity. This relation is defined in terms of the so-called “labour 
theory of value”, which is thus fundamental in Marx’s analysis of the 
nature and development of capitalist production relations. 

Dr. Popper, having failed to grasp that in Capital Marx began with 
an abstract inquiry “strictly confined to the relations of production 
between the members of society”, and having thus missed the whole 
point of the inquiry, fails to see the point of the labour theory of 
value. “Marx’s theory of value, usually considered by Marxists as 
well as by anti-Marxists as a cornerstone of the Marxist creed, is in 
my opinion one of its rather unimportant points,” he writes (2-OS. 170). 
As usual, he presents Marxist theory in terms which make its alleged 
meaning puerile; so no wonder he thinks it “rather unimportant”. 


THE CRITIQUE OP CAPITALISM 


193 


On this question, however, the other “anti-Marxists” are right: the 
labour theory of value is indeed “a cornerstone” in Marx's theoretical 
model of capitalist production relations (called by Dr. Popper “the 
Marxist creed”). 

According to Dr. Popper, the labour theory of value was “intro- 
duced in order to explain the actual prices at which all commodities 
are exchanged”. Thus “you have to pay for the job, or for any 
commodity you may buy, roughly in proportion to the amount of 
work in it, i.e. to the number of labour hours necessary for its 
production”. Of course, “actual prices fluctuate. But there is, or so 
at least it appears, always something more stable behind these prices, 
a kind of average price about which the actual prices oscillate, christened 
the ‘exchange value' or briefly, the ‘value' of the thing. Using this 
general idea, Marx defined the value of a commodity as the average 
number of labour hours necessary for its production” (2-OS. 171). 

Thus Marx is represented as a sort of careful shopper, who wants 
to know why this should cost more than that, and to find some 
standard by which a fair price can always be determined. He is 
represented as simple-minded almost to the point of imbecility. For 
of course, as Dr. Popper goes on to say, to understand why prices 
fluctuate you need “a more concrete theory; a theory which shows, 
in any particular case, how the laws of supply and demand bring 
about the effect which has to be explained” (2-OS. 175). 

He therefore concludes: “But if these laws are sufficient to explain 
these effects, then we do not need the labour theory of value at all.” 
The whole labour theory of value is therefore “unimportant” and 
‘'‘redundant”. It is for this very reason, indeed, that all those sophis- 
ticated students of economic laws (whom Marx rather rudely called 
“vulgar”) who are interested in formulating equations expressing how 
this economic variable is a function of that, find that they have no 
use whatever for the labour theory of value and have consequently 
expelled it from their economic science as a sheer irrelevancy. 

Marx's primary interest, however, was not in the fluctuations of 
prices but in the formation, development and change of relations of 
production. He saw capitalism as an historically constituted system of 
relations of production brought into being in adaptation to a definite 
development of productive forces and then becoming an obstacle to 
their further development for the satisfaction of human needs. It was 
to define these relations of production and explain their formation and 
effects that he employed the labour theory of value. 


194 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


As regards “actual prices” and their fluctuations, Dr. Popper is 
right in saying “that Marx realised” that a “concrete theory” must 
needs include an explanation of “how the laws of supply and demand 
bring about the effect which has to be explained”. That does not 
imply that “the laws of supply and demand” constitute a complete 
explanation of the whole process of exchange of commodities, nor 
does it make the labour theory of value unimportant or redundant. 
The theory explains the formation and development of relations of 
production, and so is relevant to questions which Dr. Popper and the 
economists he thinks have superseded Marx do not even ask. They 
can explain to their own satisfaction the fluctuations of costs and 
prices (even though they cannot find how to control them). What 
they cannot explain, and ask no questions about, is the formation and 
character of the relations of production which give rise to the pheno- 
mena they seek to explain. They simply ignore, and bury out of sight, 
the character of the wages system and of the exploitation of labour 
in which capitalism consists. 

Marx began his investigation of capitalist production relations by 
observing that in capitalist production “wealth . . . presents itself as 
an immense accumulation of commodities” ( Critique of Political 
Economy , Chapter i; Capital , Vol. i, Chapter i). Thus he started by 
defining capitalism as a mode of commodity production. He then 
inquired into what commodity production is in general, so a$ to 
demonstrate how it develops into that specific mode of production 
which constitutes capitalism. He thus arrived at the definition of the 
specific character of capitalist production relations. 

In commodity production, individual producers or groups of 
producers do not simply produce things for their own use, but for 
exchange against other products for which they have a use. Com- 
modities are products of labour which, firstly, have a use (people 
want them for one purpose or another), and secondly are exchangeable 
for other products. Hence they have both use-value and exchange- 
value. And the labour which produces them has a dual character, as 
producing objects for use, but not immediately for use but for 
exchange. 

When people exchange commodities, what are they doing? What 
is the social relation they enter into with one another? This is the 
question to ask, in order to arrive at the definition of production 
relations. And, as usual with fundamental questions, the answer is 
pretty obvious. They are exchanging products of definite quantities of 


THE CRITIQUE OP CAPITALISM 


195 


labour. In conditions where people share certain forces of production, 
a norm naturally gets established of how many man-hours of labour 
are socially necessary to produce each commodity. Therefore in 
commodity production people enter into a relation with one another in which 
they exchange and acquire from one another products each of which embodies 
a definite quantity of socially necessary labour. The labour theory of 
value consists simply in stating this fact — abstracting and stating this 
fundamental production relation which remains constant amid all the 
variable relations into which people enter with one another and with 
external nature in commodity production. 

Besides its use-value, every commodity has an exchange-value 
independent of its particular use. Similarly, all labour, irrespective of 
its use — regardless of its materials and its instruments, and of the use 
to which people put its products, and the desirability of their use — has 
the common feature of producing goods and services for exchange. 
All the performances of social labour are alike in using up varying 
quantities of socially necessary labour for the production of goods and 
services for exchange, and all the products are alike in embodying 
varying quantities of labour socially necessary for their production. 

In other words, what all products have in common is that they embody 
a quantity of socially necessary labour. They can all be compared , therefore , 
in respect of how much socially necessary labour has gone into them. This 
common feature of commodities, quantitatively determined and 
measured in terms of units of labour-time, is used in the labour theory 
of value to define “value”. 

The labour theory of value is therefore stated in the form of a 
definition , the definition of “value”. But this definition is no mere 
“verbal” definition. It is no more merely verbal or conventional than 
are the definitions of basic concepts employed in any other sciences — 
for example, in mechanics. It serves to abstract and define the common 
feature of all commodities y in respect of which they can all be compared. 
There can, obviously, be no doubt whatever that commodities do 
have value, in the sense defined. If some economists prefer to use the 
word “value” in other ways, that does not affect the fundamental 
truth about production relations expressed in the labour theory of 
value. It only means that these economists prefer to overlook this 
fundamental truth. 

Clearly, as so defined, the “value” of a commodity is not a property 
of an object (like its weight, for example) which it possesses in- 
dependently of whatever people do, but appertains to commodities 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


196 

because people produce them by their labour and depends on how 
much labour they expend. And the value relation between commodities 
(i.e. that two or more commodities are of equal or unequal value) 
holds between them because of the social production relations of men , i.e. 
because men work to produce commodities and because in their 
work they have to devote varying amounts of socially necessary 
labour-time to producing various objects of use. 

In supposing that the labour theory of value was “introduced in 
order to explain the actual prices at which commodities are exchanged” 
Dr. Popper absurdly misunderstands the problem the definition of 
“value” was used to solve. The problem is not simply one of explaining 
the actual prices of commodities but of explaining the social relations 
in commodity-producing societies. This explanation is achieved in the 
labour theory of value. Things people need or want are produced by 
labour ; thanks to division of labour people have to exchange products 
of labour; hence products are produced as commodities; and in 
buying and selling them people are exchanging the embodiments of 
definite quantities of socially necessary labour-time. 

Having defined the value relation of commodities in terms of the 
labour socially necessary for their production, or in other words, 
in terms of the social relations in commodity-producing society, 
Marx was then able to show quite cogently how value enters into the 
determination of price. In pricing commodities people are not just 
affixing price-tags but arranging the exchange of the products of 
labour. The quantity of labour that has gone into the production of 
each commodity is, when people are exchanging products of labour, 
a constant determining factor present in every act of exchange. Other 
things being equal, the products of a given quantity of labour would 
be exchanged for products of an equal quantity of labour. But in 
actual practice, commodities do not generally exchange at their value, 
but such factors as “supply and demand” affect the actual prices at 
which they exchange. Marx accordingly dealt with “actual prices” in 
Capital by the method of assuming, first of all, that goods do exchange 
at their value, and then, by examining in detail the actual concrete 
conditions of production and exchange, demonstrating the factors 
which make them exchange otherwise than at their values and the 
economic consequences which ensue. 

Dr. Popper says that “the whole idea that there is something 
behind the prices, an objective or real or true value of which prices are 
only ‘a form of appearance’, shows clearly enough the influence of 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


197 


Platonic Idealism” (2-OS. 177). It shows nothing of the sort; it shows 
simply that attention is paid to basic and empirically verifiable social 
relations of production. And having paid attention to these relations 
of production — having abstracted them, defined them and verified 
them — Marx was then able to show how actual prices are determined 
in commodity-producing societies. Far from being a “redundant” 
concept or an example of “the influence of Platonic Idealism”, the 
concept of “value”, as defined by Marx, first of all refers to empirically 
verifiable relations which men enter into in producing commodities, 
and is then used to state laws about the way men exchange com- 
modities, and about the variations of the prices at which commodities 
are exchanged, which are likewise empirically verifiable. 

Besides this, the labour theory of value throws a good deal of light 
on social relations in commodity-producing societies, which remain 
hidden and unremarked on so long as the exchange of commodities 
is regarded as no more than a matter of some people bringing goods 
to market and others buying them there at the market price. In any 
society people engage in social production, and the total social product 
is divided up, in the process of distribution, between the members of 
society. Each gets his share of the total product of social labour in a 
way depending on the production relations. The labour theory of 
value poses the question of how this division is effected in commodity- 
producing societies, through the process of production and exchange. 
It poses the question of how the values produced by labour are 
appropriated, how much goes to the labourers, how much goes to 
others, and how those others get it. So the labour theory of value 
has the merit of directing attention beyond questions of “explaining 
actual prices” to questions about social labour and the appropriation 
of its products which are ignored by those who simply want to study 
price fluctuations. 

All this means developing political economy as a social science, 
that is, as an investigation of social relations . For Marxism, political 
economy is the investigation of the relations into which people enter 
in the production and distribution of their means of life. 

In the section of Capital headed “the fetishism of commodities” 
Marx criticised the approach to economic science which treated it as 
an investigation of the properties and relations of the products of 
economic activity — as though commodities possessed properties of 
exchanging with one another, and so of selling at various prices, 
independently of the social relations of the people who produce, 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


198 

exchange and consume such products. Like that, people’s activity is 
ruled by the economic relations between the things they produce and 
exchange, whereas in fact such relations between things are not 
inherent in things but are determined by the social relations of the 
people who produce and exchange them. Marx called this approach 
“fetishism” because of its resemblance to the attitude of savages who 
suppose that their lives are ruled by properties inherent in the fetishes 
they worship. 

By criticising the fetishism of commodities in terms of the labour 
theory of value Marx was able to direct attention to the production 
relations in commodity-producing societies. He was able to show 
under what conditions these develop into capitalist production 
relations, and then that capitalist production relations are relations of 
the exploitation of wage-labour by capital. Having shown that, he 
was able to show how this form of exploitation can and must be 
done away with. 


3. SURPLUS VALUE AND EXPLOITATION OF 
WAGE-LABOUR 

In terms of the labour theory of value Marx could define the specific 
new features of the production relations which distinguish capitalism 
from earlier modes of commodity production. 

In production, the labourer applies instruments of production to 
the materials of labour in order to fashion the product. In commodity 
production, this product is appropriated by whoever owns the materials 
and instruments, that is, the means of production. He is the owner, 
and it is he who is entitled to make a sale. In the simplest sort of 
commodity production, goods are sold by the people who make 
them. That is not so in capitalism. Capitalism arises only when the 
labourer has been deprived of ownership of means of production 
(Marx investigated in great detail how this happens historically). 
What distinguishes capitalism is wage-labour. The means of production 
are owned by the capitalist; the labourer has to work for wages with 
means of production which belong to someone else; and the product, 
together with the proceeds of its sale, is appropriated by the capitalist. 
It is the capitalist who sells it, and he hopes to make a profit on the 
sale. 

The progressive feature of capitalism is that in these conditions 
great numbers of workers are brought together to work under the 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


199 


direction of a single capitalist management, so that the individual 
labour of individual commodity-producers is replaced by socialised 
labour — a far more effective force of production. But in contradiction 
to the new socialised character of production there remains from the 
older forms of commodity production the private appropriation of 
the product by the owner of the means of production. 

Marx then demonstrated that in capitalism the worker who, not 
owning means of production, has no products of his labour to exchange 
for what else he needs to keep alive, has one thing of his own which 
he can sell — and that is his labour^power. The workers have to sell 
their labour-power to the capitalists. The capitalists, who own means 
of production, buy from the workers the use of their labour-power 
for a stipulated number of hours. The workers get wages, with which 
they can buy things they need ; and the capitalists get the products of 
their work, which they can sell at a profit. 

Where does the profit come from? Marx answered this question 
by the very simple demonstration that the total values the workers 
receive as wages are always less (much less) than the values they 
produce by their work and which are appropriated by the capitalists. 
Evidently, the value of the labour-power sold by the workers is 
equivalent to the quantity of labour necessary to produce all that the 
workers must consume in order to supply that labour-power. But 
the total quantity of work performed by the workers is considerably 
greater than the value of their own labour-power used up in producing 
it. This difference Marx called “surplus value”. The capitalists get 
their profits and accumulate capital out of the surplus value they 
obtain by employing workers for wages. 

Each capitalist does not, however, appropriate to himself the whole 
surplus value accruing from the employment of the labour he himself 
has hired. The capitalist has to borrow money from others, on which 
he must pay interest; he has to buy or hire things from others, and 
sell things to others — and the upshot of all these sorts of transactions 
is that the owners of capital are so linked together that what happens 
is not that each takes surplus value only from the workers in his own 
employ, and leaves die rest to other employers, but rather that the 
capitalist class as a whole appropriates surplus value from the labour 
force as a whole, and divides it up amongst the different capitalist 
claimants. 

Marx devoted many chapters of Capital to demonstrating the 
various ways in which the total of surplus value extracted from the 


200 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


I 


workers is divided up to be appropriated in the various forms of rent, 
interest and profit. If one considers contemporary capitalism, with 
its elaborate machinery of finance and credit, its shareholdings, its 
great corporations staffed by professional managements, and its 
“changing balance of public and private power”, Marx’s basic analysis 
continues to apply to it. For what is going on is still that wage-labour 
produces surplus value, out of which a wide variety of claims are 
met. Some of it is appropriated by public bodies for public purposes 
(by publicly-owned services and via taxation). It is a feature of con- 
temporary capitalism that a great deal of this public appropriation 
goes to pay bondholders and property speculators, and to subsidise 
privately-owned concerns. The rest continues to be privately appro- 
priated by the shrinking number of individuals who effectively 
remain the capitalist owners and masters of the means of social 
production. Some of it gets used for directors’ fees and managerial 
salaries, some is paid out as interest, dividends, and so forth — and some 
is reinvested in production. 

Capital accumulation is always made out of surplus value. The 
economic growth of the system depends on the continuous profitable 
investment and accumulation of capital. If capital is not growing and 
accumulating in this way, it is shrinking and values are being destroyed: 
it must expand or bust. The condition, therefore, for the conduct of 
production under capitalism is that the maximum of surplus value 
should be extracted out of the employment of wage-labour. “The 
aim of capitalist production”, wrote Marx ( Capital , Vol. i, Chapter 13), 
“is to extract the greatest possible amount of surplus value, and 
consequently to exploit labour-power to the greatest possible extent.” 

What characterises the system is that in every productive process 
so much value in labour-power is used up, in fashioning so much 
value in material with the aid of so much value in wear and tear of 
machinery and other instruments of production; so much value in 
products is consequently produced; and so much surplus value is 
consequently extracted. 

However, from the point of view of management (whether manage- 
ment of particular enterprises, or the sort of overall management 
which governments are now supposed to perform), the profitability 
of enterprise and the solvency of the economy as a whole depends on 
whether the sale of products does or does not cover costs, measured 
in money. In costs are included wages and salaries, materials, machinery, 
depreciation, costs of management, rent, interest on borrowed capital 


THE CRITIQUE OP CAPITALISM 


201 


— and also public works and social services. Management reckons and 
calculates, not in terms of quantities of socially necessary labour, but 
in terms of prices and costs — reckoning with indices of productivity, 
with borrowings and repayments, with finding sales outlets, with the 
division of income between personal expenditures and reinvestment, 
and so on. These are, naturally, the “concrete” things that concern it, 
and not such “abstract” matters as values, surplus value and the rate of 
surplus value. In general (as Marx showed), the wages-bill of a 
particular enterprise does not correspond to the value of the labour- 
power it buys, the sales income does not correspond to the value of 
the goods sold, and the profit does not correspond to the sum-total 
of surplus value extracted. Even if someone worked out the values, 
it would not assist the management in its practical calculations about 
costs and profits. Management, therefore, finds no employment for 
Marx’s conception of value. This conception was not, indeed, worked 
out with a view to assisting capitalist management, and therefore 
appears to it unimportant, redundant, irrelevant, and even a relic 
of Platonic Idealism. 

The majority of professional economists, who simply study indices 
of production, costs, prices, wages, investments, savings, national 
income, and so on, with a view to formulating equations which will 
cover their variations, can likewise find no employment for the 
labour theory of value. But evidently in this they are simply accom- 
modating themselves to the point of view and interest of capitalist 
management, to which they are trying to sell professional advice. 
And while many of the equations may be accurate, and the advice 
practical and businesslike, nevertheless, considered as social science, the 
whole undertaking is strangely defective. For production costs, wages, 
prices, and all the rest, are only the results of people having entered 
into definite relations of production, in which all labour is productive 
of exchange-values, and labour-power itself and all its products are 
exchange-values and so have their variable production costs, prices, 
and so on. 

When the economist has formulated his equations, he may claim 
to have explained that when this cost varies in one way that price 
varies in another way, and to advise the manager and legislator that 
if he can peg this variable he will be able thereby to keep another under 
control. However, he has neither defined nor explained the production 
relations into which people have entered. But it is only as a result of 
those production relations that the phenomena he studies occur at all. 


202 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


Many economists object to talking about values defined in terms of 
socially necessary labour, and to talking about surplus value, on the 
grounds that it is a mere abstraction. It is an abstraction, but not an 
unimportant, redundant or irrelevant one. Abstraction is necessary, 
but the important thing is to assemble the information gained from 
different modes of abstraction so as to reveal the real connections, 
portray what is actually going on, and comprehend its law of motion. 
That is dialectics — and it was as a dialectician that Marx had the 
advantage as a social scientist. 

As Lenin said, Marx abstracted for investigation “the relations of 
production between the members of society”, and having done so 
was able to show what happens in the development of the process of 
production and exchange. Capitalist managers and their economists, 
on the other hand, also abstract — they abstract operations of producing 
and consuming, buying and selling, managing and being managed, 
from the relations of production by entering into which people come 
to do these things. They pride themselves on dealing with nothing 
but observable and measurable variables; but it is their portrayal of 
the economic movement of society as nothing but the process of 
these variables which is in truth a mere abstraction. What is actually 
going on is that people are producing, exchanging and consuming 
the products of social labour. To see only movements of costs, prices, 
productivity, national incomes, and so forth, is to represent the 
economic process simply in terms of a set of abstractions and then to 
say: these are the economic process. 

Marx’s analysis in terms of the labour theory of value portrays 
capitalism for what it is, a particular historically-constituted mode of 
production, and distinguishes it from pre-capitalist economic forma- 
tions. It shows capitalism as a mode of production based on the 
exploitation of wage-labour, and clearly distinguishes this form of 
exploitation of labour from earlier forms. Thus it clearly defines 
capitalism in terms of basic social relations — a definition deplored as 
abstract and redundant by hard-headed managerial types, who do 
not like employees to be shown exactly how they are used for making 
profits for employers. 

Whereas Marx demonstrated that capitalist production exploits 
wage-labour, many economists and sociologists today, who regard 
production relations as mere abstractions, deny that wage-labour is 
exploited. Nowadays they do sometimes agree that it used to be 
exploited; but they deny that it is exploited any longer, for they 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


203 


simply pay no attention to the capitalist production relations. Thus, 
as Dr. Popper has assured us, the exploitation of labour was an evil 
of the old laissez faire system which modem “interventionism” has 
almost got rid of. 

According to this conception, the well-managed firm, which today 
enters into collective agreements with trade union officials, does not 
exploit its workers. A collective agreement is not exploitation; there 
is exploitation only if people are bullied and coerced. It is only the 
bad and selfish employer, who sacks shop stewards and undercuts the 
rate, who exploits labour — and he should be firmly dealt with by 
the interventionist authorities, though first it is necessary to deal with 
bad and selfish workers who persist in coming out on strike. 

Exploitation, according to Dr. Popper’s definition, consists of “long 
hours of work and low real wages” (2-OS. 169). And have not hours 
of work been reduced, and real wages raised? And would not real 
wages be raised still further if only workers would get rid of the idea 
that they must resist exploitation and instead devote themselves to 
increasing productivity by resisting restrictive practices? The fact is, 
however, that the modern well-managed firm probably extracts a 
higher rate of surplus value than does its less efficient rate-cutting 
competitor. As Marx quite conclusively showed, an increased rate of 
surplus value can be got by intensifying labour and rationalising 
production, at the same time as hours of labour are reduced and real 
wages raised. 

Capitalist exploitation consists in the extraction of surplus-value, 
and this still goes on. It has not decreased but increased, for behind 
the facade of collective bargaining and modernisation it is conducted 
more efficiently and ruthlessly than ever. The capitalist, as Marx 
showed, always has a hard job to maintain his rate of profit, and to 
do so he has to scheme out how to intensify the exploitation of labour 
by rationalisation of every kind — which he duly does. 

In demonstrating that capitalism is a system of exploitation of 
labour, Marx showed exactly how it is related to and differs from 
older forms of exploitation. 

The essence (if I may be allowed the use of this word in its normally 
accepted sense, without being accused of “methodological essentialism”) 
of exploitation consists in this: that members of an owning and managing 
class contrive to appropriate to their own uses the products of the labour of 
productive workers , so that those workers are in effect working only in part 
for their own support and in the main for the support of the exploiters , 


204 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


It means that a minority of exploiters appropriate to their own uses the 
labour of the working majority. 

The typical ancient forms of exploitation were, roughly speaking, 
slavery and serfdom. In slavery the slave is a mere chattel: he is the 
property of the master, who owns both him and all he produces. In 
serfdom the producers work a certain amount of time for themselves, 
but for the rest have to work to provide the requirements of their 
lords. The advent of capitalism depended on doing away with both 
slavery and serfdom, for only on that condition could the supply of 
free labour be available for employment in the factories. But the 
exploitation of labour remains, and has simply taken another (and 
more efficient) form. For so much of the working day the wage-workers 
are doing that amount of work which has to be done to produce the value of 
their own requirements of life ; for the rest of the day they are producing 
surplus value for their employers. 

3. THE GENERAL LAW OF CAPITALIST ACCUMULATION 

In supposing that what he calls “interventionism” has actually 
supplanted capitalism, in the way Marx said that only socialism would 
supplant capitalism, Dr. Popper alleges that “economic interference 
of the state” has already brought those benefits which Marx said only 
socialism would bring. He goes so far as to say that “by social 
co-operation” monopoly capitalism has already gone a long way to 
abolish “the greatest evils which have hitherto beset the social life 
of man”, namely, “Poverty, Unemployment and similar forms of 
social insecurity, Sickness and pain, Penal Cruelty, Slavery and other 
forms of Serfdom, Religious and Racial Discrimination, Lack qf 
Educational Opportunities, Rigid Class Differences, War” (CR. 370). 
If that were true, one could not but agree with Dr. Popper that there 
would be no sense in following Marx — for if the status quo is satisfactory, 
why change it? 

According to Dr. Popper, Marx based his entire “prophecy” that 
capitalism would inevitably be overthrown on the notion that under 
capitalism people’s conditions of life would inevitably deteriorate until 
finally they became insupportable. According to this version, Marx 
predicted a century ago that the workers’ standards in the industrial 
capitalist countries would not improve but grow steadily worse. But 
in fact, as we know, they have improved. Hence Marx’s ideas about 
capitalism and its development have been proved to be entirely 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


205 


mistaken. And his idea that capitalism must be abolished and replaced 
by socialism, founded on these mistaken premises, is equally mistaken. 
Whereas Marx said that things would get worse and worse, they have, 
on the contrary, got better and better. Marxist theory, prophesying 
‘‘absolute impoverishment”, bears no relation to what has actually 
happened — and political policies based on it are therefore doomed to 
frustration. These circumstances, says Dr. Popper, force Marxists to 
“learn to believe blindly” and to become “hostile to reasonable 
arguments”. And with withering sarcasm he concludes that “it is not 
only capitalism which is labouring under inner contradictions that 
threaten to bring its downfall” (2-OS. 192). 

Like his refutation of the labour theory of value, this further 
refutation of Marxism so confidently presented by Dr. Popper is a 
hardy annual in the by now rather old-fashioned garden of refutations. 
What keeps it fresh and green is a single quotation from Capital 
(Vol. I, Chapter 25, section 4): “To the degree to which capital 
accumulates, the workers* condition must deteriorate.” This statement 
was called by Marx “the absolute general law of capitalist accumula- 
tion” — so this impressive title certainly justifies attaching to it some 
considerable importance in the body of Marxist theory. However, 
unless one proposes to be “hostile to reasonable argument”, it is best 
to understand and interpret particular statements within the context 
of the whole theory to which they belong, rather than understand 
and interpret the whole theory as though it were summed up in one 
statement. 

Immediately after stating in general terms “the absolute general 
law” Marx added the qualifying statement: “Like all other laws it is 
modified in its working by many circumstances.” If words have 
meaning, these ones imply that, contrary to the interpretation put 
upon it by Dr. Popper and others, the “absolute general law” does 
not unconditionally predict that every accumulation of capital will be 
accompanied by a deterioration of the workers* conditions. On the 
contrary, “many circumstances** will prevent such a deterioration. 

Whatever may be the case with others who have tried to refute 
Marx, it is rather extraordinary that an expert on scientific method 
like Dr. Popper should succumb to such a simple fallacy as to suppose 
that the scientific formulation of “a law*’ is the same tiling as an 
unconditional prediction. Statements of laws are not predictions, but 
tools used in making predictions. 

For instance, no one with any knowledge of science supposes that 


20 6 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


the law of gravitation is a prediction that all bodies will always fall 
to the earth. Some bodies rise and fly about in the air, and the use 
of the law of gravitation is to assist us in calculating the conditions 
under which they do so. Marx understood this perfectly well when he 
wrote about “the general law of capitalist accumulation” — and so does 
Dr. Popper understand it in any context save that of the refutation 
of Marxism. 

The point of “the absolute general law of capitalist accumulation” 
is not that it enables us to predict that under no circumstances so long 
as capitalism lasts will workers ever improve their conditions, which 
will always deteriorate. And nowhere in Capital did Marx make any 
such prediction. The point of the law is to state the “absolute general” 
condition, existing so long as capital accumulates, under which 
workers’ standards either deteriorate or improve— just as gravitation 
is the “absolute general” condition under which bodies fall or rise. 
If you think a body can fly up and up not subject to the condition 
of gravity, you are mistaken. And if you think workers’ standards can 
go up and up not subject to the condition of the absolute general 
law of capitalist accumulation, you are mistaken too. Just as a body 
exerts a gravitational attraction proportional to its mass, so does every 
accumulation of capital, accumulated by extracting as much surplus 
value as possible from the workers’ labour, create a greater power and 
urge to suck up out of labour an even greater accumulation— by 
rationalising production, throwing redundant workers on the scrap- 
heap, and encroaching in every possible way on the standards of 
labour. That is the condition under which any battle to raise standards 
has always to be fought. 

When we consider, in the light of Marx’s complete analysis of 
capitalist production, the totality of actual circumstances created by 
the accumulation of capital in the advanced capitalist countries, we 
find that these circumstances are such that it would be surprising if 
an improvement in the workers’ condition had not taken place; and 
that for several reasons. 

In the first place, as Marx said very often and very clearly, the 
actual level of workers’ standards is determined, not by an “iron law 
of wages” which decrees that they shall always be reduced to the bare 
minimum for subsistence, but by the conditions of class struggle. The 
growing strength of labour organisation succeeds in forcing stan- 
dards up. 

In the second place, the very great advances in technology which 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


207 


accompany the accumulation of capital have the result that all kinds of 
amenities become available on a mass scale, and consequently the 
consumption of these becomes a part of the material requirements 
and expectations of the worker. In other words, with an advanced 
technology the worker comes to require for his maintenance various 
goods and services his forefathers did without — and which his brothers 
in more backward regions still do without. In terms of the labour 
theory of value, the provision of these goods and services then enters 
into the determination of the value of labour-power in the advanced 
countries. This too was very clearly stated by Marx, who pointed 
out that in more developed regions the value of labour-power is con- 
siderably higher than in less developed ones — and he assigned this as a 
powerful motive for export of capital to regions of cheap labour, where 
the actual value of labour was much less than it had become at home. 

In the third place, what Dr. Popper calls the performance of 
economic functions by organised political power, which Marx and 
Engels so clearly forecast, enables capitalist governments to mitigate 
to some extent the ravages of cyclical economic crises and sudden 
mass increases of unemployment. The effect is to lessen to some extent 
the consequent pressures against the improvement of workers’ stan- 
dards which these formerly exerted. Of course it is very advantageous 
for the capitalists to have managed to provide themselves with what 
they now call “economic levers” to control economic conditions in 
the interests of the profitable operations of capital. But at the same 
time it sets them a new problem. Accompanying the “far-reaching 
economic functions” which political power performs they have to 
include appropriate political measures to counteract labour’s demand 
for rising standards. 

These are circumstances which have made it possible in some 
favoured regions to work for and achieve the limited success in 
remedying social evils under capitalism which Dr. Popper celebrates. 
When we look at his list, quoted above, we cannot doubt that much 
benefit has been gained by social security legislation, health services, 
legal reform, the educational services, and opposition to religious and 
racial discrimination; while as for “slavery and serfdom”, capitalism 
has always discouraged these forms of exploitation and sought to 
replace them by wage-labour. 

It is hardly true, however, that the benefits listed have simply been 
bestowed on grateful humanity by a benevolently interventionist 
state. They have been won only by struggle in which the working- 


208 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


class movement has played the chief part. And we may well ask by 
how much more the various social evils could have been reduced had 
it not been for the obstinate resistance of the ruling class at every 
step to every measure proposed to raise the standards of common 
people. In fact, just as the development of laissez faire to “interven- 
tionism” has verified Marx’s economic predictions, so have the 
benefits won in the process verified his prediction that under capitalism 
the working people would never get any benefits without fighting for them . 

Coming to the last two items on Dr. Popper’s list, one does perhaps 
wonder on what data he has concluded that “in Scandinavia, the 
United States, Canada, Australia and New Zealand, we have, in fact, 
something approaching classless societies” (CR. 371). Is there really 
no class distinction, in the countries mentioned, between people living 
by working for wages and by investments and capital gains? And is 
there none between the “organisation men” of the American corpora- 
tions and the poverty-stricken masses in Latin America from whose 
labour such considerable revenue flows into the United States? 

As regards war, Dr. Popper explains that what he means is that 
“the free world will only go to war ... if faced with unambiguous 
aggression” (CR. 372). But whenever people in a territory under the 
special protection of a heavily armed power of “the free world” 
seek to dispense with that protection, this is called “aggression”. That 
is why events since 1956 (which is when Dr. Popper delivered the 
lecture from which his eulogy of modern capitalism has been quoted) 
have continued to falsify his statement that “as far as the free world 
itself is concerned, war has been conquered” (CR. 372). 

For all Iris claim to oppose “reasonable argument” to “blind” 
belief, Dr. Popper does not always trouble to inquire whether facts 
support Iris own assertions. This is evidenced by the opening sentence 
of The Open Society and its Enemies, in which he says that “our civilisa- 
tion”, by which he presumably means the civilisation whose economic 
basis is monopoly capitalism, “might be perhaps described as aiming 
at humaneness and reasonableness, at equality and freedom”. It is 
true he does say “perhaps”; and perhaps so long as such methods as 
the spraying of defenceless women and children with napalm continue 
to be adopted for realising the aims, this should be accepted as the 
operative word. 

Facts make it pretty clear that in the most advanced capitalist 
countries, for all the benefits won by their inhabitants, every other 
aim of policy is subordinated to the condition of preserving the 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


209 


relations of capitalist exploitation and safeguarding capitalist profits. 
But more than that, the facts make it even clearer that the political 
power established in these countries not only intervenes inside the 
countries themselves to preserve and foster capitalist exploitation. It 
intervenes very vigorously indeed outside their borders, in other 
territories, to conquer spheres of investment, markets and sources of 
raw materials, and to make the labour of people in economically more 
backward regions subject to imperialist exploitation. The aim of this 
is neither humaneness, freedom nor equality; nor is the conduct of 
the rivalry between imperialist powers, or the relations between them 
and their dependencies, especially noteworthy for reasonableness. 

Dr. Popper assigned as Marx’s reason for advocating a socialist 
revolution the alleged unconditional prophecy (said to be implied by 
“the absolute general law of capitalist accumulation”) that, until that 
event, standards of life will from day to day and in every way go on 
getting lower and lower. So “increase of misery” will “force” the 
proletariat “to revolt against its exploiters” (2-OS. 137). The workers’ 
economic and social demands will always be refused, and consequently 
they will become inspired “with a desperate knowledge that only 
revolution can help them in their misery” (2-OS. 191). 

If that were true, the result would be discouragement and disorgani- 
sation rather than stronger organisation, and they would never make 
a revolution. The workers in fact organise because experience teaches 
them that that is the way to improve their condition — and they are 
forced to keep up an economic and political struggle against capital 
because only so can they hold on to their gains and gain more. That is 
what Marx teaches the labour movement, and not the doctrinaire and 
defeatist nonsense which Dr. Popper imagines. But Dr. Popper con- 
cludes that if the working class can improve its condition under 
capitalism there can be no reason for proposing to abolish capitalism. 
For if you can improve your condition why not improve it some more, 
instead of calling for the abolition of the system under which such 
improvements can be made? 

Dr. Popper is right about one tiling, and that is that for Marx “the 
absolute general law of capitalist accumulation” provided grounds for 
advising the abolition of capitalism and for predicting that it would 
eventually be abolished. Marx certainly did maintain that all those 
hopeful people (like Dr. Popper himself) who think that improvements 
in living standards can go on and on under capitalism, so that every- 
thing will get better and better and eventually all poverty, unemploy- 


210 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


ment, class differences and war will simply disappear, are blind to the 
operation of “the absolute general law”. But the law is not an uncon- 
ditional prediction of increasing impoverishment. And in general, as 
Dr. Popper has rightly said, unconditional predictions are foreign to 
science. What the law actually says can be summed up in three points. 

First, capitalist accumulation is realised out of surplus value. To 
obtain more surplus and accumulate more capital out of it, it is neces- 
sary to keep down the labourers’ share of the values produced by 
labour. Hence the accumulation of capital, essential for the continua- 
tion of the system, demands that in every way the pressure of the 
wage-workers for a greater share of the values produced be opposed 
and pushed back. Whatever makes for better living for the workers 
is therefore always opposed by the steady pressure engendered by 
capitalist accumulation to make living standards deteriorate. 

Second, the drive for capitalist accumulation brings a continual 
drive for rationalisation of production and the replacement of human 
labour by machinery. Until it can be re-employed at a profit, capital 
has no use for the labour displaced. The people concerned are thrown 
temporarily or permanently on to the scrapheap. Hence, as Marx 
stressed in the chapter of Capital devoted to the “general law”, 
capitalist accumulation continually generates an “industrial reserve” of 
unemployed, and this is a continual and very powerful factor acting 
against the raising of living standards. 

Third, because capitalist accumulation thrives on maximum exploita- 
tion of labour, capital always seeks for spheres of investment where 
greater profit can be got out of greater poverty. Hence such islands 
of affluence as may be formed in particular places are surrounded by 
a sea of poverty, out of the exploitation of which the affluence is 
sustained. As Marx said, the more capital accumulates the greater, on 
a world-wide scale, becomes the contrast between the wealth of a 
few and the poverty of the many. As he said, the wealth accumulates 
at one pole, the poverty at the other. 

The “absolute general law” summed up in these three points con- 
tinues to operate wherever capitalist accumulation goes on. We 
continue to see it operating every day. 

In the advanced capitalist countries experience to date contributes 
little to suggest that the situation is a stable one which will permit the 
steady uninterrupted improvement of conditions of employment and 
standards of living. There is, as Marx and Engels predicted and Dr. 
Popper has duly noted, a certain amount of planning and regulation 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


211 


of the economy — but planning and regulation by whom and for 
whom? The condition of the whole thing is the securing of profits 
for the great capitalist corporations out of the employment of wage- 
labour. It is not planning for welfare but planning for profit; and so 
far as economic growth for the satisfaction of needs is concerned, 
there remains always a chronic waste and under-employment of 
resources both material and human. The anarchic character of the 
profit motive continually asserts itself against any schemes of planned 
growth, and at the same time the demands of labour that social 
production should be turned to the well-being of the producers are 
met by the owners’ objection that we cannot afford it. As is happening 
in Britain at the time of writing (1966-7), the controllers know how 
to put the brakes on, and how to set about creating unemployment 
when “over-full employment” is giving the worker too much bargain- 
ing power. In affluent America there has always been a huge mass of 
permanent unemployment, and a vast and shameful accumulation of 
poverty. 

These facts verify among other things Marx’s theoretical conclusion 
that the process of circulation of capital, which is what capitalist 
management tries to manage, remains as a whole unmanageable. 

The circulation of capital begins with an accumulation of capital 
in the form of money, which is used to buy materials, machinery and 
labour-power. Then labour-power is set to work, to produce both 
means of consumption and the machinery to be used for new produc- 
tion. Then the products are sold, so as to realise a new and greater 
sum of money with which to buy more labour-power, materials and 
machinery. This circular movement is the life process of capital. For 
it to flow on uninterrupted would suppose the continuous production 
by socialised labour of increasing quantities (in terms of value) of both 
means of consumption and means of production, and, at the same 
time, the continuous profitable sale of everything produced. Dr. 
Popper and others talk of “a communist utopia”. However that may 
be, that this should happen is a capitalist utopia. It has never happened 
yet. And as a result of interruptions in the circulation, production 
keeps on being disrupted, poverty is perpetuated and resources are 
wasted or destroyed. 

With capitalists competing for profit the whole circulation of capital 
cannot possibly be managed, since no management, not even the most 
well-advised capitalist state, has simultaneous control over all the 
factors involved. Breakdowns and disruptions keep occurring in one 


212 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


or another stage of the process; workers demand too much pay, or 
withhold their labour; investors don’t invest enough in new capital 
equipment, or else invest too much; too much of something or other 
is produced, or else not enough; and so on. Management is for ever 
trying to repair the damage but never succeeds in preventing it, for 
while they are coping with one trouble another is breaking out. 

However, the proclivity of capitalist circulation to suffer interrup- 
tions is not due simply to the difficulty of managing to adjust the 
simultaneous independent profit-seeking operations of competing 
blocks of capital. Neither the greatest luck nor the greatest judgment 
could solve the problem. For, as Marx showed, the necessity for 
capital to maximise its profit in order that capital should go on 
accumulating out of surplus value means that, on the one hand, the 
productive forces should go on being expanded without limit, while, 
on the other hand, the share in the product going to the producers 
should be restricted. “The last cause of all real crises”, wrote Marx 
( Capital , Vol. 3, Chapter 30), “always remains the . . . restricted con- 
sumption of the masses compared to the tendency of capitalist produc- 
tion to develop the productive forces as if only the absolute power of 
consumption of the entire society would be their limit.” 

Formerly, interruptions in the circulation of capital took the regular 
form of the ten-year “trade cycle”. But while the boom-bust rhythm 
has been interrupted, that has not let the circulation of capital go on 
without interruptions. It remains utopian to believe that it can ever 
possibly do so — either providentially, through the operation of the 
economic laws of the market, as earlier economists fondly believed, or 
by the brilliant contrivances of good management, as modem ones 
equally fondly incline to hope. 

Meantime, although neither Dr. Popper nor the capitalist establish- 
ment is pleased about it, the fact is that approximately one-third of 
the people of the world have by now done away with capitalism (as 
Marx advised and predicted) before it had even the chance of proving 
to them the benefits it could confer. They are trying to build or have 
built a planned socialist economy instead. A very high proportion of 
the rest of the people, miserably poor, are in a state of revolt against 
imperalism, against colonialism and neo-colonialism. In these circum- 
stances the major capitalist powers are spending a significant proportion 
of their national income on armaments — mainly for the purpose of 
stopping impoverished peoples from shaking free of the grip of foreign 
capital and to stop the socialist countries from helping them. These 


THE CRITIQUE OF CAPITALISM 


213 

armaments, and the local wars and escalations of wars in which some 
of them are used, remain at once a threat to the peace of the world 
and to the very existence of civilisation, and a crushing burden on 
the people of the capitalist countries. We sustain them at our peril. 
And if we can force the capitalist governments to stop their wars and 
disarm, we can then hardly continue to save the capitalist interests 
the armaments, armed forces and wars are protecting. 

Moreover, whatever capitalist powers do (short of world war, 
which would destroy them), the socialist powers will continue to 
develop, and that at an accelerating pace, their own technological 
resources. And the national liberation movements against imperialism 
and neo-colonialism will continue to grow, whatever their disunity 
and whatever setbacks they sustain in this or that place. 

For how long can we suppose that such a situation, brought about 
by the operation of “the absolute general law of capitalist accumula- 
tion’, can continue? For some time more, perhaps, but not for ever. 
The operation of the general law will, as Marx predicted, either bring 
general ruin or else be terminated by the removal of the capitalist 
relations which give rise to it. 

And there is yet another factor of very great moment. The capitalist 
powers have now started on the ioad of a new technological revolu- 
tion. If they slow the pace of technological advance they will cut 
away the foundations of their own affluence and be hopelessly out- 
paced by the socialist powers. They will then be totally unable to 
maintain their dominance over at present underdeveloped countries, 
their economies will stagnate, and very serious consequences in the 
way of unemployment and impoverishment will be upon them. On 
the other hand, if they carry on, and if they develop vast new resources 
of energy for powering fully automated production, how are they to 
secure the planned development of the economy, with full employ- 
ment, if they insist that the key means of production should be 
privately owned and that the whole employed labour force should 
be wage-workers whose labour contributes to private profit? Unem- 
ployment on a huge scale would result, and not all the bread and 
circuses borrowed from the ancient Romans in the days of their 
decadence would be able to save the doomed system. 

If, then, Dr. Popper and others demand why we should heed the 
advice of Marx that capitalism should be abolished, when some of us 
are doing so well out of it, the short answer is that we cannot afford 
not to. We are living in a fools’ paradise if we remain blind to the 


214 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


operation of “the absolute general law of capitalist accumulation”. 
It is overall true that as capital accumulates the workers’ conditions 
must deteriorate. 

In socialism, the accumulation of capital, in the sense of accumula- 
tion of resources out of which social production can be expanded, 
has no tendency to lead to the deterioration of the conditions of 
workers. On the contrary, the more social capital accumulates the 
higher can standards of life be raised. The accumulation of resources is 
then the condition for raising the standards of all workers ( all , not 
some) up to a high level, for lightening labour, making hours of 
necessary work shorter and the means for enjoyment of leisure greater. 
This, Marxism concludes, is the condition of affairs which we must 
organise to achieve — or else perish. 

As we have seen, Marx expounded as the basic law of all social 
development the law that relations of production must always be 
brought into conformity with the development of forces of produc- 
tion. When, from being forms of development of production, 
relations of production become fetters on it, a social revolution is 
needed to change the social system. The need to get rid of capitalism 
and replace it by socialism is the need to get rid of production relations 
which have become fetters on the growing forces of production. The 
“ absolute general law of capitalist accumulation 9 is the concise statement of 
the way in which capitalist relations act as fetters on production. Instead of 
productive resources being accumulated for the purpose of raising the 
general standards of life of the producers, capitalist accumulation takes 
place at the expense of general welfare, is accompanied by wastage of 
material resources and human capacities, and impoverishes producers 
at the same time as it enriches owners of capital. 

It may be added that, as Lenin said, Marx dealt not only with 
relations of production but “went on to trace the superstructure 
corresponding to these relations of production”. He demonstrated the 
consequences in the encouragement of individual selfishness and greed, 
in conflicts and grabs, in speculation and corruption, in frustration, 
waste and needless suffering, in political chicanery and political op- 
pression and wars. Thus his economic analysis, “strictly confined to the 
relations of production between the members of society”, succeeds in 
explaining and interpreting the hateful experience of the members of 
society caught up in the economic system. The same theme which is 
explored by poets, painters, musicians and novelists in bourgeois 
society is given its scientific exposition by Marxism. 


4 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 

I. THE SOCIALIST REVOLUTION 

A basic change in relations of production would mean drastic inter- 
ference with the rights of property — at the present time, the ownership 
of capital — and this would constitute a social revolution. It is this 
which is so widely regarded as unthinkable or, at any rate, as not to 
be proposed in works of science which might qualify for research 
grants. Dr. Popper undoubtedly speaks for the whole establishment 
in stating that a revolution is one of the very worst things that could 
possibly happen to us. 

A revolution, he says, involves “the prolonged use of violence” 
which “may lead in the end to the loss of freedom, since it is liable to 
bring about not the dispassionate rule of reason but the rule of the 
strong man” (2-OS. 151). Nay more, it “destroys the institutional 
and traditional framework of society . . . once they destroy tradition, 
civilisation disappears with it . . . they have returned to the beasts” 
(CR. 343-4). And in a more dispassionate vein he argues that “it is not 
reasonable to assume that a complete reconstruction of our social 
world would lead at once to a workable system. Rather we should 
expect that, owing to lack of experience, many mistakes would be 
made. . . .” (i-OS. 167). 

But not only would “revolutionary methods . . . increase unneces- 
sary suffering” and “lead to more and more violence” (CR. 343), but 
the “humanitarian aims” which revolutionaries pursue can be achieved 
without any revolution. Once it is admitted that, as experience proves, 
social benefits can be won under capitalism, there is no reason “why 
the workers, who have learned by experience that they can improve 
their lot by gradual reform, should not prefer to stick to this method 
. . . why they should not compromise with the bourgeoisie and leave 
it in possession of the means of production rather than risk all their 
gains by making demands liable to lead to violent dashes”. Gradual 
reform can continue, and “there is no logical necessity why gradual 
reform, achieved by compromise, should lead to the complete destruc- 
tion of the capitalist system” (2-OS. 155). Anyway, Dr. Popper argues, 
those who believe in smashing everything up would have to undertake 


21 6 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


gradual reconstruction afterwards, so it would be far more sensible 
to get on with gradual construction in the first place and forget the 
smash-up (i-OS. 1 68). 

Dr. Popper takes a rather apocalyptic view of revolution. He 
assumes that if once capitalist ownership of means of production were 
abolished everything would crash, that if private capital were prevented 
from making profits out of exploiting wage-labour civilisation would 
end. So he cries: “They destroy tradition !” “Civilisation disappears !” 
“They have returned to the beasts !” and (a bit of an anti-climax) 
“Many mistakes would be made!” He is, of course, justified in his 
last apprehension — for people always do make mistakes, whatever 
they do. But as for “tradition” and “civilisation”, it would seem that 
Dr. Popper’s sweeping statements were made under some sort of 
emotional stress, for they are certainly “not reasonable”. 

Do “tradition” and “civilisation”, in the senses in which these may 
be regarded as something to be preserved, mean specifically capitalist 
tradition or capitalist civilisation? No, for tradition and civilisation 
are more permanent, more lasting, than particular production relations ; 
civilisation and norms of civilised living are developed by men through 
the ages, so that advances made within certain production relations 
are not lost but carried further under new production relations, which 
are “higher” in the sense that they correspond to a higher development 
of forces of production. To develop civilisation and civilised living, 
people have to go on developing their forces of production ; and when 
production relations are acting as a fetter upon the utilisation of new 
forces of production they have to be changed, or else civilisation and 
its traditions may suffer degeneration instead of renewal. 

Of course, if one considers only particular local traditions or 
pieces of tradition, or particular local or specialised amenities of 
civilisation, it would have to be admitted that they are frequently 
destroyed or disappear — and a good thing too. For example, there 
is a parliamentary tradition in Britain that the Chamber of the House 
of Commons should not contain seats for all the members. This 
tradition was successfully upheld by both Sir Winston Churchill and 
Lord Atdee when the House was rebuilt after the Second World War; 
but no doubt a socialist revolution in Britain would destroy this 
particular tradition. Again, the kind of civilised or gracious living 
associated with the ownership of town and country mansions, with 
grouse moors and large staffs of servants, is already disappearing, and 
would completely disappear if there were a socialist revolution. But 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 217 

are such destructions of traditions and disappearances of civilisation a 
bad thing? Only a few would regret them, and their loss would 
scarcely return the rest of mankind “to the beasts”. But if by “civilisa- 
tion” and “tradition” is meant, more generally, the ever-developing 
production by and distribution to the members of society of the 
necessities and comforts of life, with the development of the sciences 
and the arts, and -of social freedom and justice, then there is no reason 
at all to conclude that a change in the relations of production, calculated 
to promote the development of social production for social welfare, 
would destroy tradition or cause civilisation to disappear. Indeed, a 
far more pressing danger arises from the growth and continuation of 
certain traditions of commercialism, corrupt politics and militarism 
fostered by the existing capitalist set up, and the greatest danger of all 
from the stock-piling of nuclear weapons. If mankind should ever be 
“returned to the beasts” by the destruction of civilisation, it will be 
as a result of nuclear war unleashed by mad imperialists (and all this 
claptrap about “the institutional and traditional framework of society” 
is a part of the phraseology of such madness). 

Dr. Popper’s apocalyptic visions arise simply and solely from his 
obsession with the idea that revolution involves “the prolonged use 
of violence” and “more and more violence”. It is this violence which 
he sees as doing the damage. And he represents Marxism as in part a 
fatalistic prediction of violence, in part a conspiracy to incite violence. 

For Marxism, though not for Dr. Popper, the word “revolution” 
has a precise significance defined in terms of Marx’s theory of social 
development and class struggle. 

Hitherto, the development of relations of production, that is to say, 
of forms of ownership of means of production and appropriation of the 
products of labour, has divided society into antagonistic classes. In 
any particular social formation, a particular dominant class maintains 
its existence by exploiting the masses of producers in a particular way, 
and preventing other exploiting classes from developing as rivals 
their own methods of exploitation. The political system is the means 
by which this is managed and a particular form of ownership and 
appropriation of products of labour is imposed upon the whole of 
society. A revolution, then, is a change in the political system of such 
an order that another class comes to power and deprives the former 
ruling class of its opportunities to maintain itself by its former 
methods of exploitation. A revolution thus effects a change in the 
relations of production. And it is a phenomenon peculiar to and 


218 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


typical of class-divided society, where there are exploiting and ex- 
ploited classes. 

There have been many revolutions recorded by history, and all of 
them have been violent (involving, indeed, ‘‘the prolonged use of 
violence”). The cause of this universal violence is clear. Ruling classes 
have maintained their rule only by aggression and violent repression 
of their subjects, and the only way to get rid of them has been by 
violently opposing them. Revolutions in the past have, however, by 
no means been distinguished as regrettable outbreaks of violence 
interrupting periods of calm and peaceful progress and putting in 
jeopardy the gains of civilisation. There has always been violence and 
war, revolutions have been conducted by violence and war, and in 
them violence and war have been made the vehicles by which men 
have managed to get rid of old forms of property which fettered social 
production, the material basis of civilisation. 

Marxist analysis claims to demonstrate that what is on the agenda 
now is socialist (or “proletarian”) revolution, and to demonstrate, too, 
the ways in which this must differ from all previous revolutions. 

In previous revolutions ruling exploiting classes succumbed to the 
hostility not only of masses who were exploited but of other classes of 
exploiters or would-be exploiters. The working masses had to do 
most of the slogging, but new exploiters reaped the reward and 
came to power. 

In the past, slave revolts or peasant revolts weakened the ruling 
classes, but the invariable upshot was the defeat and dispersal of slave 
or peasant insurgents and the reconsolidation of exploitation by either 
the old or new exploiters. In modem history it has been typical of 
bourgeois revolutions that at a certain point the bourgeoisie rounded 
upon and disarmed the insurgent masses who had been making the 
pace at the start, and entered into a compromise with the defeated 
counter-revolution. In bourgeois revolutions there has always been an 
incipient democratic revolution, with demands going far beyond what 
the bourgeoisie was disposed to grant. (This is illustrated by the English, 
American and French revolutions, and by the European revolutionary 
movements of 1848; when it came to the Russian revolution in 1905 
and 1917 there was already in existence a well-organised industrial 
working class with revolutionary socialist leadership, and the result 
was the socialist revolution of 1917.) 

But wherever the bourgeoisie comes to power and a fully capitalist 
economy is created, the ruling bourgeoisie no longer faces any other 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 219 

rival group of exploiters. There emerges a direct confrontation of 
exploiters and exploited, uncomplicated by any issues of substituting 
some new form of exploitation for the existing form. Thus the single 
issue becomes that of either continuing capitalist exploitation or ending 
it by depriving the capitalist class of political power and instituting 
social ownership of the principal means of production. Thus whereas 
previous revolutions substituted new forms of exploitation for old, 
the issue now is to end exploitation once for all. 

This confrontation of classes, with the issue it poses, exists in all 
developed capitalist countries today. Dr. Popper, incidentally, raises 
some rather irrelevant objections to the recognition of this fact. “We 
must be prepared to find,” he says, “that a ve’-y considerable middle 
class exists (or that a new middle class has arisen) and that it may 
co-operate with the other non-proletarian classes against a bid for 
power by the workers; and nobody can say for certain what the 
outcome of such a contest would be. Indeed, statistics no longer show 
any tendency for the number of industrial workers to increase in 
relation to the other classes of the population” (2-OS. 156). 

By a “middle class” and “a new middle class” he presumably means 
all kinds of workers on their own account, and professional workers ; 
and by “the other non-proletarian classes” he means chiefly working 
farmers and peasants. What he says about these classes is quite true, 
but it does not in the last alter the fact that the only alternative to 
continuing capitalist exploitation is now to end all exploitation: there 
is no question of any of these classes ousting the big capitalists and 
setting up some new sort of exploitation of their own, but only, as he 
quite rightly says, of whether or not they will support “a bid for 
power by the workers”. Clearly, therefore, and as Marxists have 
always said, it is an important element in contemporary socialist 
tactics to seek to win the support of these classes for socialism, and 
not to antagonise them by a narrow sectarian concern with the 
interests of industrial workers alone. As for the decreasing proportion 
of “industrial workers”, by that he means, presumably, the relative 
increase in the number of technicians, “white collar” workers, and 
“brain workers” of one kind and another. True, there is such an 
increase ; and these are exactly the sorts of people who will be needed 
in large numbers to build a modern socialist economy. Dr. Popper, 
in fact, has understood the Marxist theory of socialist revolution so 
little, that he cites circumstances which confirm it as insuperable 
objections. 


220 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


In the socialist revolution the exploited classes play an altogether 
new role. They are not the unruly rank and file of the revolution, but 
its organisers and leaders. 

This difference is illustrated by the difference between the role of 
the organised working-class movement in the modem class struggle 
and that of the so-called “mob” in certain phases of bourgeois revolu- 
tions. The “mob” would come together in a spontaneous way, driven 
usually by anger at some sudden deterioration of conditions that made 
the already miserable condition of the poor desperate (often a rise in 
food prices, as demonstrated by G. Rude in The Crowd in the French 
Revolution ). It was a very formidable force, but without permanent 
organisation or aims, or its own permanent leadership. Its swift and 
sometimes destructive activities could pave the way for other classes 
gaining their ends, and then the mob itself could be dispersed. This 
“mob” has become transformed into the organised democratic labour 
movement, a far more formidable force when it unites to exert its 
strength, its aims clearly delineated, and neither destructive nor 
riotous but disciplined and not easily dispersed, and fully capable of 
staffing from its own ranks the entire legislative and executive 
apparatus of modem society. 

The modern working class is able to play this new role because the 
conditions of modern industry lead to its becoming organised and 
educated, and to the formation of competent groups of socialist 
intellectuals and political leaders of the labour movement. Thus it is 
an exploited class able not only to kick against exploitation, as the 
exploited have always done, but to manage affairs when the rule of 
its exploiters is ended. 

Another feature of socialist revolution is its world-wide international 
character. 

The local development of capitalism in only a few countries had 
the effect (the inevitable effect, if Dr. Popper will forgive the expres- 
sion) of bringing the entire world into the orbit of capitalist exploita- 
tion. The world became divided up into spheres of exploitation of a 
comparatively few capitalist powers. With them, capital has developed 
to the monopoly phase, with the merging of industrial and finance 
capital, and the export of capital ; capitalism developed into the phase 
of imperialism. This meant that throughout the world the struggle 
of exploited people against their being exploited involved, beyond 
issues of kicking free from whatever local feudal or proto-feudal 
forms of exploitation they suffered, the final struggle for emancipation 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 


221 


from the exploitation of capital. Besides, comparatively “primitive” 
people, whose tribal way of life still retained many communal features, 
found themselves suddenly subjected to capitalist forms of exploitation 
totally foreign to their own phase of social development, and were 
flung into the struggle against it. Thus the impingement of capitalist 
exploitation stirred up the whole world, and forced on the working 
masses everywhere, whatever their own prior stage of economic and 
social development, the issue of resisting capitalist exploitation and, 
therefore, the issue that if they were ever to be rid of it they must 
take the road of socialism. 

There has thus begun, and continues to go on, a world-wide process 
of socialist revolution, in which particular local movements are con- 
tributory parts; a world-wide process of emancipation from the 
exploitation of capital, and therefore from all exploitation. This is 
something quite new in the history of revolutions. Hitherto there 
have been only local revolutions, in which local people upset the rule 
of local exploiters and other local exploiters took their place. But 
now every revolutionary movement is up against the same opponents, 
and all the local movements, whether their members fully understand 
it or not, add up to a world-wide movement which cannot relent 
until the exploitation of man by man is ended throughout the world. 
It cannot relent because, although particular groups of people may 
suffer defeat or turn their coats, the same world-wide circumstances 
which drove them into action will continue to operate, and drive others 
into action. 

The words “socialist revolution” denote, therefore, not particular 
local revolutionary events (a “bid for power” or “desperate uprising”, 
as Dr. Popper puts it) which are repeated, or which Communists 
predict will be repeated, in much the same way at different places 
and times, but rather a whole epoch, a whole process of disturbance 
of social relations and institutions, continuing over a long period of 
time (perhaps a century, perhaps longer) and involving the whole 
world. To say, as Marxists say, that this is the epoch of the socialist 
revolution, and that socialist revolution is inevitable, is not to prophesy 
that a particular sort of armed uprising is fated to occur in each par- 
ticular place (in Britain, for example, where far from predicting an 
armed uprising the Communist Party’s programme includes no such 
thing, and regards it as not only unpractical but undesirable) ; it is to 
say that mankind is now unavoidably involved throughout the world 
in a struggle against capitalist forms of exploitation, that the removal 


222 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


of exploitation has already begun, and that the struggle against it 
cannot but go on until it is done away with everywhere. 

2. SOCIAL ENGINEERING 

According to Dr. Popper, the rational alternative to the revolutionary 
overthrow of the entire “institutional and traditional framework of 
society”, which he says Marxists think inevitable, is piecemeal “social 
engineering”. By “social engineering” he means “the planning and 
construction of institutions, with the aim, perhaps, of arresting or of 
controlling or of quickening impending social developments” 

(PH. 45). 

Social engineering must be, he says, “piecemeal”. That is to say, 
it starts with institutions as they are, examines in what ways they 
work badly, either by causing preventable human inconvenience or 
suffering, or failing to alleviate it, and then introduces reforms to 
make them work better. “Blueprints for piecemeal engineering are 
comparatively simple,” he informs us. “They are blueprints for single 
institutions, for health and unemployment insurance, for instance, or 
arbitration courts, or anti-depression budgeting, or educational 
reform.” And he continues : “If they go wrong, the damage is not very 
great, and a readjustment not very difficult” (i-OS. 159). 

This sort of social engineering advances by trial and error, it becomes 
ever more effective and successful as practical experience accumulates, 
and in this way it can bid fair “to be supported by the approval and 
agreement of a great number of people” (i-OS. 158), rather than 
causing people to fall out with one another, as is likely to result from 
more ambitious and far-reaching projects of social reconstruction. It 
goes hand in hand with the development of the social sciences. For, 
says Dr. Popper, “the social sciences have developed very largely 
through the criticism of proposals for social improvements or, more 
precisely, through attempts to find out whether or not some particular 
economic or political action is likely to produce an expected, or 
desired, result” (PH. 58). 

In one of his more eloquent passages, Dr. Popper states the credo of 
the social engineer: “Work for the elimination of concrete evils rather 
than for the realisation of abstract goods. Do not aim at establishing 
happiness by political means. Rather aim at the elimination of concrete 
miseries. Or, in more practical terms: fight for the elimination of 
poverty by direct means — for example, by making sure everybody 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 


223 


has a minimum income. Or fight against epidemics and disease by 
erecting hospitals and schools of medicine. Fight illiteracy as you fight 
criminality. But do all this by direct means. Choose what you consider 
the most urgent evil of the society in which you live, and try patiently 
to convince people that we can get rid of it.” That, he informs us, 
provides “a simple formula or recipe for distinguishing between what 
I consider to be admissible plans for social reform and inadmissible 
utopian blueprints” (CR. 361). 

In opposition to genuine or “piecemeal” social engineering, Dr. 
Popper castigates what he calls “utopian social engineering”. According 
to this, it is of no use “tinkering” with this or that institution; what has 
to be done is to reconstruct the entire fabric of society. First “we must 
determine our ultimate political aim, or the Ideal State ; . . . only then 
can we begin to consider the best ways and means for its realisation, 
and to draw up a plan for practical action” (i-OS. 157). 

Dr. Popper criticises projects for “utopian social engineering” on 
several grounds. First, to reconstruct society as a whole there must 
needs be a dictatorship, which would have to be imposed on society 
by violence and would create a state of affairs much worse than any 
it was proposed to remedy. Second, it is not true that only by a 
complete reconstruction of society could social evils be remedied, for 
experience shows that much can be achieved piecemeal, by tackling 
them little by little and one by one. Third, in his enthusiasm for 
“abstract goods” the utopian actually disregards concrete evils which 
are under his very nose. “Do not allow your dreams of a beautiful 
world to lure you away from the claims of men who suffer here and 
now”, Dr. Popper implores. “Our fellow men have a claim to our 
help” (CR. 361). To help them effectively we must tackle the im- 
mediate evils they are suffering, whereas the utopian condemns this 
as mere “tinkering”, believing that what is needed is nothing less 
than complete reconstruction of the whole society. 

Marx may have argued against “utopian socialism”, Dr. Popper 
continues, but nevertheless Marxism embraces the chief error of 
“utopianism”. This is the belief “that nothing short of a complete 
eradication of the offending social system will do”. What distinguishes 
Marxism from other utopian creeds is the “historicist” theory that 
eradication of the social system is fated to happen by the laws of 
history. According to Dr. Popper, what Marxists call “scientific” as 
opposed to “utopian socialism” does not consist in working out what 
to do in order to free mankind from exploitation on the basis of 


224 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


understanding how causes may be set in motion in order to produce 
effects (which is what in other spheres engineers trained in science 
normally do). On the contrary, it consists in “blindly” believing that 
socialism will be brought about by inexorable historical necessity. 
Therefore, says Dr. Popper, “Marx condemns in fact all social engineer- 
ing. . . . He denounces the faith in a rational planning of social insti- 
tutions as altogether unrealistic, since society must grow according to 
the laws of history and not according to our rational plans. All we can 
do, he asserts, is to lessen the birthpangs of the historical process” 
(i-OS. 164). 

So Dr. Popper presents us with an alternative: to choose between 
“utopian” and “piecemeal” social engineering. On the one hand, we 
may choose to believe that nothing short of the complete eradication 
of the present social system will benefit humanity, and that therefore 
it is of no use working out rational plans for improving our institutions 
because the only practical thing to do is to speed the fateful day when 
they will all be smashed up. On the other hand, we may reject any 
idea of a radical change in the social system and choose to keep on 
tinkering with single institutions, so as to satisfy bit by bit, so far as 
the present system allows, the various claims of our fellow men. 

This choice, as we might indeed expect when it is presented by 
Dr. Popper, is the choice of Wonderland. “In that direction lives a 
Hatter; and in that direction lives a March Hare. Visit either you like; 
they’re both mad.” “But I don’t want to go among mad people”, 
Alice remarked. “Oh, you can’t help that: we’re all mad here.” Let us 
see if we cannot, in this predicament, fare better than Alice. 

A practical socialist policy does not, as Marx made perfectly clear 
in his criticism of “utopian socialism”, take off from the enunciation 
of an “ultimate political aim, or the Ideal State”.. As for “the Ideal 
State”, it is equally a utopia whether it is supposed to be realised, as 
the utopian socialists believed, by everyone becoming convinced of 
its rationality, or, as Dr. Popper says Marxists believe, by inexorable 
processes of historical necessity. A practical socialist policy takes off 
from the scientific analysis of the mode of exploitation in modern 
society, the consequences of this exploitation, and the practical long- 
term possibilities of removing it and instituting relations of production 
which will permit the utilisation and development of modern forces 
of production for purposes of the general welfare. It then takes into 
account what sort of political organisation and policy will be necessary 
to this end, and what sort of opposition it may expect to encounter. 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 


225 


As for “our ultimate political aim”, this is not presented as “the Ideal 
State”, but as the aim which follows from the scientific analysis of the 
actual human situation. It is presented as demonstrably practicable, and 
as demonstrably necessary, in view of the actual human situation. 

Thus the question posed is not one of choosing between, on the one 
hand, the utopian aim of an “Ideal State”, to realise which requires 
the violent suppression of the existing order, and on the other hand, 
the rational practice of “piecemeal social engineering”, tinkering with 
existing institutions so as to alleviate hardships by trying to meet the 
claims of everyone concerned in them. The question is one of whether, 
on the one hand, to accept the existing mode of exploitation, or on the 
other hand, to examine what is wrong with it, what can be done to 
remove it, and what issues to tackle and what constructive proposals 
to make, step by step, in order to do so. 

It is totally untrue, as stated in the credo of “social engineering”, 
that revolutionary socialists aim only at “the realisation of abstract 
goods”, whereas the “piecemeal” social engineers “rather aim at the 
elimination of concrete miseries”. Communists “aim at the elimination 
of concrete miseries”, and it is their consciousness of these “miseries” 
and of their roots in the existing system of exploitation, that makes 
them revolutionary socialists. We do not oppose capitalism in order 
to realise “abstract goods”, but in order to “fight for the elimination 
of poverty by direct means”. That which Dr. Popper misnames 
“social engineering”, on the other hand, will allow “concrete miseries” 
to be eliminated only in so far as their elimination is compatible with 
maintaining capitalist exploitation. There is no occasion at all for Dr. 
Popper to admonish us: “Our fellow men have a claim to our help.” 
We know they have. That is why we are in favour, for instance, of 
“erecting hospitals and schools of medicine” to the full extent necessary 
“to fight against epidemics and disease”, and are not impressed by the 
admonitions of social engineers who tell us that the programme can 
be only a limited one because, meantime, we have to pay for the costs 
of fighting communism. 

Dr. Popper advises us: “Do not aim at establishing happiness by 
political means.” For, he goes on to explain, “it is my thesis that human 
misery is the most urgent problem of a rational public policy and that 
happiness is not such a problem. The attainment of happiness should 
be left to our private endeavours” (CR. 361). 

It is possible “by political means” to remove the causes of poverty 
and war, and to provide everyone with the material means for useful 


226 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


work, education, leisure, comfort and the protection of health. Even 
that, of course, would still not suffice to “establish happiness”; for 
whether individuals are happy or not will still depend on how they 
treat each other, and how each behaves, in personal life. But all the 
same, it is pretty ridiculous (or possibly cold-blooded) to pose “human 
misery” as “the most urgent problem of a rational public policy”, 
in opposition to “happiness”. A politics which really tackles “the 
problem of human misery” is not indifferent to fostering the pursuit 
of happiness, and can certainly go further towards “establishing” it 
than one which is content simply to leave it “to our private en- 
deavours”. The social engineer clears a slum, builds a council estate, 
dumps people in it, and tells them: “Your happiness now depends on 
your private endeavours”. Could not more be done to remove the 
frustrations and help establish the happiness of the council tenants? 

Revolutionary change of the social system is not opposed to “re- 
form”. No politically serious socialist, and certainly no Communist, 
ever says: Either eradicate the social system, or else reform existing 
institutions — you cannot do both. We always propose and we always 
support such reforms as will benefit the people. We do this because 
“our fellow men have a claim to our help”. It is not Communists who 
look on with indifference at preventable human miseries. Nor do we 
tolerate miseries because we believe that the more miserable people 
are the more likely they are to support our plan for a violent revolution. 
That is just one of Dr. Popper’s smears. On the contrary, it is certain 
“social engineers” of the ruling classes who look on with indifference, 
believing that if these people can be kept down they can be kept out, 
and that it will be good for profits. Every Communist is a social 
reformer. And practical ardour for social reform is not in the least 
incompatible with seeking to eradicate the social system, but is rather 
a necessary quality of effective revolutionary leadership. 

It was Lenin (in What is to be Done) who said that Communists 
should always be “the tribunes of the people”. Those who hope to 
mobilise a great movement to transform society must know how to 
respond to every grievance and every demand of every section and, 
indeed, of every individual that composes the movement. A movement 
that will be able to unite and organise to achieve a new order of society 
must be composed of persons and organisations who will never take 
any imposition lying down, but who know how to better their con- 
dition and not let others worsen it. And those whom people will trust 
as leaders are those who have shown that both heart and mind are 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 22J 

involved in protest against every deprivation and every injustice 
suffered by even the most insignificant or undeserving individual. 


3 . REFORM AND REVOLUTION 

Revolutionary change of the social system is the alternative, not to 
reform, but to the policy of allowing only such reform as can be 
accomplished without jeopardising the profits of the ruling class. 

According to Dr. Popper, “it is not so very difficult to reach agree- 
ment by discussion on what are the most urgent social reforms”. So it 
is not difficult to get agreed the measures of “piecemeal social engi- 
neering”. That is one of its great virtues, he says, for in this way “we 
can get somewhere by arguing ... we can profit here from the attitude 
of reasonableness. We can learn by listening to concrete claims, by 
patiently trying to assess them as impartially as we can, and by con- 
sidering ways of meeting them without creating worse evils” 
(CR. 361). 

This, says Dr. Popper, “is a fact, and not a very strange fact”. 
Certainly, it is “not a very strange fact” that agreement on some 
“urgent social reform” should sometimes be “not so very difficult”, 
when, on the one hand, there would be a great deal of protest if the 
urgent need for reform were ignored and, on the other hand, the 
agreed reform impartially but generously acknowledges the “concrete 
claims” of capitalist vested interests. Thus, for example, there is general 
agreement in Britain today that something must be done to meet the 
housing situation. And although some disagreement is expressed as to 
the proportionate parts that private enterprise and public authorities 
should play in the housing programme, no very serious disagreements 
break out so long as rent, interest and profit are duly upheld. Housing 
may be, with a considerable measure of agreement, subsidised out of 
public funds, so long as the subsidy guarantees that the moneylenders 
shall be paid in full. So isn’t that “reasonable”? Surely the rehousing 
of homeless families removes a positive evil, and creates no “worse 
evil”, even if the condition for it is that vested interests shall get their 
rake off? And even though the job is done very slowly, and is inter- 
rupted whenever the government declares a “crisis”, it is still claimed 
that this way of doing it is the best way. For the removal of the vested 
interests which obstruct an all-out effort to solve the housing problem 
could well prove a “worse evil”, because they would object, govern- 
ment would have to suppress their objections, and that would be 


228 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


“dictatorship” ; at all events, it would put an end to the desirable but 
“not very strange fact” of agreement. 

In actual fact in capitalist society — and this, too, is “not very strange” 
— all “agreements”, whether they concern such matters as social 
services or wages, hours, working conditions and holidays, are arrived 
at as accommodations between opposed interests — for instance, those 
of people wanting cheap and good houses, and those of moneylenders 
and landlords who want interest and rent; or those of workers wanting 
more real wages, and those of employers wanting more profits. 

It may then be said — and, indeed, Dr. Popper does say so — that 
the fact that affairs get arranged through these sorts of accommodations 
means that the class struggle has been abated and is on the way to dis- 
appearance. But, on the contrary, these accommodations demonstrate the 
continued existence of the class struggle , and are its outcome . 

First of all, it was the conduct of class struggle which led to the 
position where they could be made at all. If there were no class organ- 
isations of the working class, which have grown strong enough and 
fight hard enough to gain recognition, the ruling class would not be 
so accommodating. And secondly, what can be got depends on the 
complex balance of effective pressures behind the competing claims of 
competing class interests. If the working people want to gain more 
benefits, and stop vested interests from robbing them of them, they 
must fight more determinedly and harder. 

Persons in ministries and offices drafting blueprints for making this 
or that improvement in this or that institution or service, and other 
persons sitting critically commenting on them in the London School 
of Economics, or getting on their hind legs in parliament, may imagine 
that they are, like wise and impartial legislators, performing judicious 
operations of piecemeal social engineering. But they are not in fact 
like engineers working out designs for a new bridge or, maybe, for 
strengthening one which is failing to stand up under the load of 
heavier traffic. They are seeking to control people and shape their social 
relations, and dealing not with mechanical but with social stresses; 
and what they can plan, and what actually happens to their plans, 
depends on the actual power that is exerted in the social institutions by 
conflicting class interests. 

The occurrence of so-called “piecemeal social engineering” is only a 
particular contemporary manifestation of the class struggle between 
capital and labour, and its laws of operation are not those of engineering 
but of class struggle. 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 229 

The fact is not very strange that, so long as the situation remains such 
that accommodations can be reached which do not vitally impair the 
accumulation of capital and which, at the same time, bestow benefits 
on labour, such accommodations will go on being reached. It has never 
happened, and is not likely to happen now, that an exploiting class will 
be removed from power so long as it is able to make substantial 
concessions to the interests of other classes. What goes on in the 
meantime is the pressure of the one class for those concessions, and 
the resistance of the other class to every infringement of its interests. 
The outcome is the expression of this immensely complex social inter- 
action. It cannot be decided simply by reference to the blueprints of 
“social engineers”. They delude themselves when they fancy that the 
backrooms where they have set up their drawing-boards have been 
miraculously transformed into engineering workshops strategically 
placed in the corridors of power, and that everyone outside is just 
waiting patiently for claims to be met. 

The necessity for the eventual socialist solution of the contradictions 
of capitalism arises from the fact that capital cannot indefinitely go on 
in the same way exploiting labour whose forces of production are 
being continually revolutionised, and cannot indefinitely go on draw- 
ing raw materials and tribute from industrially underdeveloped 
dependencies. Social strains are unavoidable, and cannot but issue in 
revolutionary crises, when the ruling class can no longer go on ruling 
in the old way and is divided as to what to do, and the popular organ- 
isations are determined on a change which the rulers cannot concede. 
It is at such moments that the actual organisation and influence gained 
by revolutionary scientific socialism in the preceding years becomes 
decisive; and that the illusions of “social engineering” become manifest. 
They are revealed as no more than what Marx (analysing earlier class 
s truggles in The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte) called the 
“imbecility which holds those infected by it fast in an imaginary 
world and robs them of all sense, all memory, all understanding of 
the rude external world”. 

In “the rude external world” the fact which escapes the notice of 
all who dream of engineering a perpetual motion machine of reform 
by agreement is the fact (about which we shall have a lot more to say 
presently) that control of political power is in the hands of the big capitalist 
interests. They keep the power; and though they may discreetly keep 
it in reserve most of the time, it is there to be unmasked when occasion 
arises and exercised with authoritarian violence, both in foreign wars 


230 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


for the defence of capitalist profit and in repression at home* No 
schemes of social engineering can get round the fact that at some time 
or another this power will have to be challenged and overcome. 

Marx is rather severely reproached by Dr. Popper for having written, 
in the Preface to Capital , that “when a society has discovered the 
natural law that determines its own movement, even then it can 
neither overleap the natural phases of its own evolution, nor shuffle 
them out of the world by a stroke of the pen. But this much it can do : 
it can shorten and lessen the birthpangs”. He interprets this as meaning 
that Communists lack any policy based on working out on scientific 
principles what can be done for social betterment. For they believe 
that a violent revolution is historically inevitable and that therefore it is 
useless to attempt reforms and the only thing to do is by revolutionary 
propaganda and conspiracy to hasten the day of reckoning. This is 
“a peculiar variety of fatalism”, he says, and as such scientifically 
untenable and unacceptable to “social engineers” (PH. 51). 

But the scientific sense of Marx’s statement is quite clear, and so is 
its truth. 

Marx’s fundamental discovery of “the natural law” governing 
social changes was the discovery of the universal limiting conditions 
of men’s conduct of their social relations — much as fundamental 
discoveries of thermodynamics, for example, were discoveries of 
limiting conditions for the exchange of energy in physical systems, 
namely, that energy is conserved and entropy increases. Marx’s 
fundamental discovery was that relations of production have to be 
adapted to forces of production. So what was he saying in the Preface 
to Capital ? He was saying that to discover this law is not to discover 
how to abrogate it, how to “overleap” its limitations — any more than 
to discover the laws of thermodynamics is to discover how to abrogate 
them by constructing perpetual motion machines. But it is to discover 
what to expect to happen and how to act in concrete situations governed 
by the law— just as discoveries of thermodynamics are discoveries about 
how to make engines more efficient. Hence Marx said that when we 
have discovered that relations of production have to be adapted to 
forces of production, that does not enable us to contract out of the 
painful business of involvement in the processes of this adaptation, 
but it does enable us to work out ways of speeding them up and 
making them less painful. 

The social circumstances we are in (so Marxism explains to us) are 
governed by universal laws of social development, and so valid 


SOCIAL REVOLUTION AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING 2 } I 

expectations must be limited. Some things are possible, and other 
things are not. The indefinite and prosperous continuance of capitalism, 
free from revolutionary crises, is one of those that are not possible. 
On the other hand, if we are to develop and utilise ‘the forces of 
production we have already got for social welfare, we must find how to 
bring into being relations of production within which production can 
be organised for welfare. It is up to us how long it takes and how 
much we suffer: by militant organisation and wise policy we can 
“lessen the birthpangs”, but by no possible means can we dodge the 
issues, the crises and conflicts which the existing situation entails. 

This concept that we cannot “overleap” the consequences of the 
law that production relations must be adapted to productive forces, 
but that we can “lessen the birthpangs” occasioned by their becoming 
adapted, makes both scientific and political good sense. For example, 
capitalism could be let develop into the final crisis of World War Three — 
but this is not inevitable, and we can work to prevent it. Again, 
capitalism could be let develop the automation of production under 
private enterprise to the point where it creates vast unemployment. 
It is possible that things will be let develop in the U.S.A., for example, 
to the point where there are millions of desperate displaced people 
without support and without hope, making chaos and bloodshed a 
certainty; but this need not happen if in good time organised labour, 
in an orderly way, takes over control of the situation. 

The phrase “social engineering” is, all things considered, a pretty 
inept one. Those to whom Dr. Popper applies it are, if they can be 
called “engineers” at all, at all events remarkably innocent of scientific 
theory, like engineers who, when a few wheels start turning, think they 
have become masters of a perpetual motion machine. But if any sense 
is to be given to the expression, it is the policy of a united labour 
movement engaged in bringing into being and lessening the birth- 
pangs of a new social order, which deserves to be called “social 
engineering”. 


5 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 

I. INSTITUTIONS 

Social engineering, according to Dr. Popper’s conception, is concerned 
with institutions and their management. The social engineer does not 
directly deal with individuals, but he is both maintenance and con- 
struction engineer for institutions. 

Institutions (says Dr. Popper) become amenable to rational scienti- 
fically directed social engineering operations when they are demo- 
cratic. Non-democratic institutions cannot be engineered. For instance, 
social engineers entering the court of the Khalif Harun al-Rashid 
would have been liable to summary expulsion as unbelieving dogs, 
if no worse ; their field of operation is in the democratic institutions 
of modern capitalist society, where they are not merely tolerated but 
rewarded. Social engineering is thus the product of democracy. It 
was the development of democratic institutions that made possible 
the rational practices of social engineering, instead of the crude 
methods of violence which prevailed in earlier times; and their 
continued development not only requires the services of social engi- 
neering, but will be wrecked if violent methods of smashing up insti- 
tutions are chosen in their place. 

Dr. Popper thus sees social engineering as the democratic method 
of conducting human affairs, in opposition to violence. “There are 
only two kinds of government institutions,” he explains, “those which 
provide for a change of the government without bloodshed, and those 
which do not” (CR. 344). The former he calls democratic. If un- 
democratic types of institutions prevail, then, obviously, violence is 
the only means available for righting wrongs. “The use of violence”, 
he concludes, “is justified only under a tyranny which makes reforms 
without violence impossible, and it should have only one aim, that is, 
to bring about a state of affairs which makes reforms without violence 
possible” (2-OS. 151). 

These simple truths about democratic institutions are not, he 
charges, understood by Marxists. For, as we have already learned from 
him, “Marx . . . denounces the faith in a rational planning of social 
institutions as altogether unrealistic, since society must grow according 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


233 


to the laws of history and not according to our rational plans”. The 
laws of history are those of the development of class struggles. Con- 
sequently “Marxists have been taught to think in terms not of insti- 
tutions but of classes”. But whereas “Marxists nowadays do not think 
in terms of institutions . . . rationalists, on the contrary, are more 
inclined to rely on institutions for controlling men. This is the main 
difference” (CR. 345). 

Since, then, Dr. Popper says that Marxists are taught not to “think 
in terms of institutions”, let us see how he himself teaches us to think 
in terms of them. For in this matter of teaching us how to “think in 
terms of institutions”, he would have been well advised to attend to 
several large chunks of opaque matter in his own eye before concerning 
himself with motes in the eyes of his Marxist neighbours. 

Human progress, says Dr. Popper, depends on the design and 
working of institutions. “For institutions, like levers, are needed if we 
want to achieve anything which goes beyond the power of our 
muscles. Like machines, institutions multiply our powers for good 
and evil. Like machines, they need intelligent supervision by someone 
who understands their way of functioning and, most of all, their 
purpose . . .” (i-OS. 67). 

At the same time, the social engineer must remain cautiously aware 
of what is called “the human element” in institutions. He “cannot 
construct foolproof institutions, that is to say, institutions whose 
functioning does not very largely depend on persons: institutions, at 
best, can reduce the uncertainty of the personal element, by assisting 
those who work for the aims for which the institutions are designed, 
and on whose personal initiative and knowledge success largely 
depends” (PH. 66-7). 

Democratic institutions are not only the means we can use for 
engineering social achievements, they also provide “checks” on what 
would otherwise be the irresponsible power of certain individuals or 
groups of individuals. “This leads to a new approach to the problem 
of politics,” says Dr. Popper, “for it forces us to replace the question: 
Who should rule? by the new question: How can we so organise 
political institutions that bad and incompetent rulers can be prevented 
from doing too much damage?” (i-OS. 121). 

Thus he concludes: “Just as the task of the physical engineer is to 
design machines and to remodel and service them, the task of the 
piecemeal social engineer is to design social institutions and to re- 
construct and run those already in existence. . . . The piecemeal tech- 


234 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


nologist or engineer recognises that only a minority of social insti- 
tutions are consciously designed, while the vast majority have just 
‘grown’, as the undesigned results of human actions. But however 
strongly he may be impressed by this important fact, as a technologist 
or engineer he will look upon them from a ‘functional’ or ‘instrumental’ 
point of view. He will see them as means to certain ends, or as conver- 
tible to the service of certain ends ; as machines rather than as organisms” 
(PH. 64-5). 

Although he admits that in the past “the vast majority have just 
grown”, Dr. Popper asserts that institutions can be increasingly 
engineered once the practice of engineering them has been instituted. 
“Marx was quite right when he insisted that ‘history’ cannot be 
planned on paper,” he assures us. “But institutions can be planned; 
and they are being planned” (2-OS. 143). 

In the course of this instruction on how to “think in terms of insti- 
tutions”, Dr. Popper remarks, with justice, that “their construction 
needs some knowledge of social regularities which impose limitations 
upon what can be achieved by institutions. These limitations are 
somewhat analogous, for instance, to the law of conservation of 
energy, which amounts to the statement that we cannot build a 
perpetual motion machine” (i-OS. 67). He has very little to say, 
however, on this all-important topic of just what these “social regular- 
ities” are and in what way they “impose limitations”. Surely, to “think 
in terms of institutions”, this question needs looking into with care. 
That is exactly what Marxists have done. And if only Dr. Popper had 
done so, he too might have gained “some knowledge” of the “limita- 
tions upon what can be achieved by institutions”. He says that, for 
Marxists, “society must grow according to the laws of history and 
not according to our rational plans”. But what Marxists actually 
maintain is that “our rational plans” must take account of “the laws 
of history” — that is to say, of “social regularities which impose 
limitations upon what can be achieved by institutions”. Marxists 
do not believe that plans for a democratic perpetual motion machine 
are rational. 

Dr. Popper has very rightly observed that no social life can be 
carried on except through institutions of one sort and another. But 
when he teaches us to “think in terms of institutions” his lessons 
include no instruction about how institutions are instituted, under 
what conditions and limitations, or how one influences or limits 
another. The term itself is never clearly defined by him. “The term 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 235 

‘social institution' ”, he tells us, “is used here in a very wide sense, to 
include bodies of a private as w T ell as of a public character. Thus 
I shall use it to describe a business, whether it is a small shop or an 
insurance company, and likewise a school, or an ‘educational system', 
or a police force, or a church, or a law court” (PH. 65). He then goes 
on to point out that the term bears an even “wider” sense than these 
examples would suggest, and tells us: “Language is a social institution. 

. . . Writing is a social institution. . . .” (PH. 154). Thus any product of 
men's getting together in society, which regulates social activity, from 
language to a small shop, is an institution. He attempts no sort of 
analysis of institutions, as to their different kinds and their inter- 
connections. And that being so, the best we may expect from him is 
the best he gives us — the solemn assurance that, while institutions 
“just grow” in some unspecified manner, and are never “foolproof”, 
nevertheless some of them can be “planned”, subject always to un- 
stated “limitations”. If that is to “think in terms of institutions”, then 
by all means let us try to “think in terms of classes” and find out what 
the limitations are. 

We need not dispute that both languages and small shops are 
institutions — for, of course, if the term is used in a wide enough sense 
it can be made to cover both. But since the term is such a very “wide” 
one, how are we to “think in terms of institutions” without getting 
hopelessly muddled in the use of words? We must draw distinctions 
between institutions, in terms of their social functions, and examine 
how one set of institutions is conditioned by and grows out of another. 
That is what Marx did (although he seldom used the word “insti- 
tutions”, which was not so much in vogue when he was writing). 
Here in Britain today the English language, the capitalist system, the 
Marylebone Cricket Club, the Oxford and Cambridge Boat Race, 
Harrods, British Railways, the Prices and Incomes Board, Parliament, 
the Board of Trade, the trade unions, political parties and the Secret 
Police are all social institutions. If we want to know how we can use 
our institutions, and what to do about them, distinctions must be 
drawn and connections traced. Dr. Popper has stressed, for example, 
the importance of making our institutions democratic. But the term 
“democratic” applies only to some institutions, and makes no sense at 
all in relation to others. For example, how could the English language 
be democratic? Or a small shop, for that matter? 

As I have said, institutions, in the widest sense, are products of our 
getting together in society, and they regulate social activity. An 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


236 

institution is anything socially instituted. The sense of the verb “insti- 
tuted” can best be demonstrated by examples. Thus for communication 
we use language, and also telephones. Both are social products, but a 
telephone is a material implement, whereas a language is not. The 
telephone is manufactured, and the language instituted. The material 
object, a telephone, is not an institution — but the language we use 
when we communicate by telephone is an institution; and so is the 
Post Office (or in the U.S.A. the private company) which instals and 
controls telephones. Institutions are not material things : they cannot be 
seen or touched or pointed at, like material things. 

This non-material character of institutions is illustrated by the sort 
of explanations we have to offer when someone does not know what 
it is we are referring to when we refer to some given institution, 
and we explain it to him. Take the Oxford and Cambridge Boat 
Race, for example. To explain what “a boat” is, one must explain that 
it is a manufactured object which people can sit in and propel through 
the water. To explain what “the Boat Race” is, as an institution, is 
much more complicated. One must say: “Every year, at approximately 
the same date, two sets of eight young men, one set from Oxford and 
one from Cambridge, get into boats on the River Thames and propel 
themselves from Putney to Mortlake; they start when someone gives 
the signal, and the ones who arrive at Mortlake first are the winners.” 
One can of course (in this instance) “see” the Boat Race— but not in 
the same sense as one can “see” the boats. The Boat Race itself is “seen” 
only in the sense that one sees particular crews engaging in activity 
regulated in accordance with the institution. The Boat Race is like a 
Platonic Idea manifesting itself in time — and so is language, the Post 
Office, and any other institution. But yet institutions are not “eternal 
objects” which manifest themselves in the material world, but social 
products, instituted by men. 

The universal distinguishing feature of institutions is, that they have 
rules — conventional rules, definitive of each institution. People institute 
institutions when, for carrying out their various activities, they come 
to adopt certain rules of procedure — like the vocabulary and syntax of 
a language, or the rules of the Boat Race, or the multifarious conven- 
tions which govern the conduct of small shops or the Secret Police. 
Such rules generally get established by custom, as the activity develops, 
though they may also be, in certain cases, consciously formulated, 
agreed and promulgated. Very often, to begin with, they “just grow”, 
then at a certain stage of growth they are formulated and promulgated 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


237 


(language itself is a case in point). That is why our social activities may 
be said to be “regulated” by our institutions. 

In our social actions we use various material objects and material 
products for our purposes, in a way regulated by our institutions. 
Institutions with their rules of social behaviour are essential for social 
activities and the realisation of their purposes, for without this kind of 
regulation the activities could neither be conducted nor succeed. 
Indeed, all social activities are, and must be, institutionalised. There is 
not first an activity and then, later, an institution — but social activities 
only develop by developing the appropriate institutional regulation. 
Hence while one can, in words, distinguish a social activity and the 
institution for performing it, each is an abstraction apart from the 
other, and the concrete reality is the institutionalised activity. 

Of course, separate individual activities are not always fully institu- 
tionalised. For example, a man enjoying himself in a boat on the 
Thames is not engaged in institutionalised activity like the crews in 
the Boat Race; though even his activity is institutionalised to some 
extent, since he probably has to hire the boat and return it within a 
stated time, and the motions he performs are those which have been 
instituted in the development of boating, and have to be learned by 
him in the school of Thames boating — different in many respects from 
that of, say, the Yangtse. It is social activity that is institutionalised ; 
but so social is man that institutional rules are often obeyed in solitude, 
as when an Englishman exploring the jungle dresses for dinner. 

Clearly, it is important to distinguish between, on the one hand, 
the rules enjoined by institutions and, on the other hand, the objective 
laws characteristic of material processes and the objective requirements 
for dealing with them. This is a distinction which, historically, people 
have found it hard to draw. Thus, on the one hand, we imagine 
ourselves to be bound by the rules of our institutions as by natural laws, 
and on the other hand, we imagine natural laws to have been instituted 
somehow or other (by God) for the regulation of natural processes. 
There is, however, a pretty close connection between the rules of 
institutions and objective laws. The institutional rules of an activity 
have to accord with the laws which limit the activity, so that we 
cannot simply make up and alter the rules in any way we like. The 
purely conventional rules of a language, for example, have to accord 
with the objective requirements of communication which govern 
speaking. Again, such an institution as the Board of Trade, in Britain, 
has to be conducted in accordance with the objective requirements of 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


238 

the economy. We could neither institute rules for language just as we 
please, nor ^regulate trade just as we please. Moreover, in so far as 
activities deal with material objects, they have to be regulated in 
accordance with the natural properties of the objects. 

Institutions, then, are characterised by rules — rules which are 
themselves limited by the laws of the activities they regulate. In the 
second place, most institutions (but not all — languages, for example, 
are exceptions) require the construction of some sort of permanent 
material equipment for the purpose of carrying on the regulated 
activity. Thus, for example, many institutions are housed in buildings; 
others possess moveable equipment, such as the locomotives of British 
Railways or the cloaks and daggers of the Secret Police. 

This sometimes leads to verbal confusion in talking about institutions, 
when the material equipment is identified with the institution itself. 
Thus the words “The Board of Trade” may be used to denote the 
building in which the Board of Trade operates, or “British Railways” 
to denote the totality of railway lines and rolling stock. Again, the 
so-called social engineer is often very much concerned with material 
equipment — as when the educational reformer calls for the building 
of new schools, and for their architectural design in accordance with 
his recommendations about how the education inside them should be 
conducted. Again, he may call for “the taking over” of material 
equipment, as when he calls for his own nominees to be installed in 
positions where they will manage its use in different ways from that 
in which it was managed before. 

This general definition of institutions makes clear, then, a point in 
which Dr. Popper is interested, from the point of view of “social 
engineering”, when he asks how institutions can change, or be changed. 
In general, institutions are changed when the rules are changed — 
including cases where new material equipment is introduced, neces- 
sitating change of rules, and where change of rules necessitates pro- 
vision of new equipment. It also makes clear that there are, as Dr. 
Popper recognises but abstains from too much inquiry into, definite 
limitations both to how existing institutions can be changed and to 
what new or changed institutions can, in given circumstances, be 
introduced. 

In considering the development of institutions, as means and 
regulators of human social activity, and what can and cannot be done 
by way of purposively developing them in the future, it is evidently 
of great importance to consider both the character and objective laws 


THE INSTITUTION OP POLITICAL POWER 


239 


of interconnection and development of human social activities, and 
the modes of interconnection and interdependence of institutions in 
regulation of social activities. This is dialectics: fitting abstractions 
together in the concrete picture of how a process actually proceeds. 
It is in fact what Marx did, and Dr. Popper does not do — although 
Dr. Popper says that Marx teaches us not “to think in terms of insti- 
tutions” and that he himself is overthrowing Marx by performing an 
“institutional analysis”. From a very exact analysis of the laws of 
development of institutions Marx arrived at a practical political 
programme for changing them. It is from trite and empty phrases 
about “institutions” that Dr. Popper arrives at equally vapid general- 
isations about “social engineering”. 

Marx examined the connections and interdependence of institutions 
as they are formed for socially necessary purposes of human activity. 
He did not just talk about “institutions” in general, drawing no dis- 
tinction between languages and small shops, or between boat races and 
police forces. His analysis showed that the condition for all other 
human activities is the performance of social production, so that the 
techniques of production have to be instituted and, as an essential 
requisite first for social labour and then for everything else people do 
together, languages. To carry out production with the given tech- 
niques, with the given forces of production, men have to enter into 
corresponding relations of production — which therefore have also to 
be instituted, so that an economic structure and property relations are 
instituted. Then follows the institution of all the common activities of 
everyday life, from the acquisition and exchange of products to sports 
and the pursuit of arts and sciences. Lastly, to hold society together, 
there must be institutions of education, propaganda and management 
— schools, churches, legal institutions, government and political 
institutions, equipped where necessary with means of material coercion. 


2. INSTITUTIONS AND CLASSES 

The all-important “social regularity” which Dr. Popper overlooks 
when he lectures us about social engineering and institutions, and to 
which opacities in his intellectual retina render him quite blind, is the 
fundamental one which Marx discovered, namely, that to maintain and 
continue our social existence we have to enter into relations of pro- 
duction corresponding to our forces of production. 

Unless we instituted arrangements to carry on social production 


240 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


we could have no social life at all. In other words, the whole of social 
life is lived on the basis of having entered into and instituted definite 
relations of production. The production relations are the basis or 
“foundation” of all the institutions for regulating how we use or enjoy 
the various material means and mental abilities which we derive from 
having engaged in social production. As Marx said (in the Preface to 
the Critique of Political Economy ) : “The sum total of relations of pro- 
duction constitutes the economic structure of society, the real founda- 
tion on which rises a legal and political superstructure and to which 
correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of produc- 
tion of material life conditions the social, political and intellectual life 
process in general.” 

Relations of production include, as Marx went on to say, “property 
relations”. To enter into relations of production is to enter into 
regulative arrangements of production and distribution such that both 
means of production and products are treated as the property of definite 
persons or groups of persons. The institution of production relations 
is thus the institution of property — and so Marx called the institution 
of property “but a legal expression of the same thing”. 

Incidentally, property and all other institutional arrangements 
of society are dependent, not only on the development of techniques 
of social production, but on language. People had to speak, because 
social techniques of production involve this sort of communication. 
The institution of language then supplies the necessary means of 
communication for instituting everything else, including property. 
Indeed, every human attribute is dependent on language — labour, 
thought, property, religion, the sciences and arts, the whole develop- 
ment of social life and of the individual personality which is the 
product of social life. 

As Dr. Popper has said, many institutions “just grow”. That is to 
say, they are not begun, nor thereafter are they changed, as a result of 
anyone thinking up the rules and inventing the equipment, and 
everyone else then agreeing to do as he proposes. Rather do people 
enter into certain arrangements, and modify them, from the necessities 
of their social life, in accordance with what is possible and what is 
necessary for them to do in view of their productive forces. Marx 
devoted a great deal of attention to the question of how relations of 
production, and property relations, “grow”. People have entered into 
them, as he said, “independent of their will”. And so these institutions 
have appeared to the people who have regulated their lives by them as 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


241 


either natural or God-given laws of life, since they themselves never 
deliberately instituted them. 

Property, Marx showed, is derivative from division of labour in 
social production. With the very primitive techniques of small groups 
engaged in hunting and food-gathering everyone had much the same 
things to do, and such division of labour as there was came from the 
natural differences of the two sexes. The development of production 
techniques, such as began first of all with agriculture, the domestication 
of animals, and the development of various crafts, brought increasing 
division of labour ; and this division of labour led to means of pro- 
duction and products becoming allocated as the property of this or 
that person or group of persons. "The various stages of development 
in the division of labour”, wrote Marx and Engels in The German 
Ideology (I, 1), "are just so many different forms of ownership; i.e. the 
existing stage in the division of labour determines also the relations of 
individuals to one another with reference to the materials, instruments 
and products of labour.” 

Property relations have been, in their development, class relations. 
The division of labour has given rise to property, and the development 
of property to the division of society into classes. Classes are dis- 
tinguished by "the place they occupy in social production and, con- 
sequently, the relation in which they stand to the means of production”. 
Lenin, to whom we owe this brief definition of class distinctions, also 
elaborated the definition of "social class” at more length: "Classes are 
large groups of people which differ from each other by the place they 
occupy in an historically definite system of social production, by their 
relation (in most cases fixed and formulated in laws) to the means of 
production, by their role in the social organisation of labour, and, con- 
sequently, by the dimensions of the social wealth that they obtain and 
their method of acquiring their share in it. Classes are groups of people 
one of which may appropriate the labour of another, owing to the 
different places they occupy in the definite system of social economy” 
(A Great Beginning). 

The development of property divides society into classes when some 
acquire monopoly-ownership of means of production of such a kind 
as enables them to exploit the labour of others in definite ways. In the 
total social process of division of labour in production and distribution 
each class fulfils its role, whether of labour or of management. But 
the relations of classes do not constitute a harmonious system in which 
the function of one requires and complements the function of another 


242 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


(as in Plato’s ideal Republic, where “justice” consisted in each class 
being content to perform its proper role, or in the fable of Menenius 
Agrippa in Shakespeare’s Coriolanus). On the contrary, these relations 
are antagonistic. Exploiters and exploited continually dispute their 
share of the social wealth as well as the method of acquiring it, and so 
do exploiters with rival methods of exploitation. 

Classes are not institutions, but groups of people who have become 
differentiated as a result of the institution of property and of class 
relations. Thus the regulation and management of production in 
accordance with the institutional development of property relations — 
which have developed in a definite way because of the necessities 
imposed upon the regulation of production by definite developments 
of the forces of production — has divided society into social classes, with 
some exploiting others. As a result of the division into classes, distinct 
and antagonistic “class interests” have arisen. For institutions of 
property, with resulting class divisions, which have brought material 
benefits to one class have brought the opposite to another. Hence one 
class has had an interest in carrying on institutions in one way, and 
another class in carrying them on in another way, or in doing away 
with them and substituting different institutions. 

Institutions of all kinds are instituted, carried on and changed by 
people — and so, in a society divided into classes, the instituting , carrying 
on and change of the social institutions is done by people with divergent 
antagonistic class interests. Some classes are interested in preserving the 
existing class relations, and in setting up and managing other insti- 
tutions (for example, for government, for enjoyment of leisure and, 
in general, for all kinds of social purposes) on the basis of preserving 
the property relations; whereas other classes have contrary in- 
terests. 

What happens to institutions, and what is done with their aid, is 
decided, naturally enough, by the aggregate of interactions of all the 
persons concerned. Hence naturally enough (indeed, inevitably) what 
happens to institutions in class-divided society , and what is done with their 
aid , is decided as the outcome of class struggles. And this is equally true 
whether, in given circumstances, class struggles result in fundamental 
changes in institutions, or whether their temporary issue proves to be 
some sort of accommodation or compromise. The basic issue of class 
struggle is always that of preserving or changing property relations. 
The classes dispute their share of the social wealth and the method of 
acquiring it. In this dispute they form specific class-institutions of their own t 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


243 


and likewise dispute over the management and character of all sorts of other 
institutions . 

Classes are formed by the divisions introduced by property relations. 
They develop and consolidate their existence as classes by the develop- 
ment of institutions to preserve and push forward their interests in 
opposition to other classes, and of definite modes of consciousness or 
“ideologies” in which their collective determination to do so, and 
belief in the rightness of so doing, is expressed. Thus the modem 
working class, for example, was formed as a result of the divisions 
introduced by the relations of capital and wage-labour; it developed 
and consolidated its existence as a class by setting up working-class 
organisations and developing corresponding modes of consciousness. 

These are the conclusions scientifically drawn by Marx. We can 
now judge, therefore, whether it is true to say, as Dr. Popper has said, 
that “Marxists have been taught to think in terms not of institutions 
but of classes”. The implied disjunction is false. To think of social 
activities, as one is bound to do, and as Marx did, “in terms of insti- 
tutions”, is to think of them “in terms of classes”, since the people who 
set up institutions, and keep them going, are divided into classes. To 
think of any institutions connected with property and its administration 
otherwise than “in terms of classes” is to think of them in abstraction 
from the people who institute and use them, and from the actual social 
circumstances in which they institute and use them. Dr. Popper may 
favour that kind of metaphysical abstraction, and make out that when 
people are divided into classes they can nevertheless regulate their 
social activities through institutions as if they were not divided into 
classes; but we who have paid some attention to what Marx had to 
teach about dialectics are able to spot this false abstraction, and recognise 
how the categories of “class” and “institution” are connected in the 
actual concrete development of social activity. 

Classes are, we may note, and as Marx demonstrated, derivative 
from the development of relations of production, or the institution 
of property. Having, as a result of the division of labour consequent 
upon development of productive forces, instituted property relations 
which divide society into classes, people have thereafter been engaged 
in class struggles, and have changed their institutions only in the course 
of and as the outcome of class struggles. To listen to Dr. Popper on 
“the class struggle” one would be led to imagine, however, that for 
Marx the class struggle was some sort of fundamental law of society — 
so that one must “think in terms not of institutions but of classes”. 


244 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


But on the contrary, classes and class struggles are merely derivative 
from certain temporary historically-constituted types of social insti- 
tutions. Let us find how to get rid of these types of institutions and 
we shall have got rid of the class struggle. As a result of his paying no 
attention to the scientific analysis of class struggles as actually derivative 
from the institution of property, Dr. Popper’s own exposition is most 
inconsistently and curiously divided between imagining that classes 
have already disappeared, so that capitalist institutions can be managed 
as though there were no class struggle at all, and imagining that class- 
division is so necessary a feature of all human society that “a classless 
society” is “a utopia”. 

Revolutionary changes in institutions, that is to say, the ousting of 
one form of exploitation by another or, in socialist revolution, of all 
exploitation, are made necessary, as Marx showed, by the development 
of productive forces. It is evident enough that, in Europe for example, 
the sorts of improvements in agricultural techniques which took place 
under feudalism not only were not but could not have been effected on 
the slave estates of the ancient Roman Empire, and that the later 
developments of industrial techniques which took place under capital- 
ism could not have been effected so long as feudal relations hampered 
them. To make these things possible great institutional changes had to 
be effected. And these changes were effected as a result of long and, 
indeed, bloody struggles, in which one interest in the acquiring of 
wealth overcame another. Ruling classes succumbed, and institutions 
became radically altered, only when the former had been sufficiently 
weakened and divided as a result of their inability successfully to 
manage the existing economy through the existing institutions. 
Revolutions, necessary for the development of the social forces of 
production, are brought about as a consequence of clashes between 
people interested in different ways of acquiring their share of the social 
wealth. 

Today the necessity of socialist revolution is deduced from the fact that 
the full development of modern forces of production , including the full employ- 
ment of all human , technological and scientific resources , and the full enjoy- 
ment of the possible benefits^ is not possible so long as capitalist property 
relations prevail Once again the institutional changes that are necessary 
cannot be engineered except through the sort of “ engineering ” effected by 
class struggles. Dr. Popper (echoing the spurious wisdom of other 
bourgeois sages of greater antiquity) maintains that “a revolution” is 
a sort of unnecessary catastrophe, brought about as an interruption in 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


245 


orderly progress by some explosion of passions or conspiracy of 
bloody-minded agitators, which could have been avoided had the 
rulers been wiser. After the destructive anarchy of a revolution, order 
has eventually to be restored again and affairs brought back to normal 
— and such progress as may then be achieved could have been achieved 
just as well, and probably much better, without a revolution. This is 
to overlook the fact that the institutional changes effected by revolution 
were necessary, and could only be effected by class struggle and the 
decisive overcoming of one interest by another. Opposing “social 
engineering ,, to revolution, Dr. Popper tells us that “only by planning, 
step by step, for institutions to safeguard freedom, especially freedom 
from exploitation, can we hope to achieve a better world” (2-OS. 143), 
But to “safeguard freedom from exploitation” it would first be 
necessary to have instituted freedom from exploitation, that is to say, 
to have instituted socialist relations of production, that is to say, to 
have “engineered” a socialist revolution. 

3. CLASSES AND POLITICAL POWER 

Human social activity is, one need hardly stress, a very complex thing, 
and has got more complex as civilisation has developed. This complexity 
is due not simply to the multiplication of activities but to the cor- 
responding multiplication of institutions. For every social activity is 
regulated in one way or another and so has its institutions. As activities 
have multiplied, so there has developed activity the object of which is 
to direct, organise and control activities, to administer and to manage, 
and so also institutions of direction, organisation, control, adminis- 
tration and management. 

It is always as well to bear in mind, when talking about institutions, 
that they are of many distinct types and that what may sensibly be 
predicated of one type makes no sense if predicated of another. 
Statements about “all institutions” or “institutions in general” are, 
therefore, often merely nonsensical. When Dr. Popper lectures us 
about “social engineering” he is evidently specially concerned with 
institutions of management . The special character of such institutions is 
expressed in the fact that certain persons are “in charge” of them, 
“hold office” in them, and so on — statements which make no sense at 
all applied to other types of institution. With these institutions there 
enters into social life the element known as “authority” and “power”. 
And with this we must be concerned if we are to talk practical sense 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


246 

about “social engineering ,, to “plan step by step institutions to achieve 
a better world”. 

Authority or power has sometimes been understood by some rather 
simple-minded sociologists (including Duhring, whom Engels criti- 
cised, but not, of course, including Dr. Popper) as consisting simply in 
the possession by some persons of material means for intimidating and 
bossing others. Thus the man with the big stick is the man of power, 
and the origin of power is explained in a very simple way by the theory 
that one day long ago some people armed themselves with big sticks 
while the others weren’t looking. Power, however, is developed in 
society by the development of institutions of management, and is 
exercised through those institutions and in accordance with their rules. 
This fact is expressed in our language by the virtual equivalence of 
“power” with “authority”. Even tyrants, against whom Dr. Popper 
inveighs so much, are not able to seize power simply by beating other 
people over the head, but only by achieving authority in social insti- 
tutions and “planning and constructing” special institutions of their 
own for the exercise of their power. 

An important feature of the relation of institutions of management 
and government to other institutions is that changes in the latter are 
often effected through the agency and by the authority of the former. 
Thus, for example, changes in instituted propery arrangements may be 
made through the agency of legislation adopted and executed by 
government institutions. On a lesser scale, changes in the rules of 
cricket may be made through the agency of such a governing body as 
the Marylebone Cricket Club. On the other hand, the power of such 
agencies is not unlimited. They cannot effect any changes they like, 
but only those which conditions permit and which they can get people 
to accept. And at the same time, changes taking place in the sum of 
social activities, and particularly the development of class struggles, 
often demand and lead to considerable changes in the constitution and 
operation of power. 

The limitations of instituted power take the form that there are 
not only some things those in power cannot do but other things they 
are obliged to do. This applies to the power of tyrants and dictators 
equally with that of democratically instituted authorities. And it 
applies equally whether the powers concerned be the supreme powers 
of government or the lesser powers exercised in, say, women’s institutes 
or village cricket clubs. Every office is subject to obligations and 
restrictions. In a cricket club, for example, the pitch must be kept in 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


247 


condition, the games organised, and funds raised. The club committee 
is obliged to attend to such matters, since they are objective conditions 
for playing cricket. Somewhat similar considerations apply to govern- 
ments. And, in either case, if those in authority neglect obligations or 
seek to exceed their mandate, their power is either lost at once or 
begins to decrease. Thus Engels observed that, even in the case of 
“despotic” governments, “the exercise of a social function was every- 
where the basis of political supremacy . . . political supremacy has 
existed for any length of time only when it fulfilled its social functions. 
However great the number of despotic governments which rose and 
fell in India and Persia, each was fully aware that its first duty was the 
general maintenance of irrigation throughout the valleys, without 
which no agriculture was possible” (. Anti-Duhring , Part II, Chapter 

4). 

According to the scientific way Marx thought about institutions, 
a government or a state is a highly specialised type of institution 
(or rather a complex of specialised institutions), evolved subject to 
the requirements set by the mode of production. The specialised 
function of governing, performed through governments or state 
institutions, is, clearly, a case of division of labour, a product of the 
social development of division of labour. In primitive conditions, 
where the institution of tribal meetings and the leading role of head- 
men and suchlike suffices for directing and organising the simple com- 
munal life, specialised institutions of government are unknown. It is 
where division of labour has led not merely to a multiplicity of 
specialised individual activities which need co-ordination but to the 
institution of private property in means of production, and conse- 
quently to class divisions and antagonism of class interests, that the 
specialised kind of overall social management which is done by 
government institutions becomes necessary. At that stage these 
institutions are established, with certain individuals becoming govern- 
ors, office-holders and rulers. The multiplication of diverse and inter- 
dependent social activities and functions, each regulated and directed 
by its appropriate institutions, makes necessary the institution of a 
supreme power which will make as secure as possible the general 
conditions within which they can all develop; and at the same time 
the antagonisms entailed by property relations and class divisions make 
necessary the institution of a power strong enough to hold conflicts in 
check and prevent them from disrupting the social order. 

It is obvious that when the instituted relations of production are such 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


248 

that a comparatively few men of property are able to exploit the 
toiling majority, such a social order could not (human nature being 
what it is, as Thucydides used to say) last very long unless the state 
institutions served to uphold the property relations and hold back 
or punish any who might combine to resist exploitation. Whenever 
and wherever a social order has been -instituted based on the exploitation 
of man by man , it has included state institutions which serve to maintain 
that exploitation and , therefore y the interests of the principal exploiting class. 
It has endured only so long as such institutions endured, and has 
fallen only when its state institutions have succumbed either to internal 
revolution or external attack or a combination of both. 

Such, in its most general terms, is the Marxist theory of the origin 
of the state. Dr. Popper protests, with his customary vigour, that one 
cannot deduce conclusions about what can or cannot be done with 
something now from a theory of origins. States may have originated 
to uphold exploitation; but that does not necessarily imply that the 
social engineer today , who wishes to “plan institutions to safeguard 
freedom from exploitation”, must lead a revolutionary attack on the 
existing institutions of government — for whatever the origin of these 
institutions in ancient society, they may have changed fundamentally 
in the interim period. That is, of course, quite true. Nor are Marxists 
quite so stupid as to deduce conclusions about “the essence” of govern- 
ment institutions housed today on the banks of the Thames from 
hypotheses about the origins of those set up thousands of years ago 
on the Tigris and Euphrates. 

The point of inquiring into origins is that such inquiries throw light on 
functions. To propound a theory about how government activity and 
its state institutions originated out of the multiplication and diversifi- 
cation of human activities and relations consequent upon the develop- 
ment of social production (which is what Marx did) is to demonstrate 
the social functions which state power has fulfilled and to which its institutions 
have been adapted. So far as the present day is concerned, the question 
to settle is the factual question of whether or not state power is still 
required to fulfil, and still fulfils, analogous functions. Since capitalism 
continues to be based on the exploitation of man by man, and class 
struggle of exploited with exploiters continues, Marx concluded (and 
his conclusion continues to be verified) that in capitalist society 
state power continues to exercise the function of preserving the social order 
with its relations of exploitation. He therefore concluded that those who 
wish to get rid of exploitation, and to “plan institutions to safeguard 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


249 


freedom from exploitation”, should carefully examine the existing 
state institutions in order to ascertain just how they function to preserve 
exploitation. Having ascertained that, they can work out what to do 
in order to stop this function from being exercised. 

As for Dr. Popper’s “social engineers”, if they really want to 
“plan a better world” they ought at least to make some inquiry into 
what can be done about those institutions which confer powers to 
preserve a worse world. But that inquiry would upset Dr. Popper’s 
utopian hopes of “agreement”, for the powers in question are not 
likely to agree to abdicate without a struggle. He prefers to stick to his 
airy-fairy generalisations about “institutions in general”. 

According to Dr. Popper, the great superiority of a democratic 
system of government over a tyranny or dictatorship lies in the 
elaboration of institutional mechanisms for controlling office-holders 
and getting rid of them if they fail to give satisfaction. A bad tyrant 
like a bad prime minister can be ejected — but only by violence, 
whereas there are institutional provisions for changing the prime 
minister by constitutional means without violence. We may whole- 
heartedly agree that democratic government does possess this ad- 
vantage, and that accordingly the evolution of democratic institutions 
is progress in the arts of civilised living. All the same, we should qualify 
our assent to Dr. Popper’s jubilation over the perfection of our 
government institutions by asking what particular class interests 
these institutions have been evolved to promote, and what safeguards 
they include for the promotion of class interests. If “to achieve a 
better world” requires other interests to be promoted in opposition 
to those chiefly promoted by the existing institutions of government, 
our concern must be not so much to preserve our institutions as to 
change them — to remove safeguards for one set of interests and institute 
safeguards for another, to remove provisions to ensure that one set of 
interests are always satisfied and institute provisions to satisfy another. 
Precisely that is the political programme of the Communist Party. 

One complaint of Dr. Popper against the Communist Party is that 
Marx has taught it to “think in terms not of institutions but of classes”. 
But the great contribution of Marx to scientific thinking about 
institutions lay in his demonstration of the ways in which classes 
secure and promote their interests through the agency of institutions , and 
particularly of government institutions. 

It is a commonly held view, amongst those who do not go so far 
as to deny that class interests have an important influence in govern- 


250 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


ment (and, to do him justice, Dr. Popper should perhaps be included 
amongst them), that the function of government is to hold a kind of 
balance between class interests — to ensure that each interest is satisfied 
so far as is possible without injuring others. This view appears to receive 
confirmation in the custom of contemporary governments in the case, 
for example, of industrial disputes, when they generally invite each 
side to the Ministry of Labour in an effort to achieve a compromise. 
A less pleasing version of this theory of government is the view that 
governments retain power by playing off one interest against another 
(according to Charles II this was the secret of royal power in his own 
merry reign). The essential tenet of all such theories is that the govern- 
ment is not itself the instrument of any sectional interest (or if it is, 
it is a “bad” government), but that its function is to maintain law and 
order in the general interest of everyone — of “the people”, “the com- 
munity” or “the nation”. Dr. Popper’s view is evidently that, although 
in the bad old days governments were often far from disinterested, 
democracy as instituted in Great Britam and the United States of 
America has today actually achieved, or very nearly achieved, this 
object. 

The falsification of such theories in the case of every social order 
based on the exploitation of man by man, which includes contemporary 
capitalism, is ensured by the fact that, to preserve the basic property 
relations and to direct affairs within the framework they provide , the govern- 
ment has always got to uphold the essential interest of the exploiting against 
the exploited classes. This function of contemporary capitalist govern- 
ments is, indeed, demonstrated clearly enough in the case of industrial 
disputes, cited above. If the workers won’t accept a compromise 
acceptable to the employers, the government always proceeds to 
assist the employers in coercing them to accept it. Otherwise, as the 
spokesmen of the government always tell us, the very fabric of society, 
and the essential welfare of the community as a whole, would suffer. 
This function of governments is ensured by the fact that powerful 
well-established institutions exist to ensure that governments do 
function in that way. 

In general, authority, with the exercise of power, is instituted to 
serve a social function, to direct, organise and control certain social 
activities for certain purposes. Office-holders and persons of authority 
possess power on the condition that they fulfil their social function. 
The pt>wer they exert is the power socially instituted for preserving 
certain social relations and organising social activity within them, 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 25 1 

in which not only the office-holders but numerous other people, over 
whom the office-holders exert authority, have a direct interest. 

Even a tyrant must, if his power is to survive, take care of the 
obligations which his office entails to definite social interests. The 
successful tyrant is always, in certain matters of key social importance, 
a very conscientious person: he looks after irrigation works, for 
example, or he promotes trade and industry. Unconscientious tyrants 
(like several Roman emperors) have usually come to a sticky end. 
Today, in democratic capitalist countries, there have been evolved 
elaborate systems of institutional checks and counterchecks which 
ensure not only that office-holders carry out their functions to the 
satisfaction of capitalist interests, but that only persons of requisite 
social outlook and allegiance shall be selected for office, while the un- 
reliable are weeded out. In the democratic government of Britain, 
for example, this is provided for not (as is often suggested) simply 
by periodic elections, but by the party system, and the elaborate 
processes of behind-the-scenes jockeying by which civil servants 
influence ministers and industrial and financial interests influence civil 
servants and party executives. 

Of great importance, therefore, are the institutional mechanisms 
whereby, in die case of any exercise of power (whether it be that of a 
club committee, an oriental despotism, or a democratic government), 
the persons of authority are selected, kept in line, restricted in their 
exercise of power, and made to fulfil their functions and carry out 
their obligations to those whose interest is served by their activity. 

Class interests are asserted through institutions. This does not mean 
that all institutions promote exclusively class interests, for obviously 
they do not: it means that wherever there is a class interest there are 
institutions to promote it . It is quite true that the numerous individuals 
who compose a class do not one and all devote themselves to furthering 
the common class interest, since many individual causes lead individuals 
to pursue aims irrelevant to or conflicting with their class interests. But 
in the aggregate of social activities class interests get affirmed. The existence 
of a common class interest leads to institutions being formed to 
promote it, and these exert much greater power than belongs to 
institutions which serve only the eccentric aims of other groups of 
individuals. Thus in Britain today the Conservative Party is a far 
more powerful institution than, say, the Anti-vaccination League or the 
Lord’s Day Observance Society, and the Federation of British Industries 
than, say, the Canine Defence League. 


252 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


I have already observed that classes are developed and consolidated 
by the development of institutions to preserve and push forward their 
interests, in opposition to other classes. A class may be said to be 
powerful to the extent to which there has been established a system of 
institutions through which its interests are effectively promoted. When 
these include key institutions of government, the class concerned may 
be accurately described as “the ruling class”. Under such circumstances, 
state or political power effectively belongs to that class — as it effectively 
belongs to the capitalist class in capitalist countries today, democratic 
as some of them may be. 

“Classes never rule,” says Dr. Popper. “The rulers are always 
certain persons” (CR. 345). It would be difficult to imagine a more 
flagrant example of Dr. Popper’s illogical habit of posing false 
antitheses. Of course “rulers are always persons”. If I am asked, for 
example, who is the prime minister of Britain today (1967), I answer: 
Mr. Harold Wilson. Because as a Marxist I am of opinion that the 
capitalist class is the ruling class, I would not suggest that the capitalist 
class is the prime minister, but only that the prime minister is under 
the thumb of the capitalist class. Clearly, the sense in which a class 
rules is different from that in which an individual rules by virtue of 
his holding high office. The prime minister in Britain holds the highest 
office. But the government institutions of Britain are so contrived 
(not as a result of anyone’s plot but of a long process of historical 
growth and class struggle) that there are hundreds of institutional 
links whereby the capitalist class is able to prevent the appointment 
to high office of persons unreliable from the point of view of its 
class interest, and to ensure that those who wield power shall exert 
it in one way and not in another. That is how the capitalist class 
rules. If and when this complex institutional mechanism is broken, 
the capitalist class will no longer be the ruling class. Mr. Wilson, 
although he sometimes calls himself a socialist, does not even want to 
break it — nor could he, just on his own. For that there is required the 
concerted efforts of a great many people, united in institutions which 
promote other class interests. 

Instituted poiver is always tied up with the preservation and promotion 
of definite interests . This is as true of many lesser institutions (societies, 
clubs and such-like) as it is of state power and governments. Those 
who want to make a change are always up against a dead weight of 
traditional resistance. They often put this down to the obstinacy and 
thick-headedness of individuals — but it is more than that, it is the 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


253 


resistance of institutions geared to one interest to the promotion of 
another. In face of this, individuals, even those in office, may well 
feel helpless: “I would so much like to do something else, but Tm 
not allowed to.” To make a change another interest has got to organise 
effectively enough to break the links of power with the former interest . 

Marx’s class approach, teaching us to think of government institu- 
tions concretely in terms of classes, and not to think of them in the 
abstract, abstracted from the' promotion of aggregate class interest, 
teaches us that the capitalist order of society survives, and can only 
survive, thanks to the established institutional arrangements whereby 
the capitalist interest is served and preserved through the power of 
the state. To break the fetters which capitalist relationships impose 
on social production for social welfare it is necessary to develop 
working-class organisation in resistance to the instituted power, to 
the point where power passes into the hands of the working class. 
This means that not only must persons be put into power who are 
persons of socialist allegiance and with the will to execute a socialist 
programme, but that the institutions of power must themselves be 
altered and replaced, to the extent that the entire machinery of govern- 
ment is geared to instituting socialist relations instead of preserving 
capitalist ones, and its former links with capitalist class organisations 
are broken and different links consolidated. 

4. THE EXECUTIVE POWER OF THE STATE 

In his book The Origin of the Fatnily 9 Private Property and the State 
(Chapter 9), Engels described a “state” as a “power, arisen out of 
society, but placing itself above it”. Its first “distinguishing charac- 
teristic”, he continued, is that “the state is distinguished by the group- 
ing of its members on a territorial basis”; a state holds sway over a 
definite territory. Its second characteristic is “the institution of a 
public force” which “consists not merely of armed men, but also of 
material appendages, prisons and coercive institutions of all kinds”. 
Within the territory of the state, therefore, the officers of the state, 
who are “in possession of the public power”, act as “officials of society 
standing above society”. 

Marxism recognises very clearly, therefore, that a state, as an 
instituted system of management and government, has to include not 
only an organisation of administration but an organisation of coercion. 
Of course, with the growing complexity of social activity and social 


254 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


relations, modern states have come to provide a number of social 
services, to undertake a number of specifically economic functions, 
and to employ a very large number of officials for these purposes only. 
However, what remains essential for the existence of the state and of 
its power is the same as what has always been essential for any state — 
“the institution of a public force”, a coercive apparatus, with its 
command and administration. As Engels said in the chapter quoted, 
this public force first became necessary, and has been necessary ever 
since, on account of the appearance of class antagonisms within 
society. “In order that these antagonisms, classes with conflicting 
economic interests, shall not consume themselves and society in 
fruitless struggle, a power, apparently standing above society, has 
become necessary to moderate the conflict and keep it within the 
boimds of ‘order’.” There must be corps of armed men, prisons, 
effective material means to intimidate, coerce and punish, and a group 
of persons in command of these, so as to preserve the social order from 
any individuals or body of individuals whose activities threaten to 
disrupt it. 

In a number of studies of what were then contemporary or fairly 
recent events, Marx showed how in the course of the bourgeois 
revolution (by which is meant that series of events in which capitalist 
relations of production and democratic rights were instituted) the 
administrative, judicial and coercive apparatus of the state was 
immensely strengthened. The building of such a strong centralised 
apparatus was already beginning under the Absolute Monarchy. 
Today it is obvious that, compared with anything at the disposal of 
ancient despotisms or feudal states, the modem civil service, judiciary, 
army and police is an immensely powerful force. This tightly-knit, 
centralised, well armed and seemingly permanent force has become 
attached to the service of capital by thousands of ties of sentiment 
and interest; and it has acquired a permanence, stability and continuity 
independent of the comings and goings of ministries and governments. 

Marx was, of course, not the only observer to have noted this 
phenomenon. Balzac, that close student of the bourgeois revolution 
to whose acumen Marx owed a good deal, observed it before him. 
At the end of his novel Les Petits Bourgeois the hero joins the Secret 
Police (but do not ask for it at the library in the expectation of reading 
the adventures of a prototype James Bond) ; and the Chief of Police 
then congratulates him as a new recruit to that force “whose influence 
the last half-century has daily increased ... to whom all governments, 


THE INSTITUTION OP POLITICAL POWER 


255 


as they fall one on top of the other like houses of cards, come to 
ask for safety and for the power to rebuild their future . . . Govern- 
ments pass, societies perish or dwindle, but we — we dominate all 
things; the police is eternal.” 

I dare say those responsible for “security” in the British State today 
are not personally gifted with such powers of clear expression; but 
they could well talk in exactly the same way as they watch the rise 
and fall of successive Conservative and Labour governments. 

In The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (Chapter 7) Marx 
remarked on the growth of an “executive power with its enormous 
bureaucratic and military organisation” which, at every stage in its 
efforts to establish or preserve security for capital investment, the 
bourgeoisie has “found itself compelled to strengthen”. In times of 
weakness or danger this organisation is there to take command, 
independent of any democratic forms, for the purpose of preserving 
law and order. And ministers holding temporary elected office, while 
nominally the masters of the whole organisation, have left it intact 
to work on, administering and protecting the social system based on 
exploitation of labour; or, if they interfered too much, they have been 
thrown out of office. The machine works on while its masters come 
and go. And to change over to a Biblical metaphor, if they don’t 
suit it, it spews them forth. 

Marx pointed out, and what he then observed has continued to 
happen, that throughout a series of economic developments and of 
changes in the institutions of political power, the increasing activity 
and organisation of the working people, though playing a great part 
in all the events, did not prevent the growth of the “enormous 
bureaucratic and military organisation” which sustains capitalism. 
Indeed, protests and demands made it strengthen itself in order to 
cope with them ; and of late years, as labour organisations have been 
consolidated, it has been further strengthened and perfected by 
including machinery for labour consultation and conciliation. Marx 
concluded: “All revolutions perfected this machine instead of smashing 
it.” But if the exploitation of labour is ever to be ended, then instead 
of allowing this organisation of executive power to be strengthened 
and perfected the working class must use the power of its own organisation to 
smash it up , and institute a differently constituted and oriented executive power. 

In a modem capitalist society there is an immense complex of 
interlocked institutions through which affairs are conducted and 
managed. To mention only the most indispensable ones, there are the 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


256 

institutions of industry, of finance, of education and other social 
services, all of them with their own commands, and with control 
working on them both from “above” and from “below”. There are 
elected assemblies, councils and committees, and manifold arrange- 
ments for consultation. And the preservation and working of this 
entire institutional complex depends on the activity and vigilance of 
the central state institutions of administration and compulsion. Here 
is the apex of the power structure. Controls of power work from lower 
bodies to higher, and from higher to lower. From this centralised top 
organisation control is exerted from above over all the rest of the 
structure. The power so instituted is used both to direct and to protect 
the whole. 

How is this top organisation of power itself controlled? The whole 
institutional structure has developed on the basis of the development 
of capitalist relations of production, and in this development there 
are instituted close ties between the “bureaucratic and military 
organisation” of the state and the top ranks of industry and finance 
in control of “economic power”. As capital has become concentrated 
in fewer and bigger organisations, so has this tie-up become more firm. 

In such a country as Britain, for example, the commands of the 
civil service and the armed forces, together with the police and 
judiciary, have grown up over long years as protectors and executive 
officers of capital. It is not the case, of course, that certain tycoons in 
die City of London give the orders and these commands simply obey 
them. It is not as simple as that. And often it is the other way round. 
The system represents in fact a system of checks and balances, where 
those who occupy the corridors of power in Whitehall and those in 
the City both consult each other and manoeuvre against each other as 
individuals. But the institutional tie-up is complete, and is far stronger 
than any agreement or disagreement between individuals who hold 
office either in the state machine or in the organisation of big business. 
It is an immensely strong impersonal force working for the preserva- 
tion and profit of monopoly capital, which thus appears as an 
impersonal power far greater than any individual tycoon or govern- 
ment official. 

To break this tie-up, to take the bureaucratic and military organisa- 
tion into democratic control, under the leadership of labour organisa- 
tions, and use it to administer the change-over from capitalist to socialist 
relations of production, would amount to “smashing” the existing 
organisation. Dr. Popper and others, including the leaders of the present 


THE INSTITUTION OF POLITICAL POWER 


257 


(1967) Labour Government in Britain, say the organisation is efficient, 
so the sensible course is to work democratically to make it more efficient 
in the service of the common welfare — not to “smash” it. But a 
bureaucratic and military organisation, though often called “a 
machine” (and Marx himself used this word for it), is not something 
which, like a conventional machine, is built as a complex of parts 
subject to a motivation and control applied externally, so that anyone 
who can get his hands on to the controls can set it working on any job 
he chooses. The organisation has grown and been perfected as an 
organisation of capitalism, and of the capitalist tie-up of economic and 
political power. 

A lot is said nowadays about the struggle for power within democra- 
tic institutions of government. This is not a struggle to make any great 
change in the power-institutions and the ways they are controlled and 
work, but a struggle of individuals, political factions and political 
parties for particular coveted offices within them. Its premise is accep- 
tance of power-institutions more or less as they are, and its aim to get 
oneself and one’s friends into office and not be left in the cold outside. 
Those who engage in this sort of politics must watch their step, or 
instead of being able to use the power they have won to operate the 
policy of their choice they find that the machine which they have sought 
to control operates against them and throws them out. This point was 
well illustrated in C. P. Snow’s recent novel The Corridors of Power , 
where a minister, moved by his concern over the nuclear arms race to 
make proposals which business organisations, influential men of both 
parties and the top ranks of the civil service felt to be going too far, is 
forced to resign and is relegated to the position of an ineffectual back- 
bencher. (I say nothing of this novelist’s literary merits, though to 
mirror so clearly how affairs are conducted is perhaps itself an item of 
literary merit.) 

It should be added that as democratic institutions have developed, 
making ministers responsible to the electors (a development which has 
proceeded apace since Marx wrote), so have the means of propaganda, 
“mass media” and highly-organised party machines been perfected — 
financed by big business and controlled by it. Hence tins powerful 
apparatus is there to serve big business, to influence the electors, to 
manipulate votes and stampede public opinion as required. 


6 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 

I. DEFINITION OF DEMOCRACY 

The central political issue posed in capitalist society is to deprive the capitalist 
class of state power and vest it in the working class , so that this power can be 
employed to get rid of capitalism and construct a socialist society . This was 
the conclusion Karl Marx drew from his analysis of institutions, and 
particularly institutions of management and government, in terms of 
classes and class struggles. Dr. Popper, on the other hand, is of 
opinion that the central political issue is that of extending and streng- 
thening democracy. The issue is not between one set of rulers and 
another, but between democracy and dictatorship. In posing the issue 
in this way Dr. Popper denies that democracy is (as Marx maintained) 
an institutional form within which class-power is exerted, and maintains 
that it is, on the contrary, something which renders any issues of class- 
power irrelevant and obsolete. 

Dr. Popper traces back to Plato what he takes to be Marx’s confused 
and antidemocratic way of thinking about political power. “It is my 
conviction,” he says, “that by expressing the problem of politics in the 
form ‘Who should rule?’ . . . Plato created a lasting confusion in 
political philosophy” (i-OS. 120). The political issue then seems to be 
one of what persons or what groups or what classes should seize and 
hold on to power. But experience shows that whoever gets power is 
always under a strong temptation to misuse it. Of greater political 
importance, therefore, than the question of who holds power is the 
question of how to control their use of it. The key political question is 
not that of who should be entrusted with power, but rather the question 
(since none are really trustworthy with all power in their hands) of how 
to organise, through political institutions, the most effective checks on 
power. Democracy is the answer to this question. 

In The Communist Manifesto Marx and Engels said that to “raise the 
proletariat to the position of ruling class” was to “win the battle of 
democracy”. They said this, Dr. Popper suggests, because they 
thought that “democracy” means “the rule of the people” or “the rule 
of the majority” — and the proletariat is the majority. But on the con- 
trary, he tells us, democracy does not consist in “the rule” of anyone in 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


259 


particular, but in “institutional control’ * of those who hold office by 
those who do not hold office. Thus the Marxist “theory that the only 
alternative to the dictatorship of one class is that of another class” 
(i-OS. 122) is refuted by pointing out that the alternative to any dictator- 
ship, whether of a class or of an individual, is the democratic organisa- 
tion of effective “institutional control of the rulers”. But as for “the 
dictatorship of one class”, Dr. Popper has already contended that it is in 
any case an absurd idea, since “classes never rule. The rulers are always 
persons.” The so-called “dictatorship of the proletariat” is in reality 
nothing but the tyranny of a small clique masquerading as “the rule of 
the people”. 

The greatest advantage of democracy, Dr. Popper explains, is that it 
enables checks to be exerted upon the actions of the rulers or office- 
holders, whoever they are ; and for the rulers to be changed, if necessary, 
without violence. If there are no democratic institutions, or if these 
institutions are undeveloped or weak, the only way of checking the 
rulers, or of changing them, is to oppose some form of violence to 
the violence of the rulers. It is, of course, historically from opposition 
to the actions of tyrannical rulers that democratic institutions have been 
established. And Dr. Popper is accordingly able to state a definition of 
“democracy” in these terms: “By a democracy I do not mean some- 
thing as vague as ‘the rule of the people’ or ‘the rule of the majority’, 
but a set of institutions (among them especially general elections, i.e. 
the right of the people to dismiss their government) which permit 
public control of the rulers and their dismissal by the ruled, and which 
make it possible for the ruled to obtain reforms without using violence, 
even against the will of the rulers” (2-OS. 151). 

With this definition go two conclusions, with the first of which we 
are already familiar. 

The first conclusion is that “we may distinguish two main types of 
government”, namely, democracies and dictatorships or tyrannies. 
“The first type consists of governments of which we can get rid without 
bloodshed — for example, by way of general elections. . . . The second 
type consists of governments which the ruled cannot get rid of except 
by way of a successful revolution” (i-OS. 124). 

The other is that “the principle of a democratic policy” is “to 
create, develop and protect political institutions for the avoidance of 
tyranny. This principle does not imply that we can ever develop insti- 
tutions of this kind which are faultless or foolproof, or which ensure that 
the policies adopted by a democratic government will be right or good 


2<5o 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


or wise — or even necessarily better or wiser than the policies adopted 
by a benevolent tyrant. . . . What may be said, however, to be implied 
in the adoption of the democratic principle is the conviction that the 
acceptance of even a bad policy in a democracy (as long as we can work 
for a peaceful change) is preferable to the submission to a tyranny, 
however wise and benevolent” (i-OS. 125). 

Asa Marxist, I cannot but agree with Dr. Popper that “by a democ- 
racy I do not mean something as vague as ‘the rule of the people' or 
‘the rule of the majority' ''. Marx and Engels may perhaps be reproached 
because they often used the word “democracy' 'without defining it. 
But at all events it was not Marx but Abraham Lincoln who defined 
democracy as “rule of the people for the people by the people'*. And 
it was not any Marxist but the late John Strachey, after he had stopped 
being a Marxist, who defined it as the wide dissemination of power 
amongst the members of the community. This is the type of definition 
of “democracy'* which, as H. G. Wells relates, so much puzzled the 
immensely intelligent supreme ruler of the moon when the first man on 
the moon “gave him an outline of the democratic method”, explaining 
that on the earth “ all rule”. On hearing this, the Grand Lunar is reported 
to have “ordered cooling sprays upon his brow”. Democracy cer- 
tainly cannot be defined as a political system in which everyone, or 
even the majority, takes his share of “ruling”. Nor can it be defined in 
terms of what particular persons or classes hold power. That much is 
very clearly implied in Marx's insistence that there can be both capital- 
ist and socialist democracies, or in other words, that the capitalist 
class, a small exploiting minority, can and often does exercise effective 
power in governing the Eves of the majority through the operation of 
democratic institutions of government. To define “democracy” as 
“the rule of the people” would imply one or other of two conclusions, 
both of which Marxists would dispute: either there is no democracy 
in capitalist countries, or else political power in those countries does 
not effectively belong to the capitalist class. 

Whatever Dr. Popper may say we mean, Marxists cannot define 
“democracy” in terms of “who rules” or “who has the power”. On the 
contrary, we may agree with Dr. Popper in understanding it as a 
characteristic or form of power-institutions, or of institutions of 
management, defined in terms of the institutional control over office- 
holders or governors, including their dismissal and replacement, which 
is exerted by those whom they govern. 

For us, therefore, as for Dr. Popper, the practical test of whether 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


261 


an institution through which affairs are managed and people are 
governed is democratic, or of how far it is democratic, lies in deter- 
mining whether, or how far, it includes institutional provisions by 
which those who do not hold office can question , check and control the 
policies of office-holders , and confirm them in , or dismiss them from 
office . This test suffices for us to criticise imdemocratic procedures, and 
to propose or support democratic ones, whether in the management of 
a cricket club, a trade union or the national economy. We are in 
favour of democracy. And we are in favour of it for very much the 
same reasons as Dr. Popper declares himself in favour of it: it is a 
bulwark against tyranny, a means of getting rid of bad rulers, a means of 
getting policies discussed and criticised, and a means of securing reforms 
without violence. 

But Dr. Popper, apparently without noticing it, or at any rate 
without being too scrupulous about it, jumps from defining democ- 
racy as that characteristic of institutions of management whereby 
office-holders are made answerable to other people, to defining “a 
democracy” as a complete political system, or as “a set of institutions” 
which, all together, “permit public control of the rulers . . . and make 
it possible to obtain reforms without violence”. Yet it is a far cry from 
establishing particular democratic institutions and enjoying through 
them certain democratic rights, to establishing a complete “set of 
institutions” to do all the work of government, and which is a democ- 
racy and nothing but a democracy. It cannot be too much emphasised 
that democracy is a characteristic of institutions of management , or a form 
of such institutions , and not itself either an institution or a set of institu- 
tions. While there are many democratic institutions through which 
government is carried on, there is nowhere any complete set of insti- 
tutions of government in which democratic methods are not countered 
by, and often at war with, undemocratic methods. There is no such 
thing as “a democracy” pure and simple, but only various kinds of 
democratic institutions. All of these are historically formed out of the 
exigencies of particular circumstances, in particular conditions of class 
relations and class struggles. 

When Dr. Popper divides all governments into democracies and 
tyrannies he is adopting a principle of classification which will not fit 
the facts, as is obvious if one considers cases. Were the Tudor govern- 
ments in England tyrannies or democracies, for example? One can 
hardly call them either without qualification, though to call them 
“democracies” would perhaps require more qualification than to call 


262 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


them “tyrannies”. This proposed classification of all governments is 
far from accurate. And its chief failing becomes evident when one con- 
siders how particular governments have actually been constituted and 
what they have done. Thus, for example, the ancient tyranny of 
Peisistratos in Athens was in its social basis and functions very different 
from the modem tyranny exercised by Hitler in Germany, inasmuch 
as what Peisistratos did was to break the pow T er of the former ruling 
class, whereas what Hitler did was to ensure that the ruling class could 
rule without restraint. Again, the admittedly high-handed and often 
violent policies of the Tudor monarchs effectively checked the former 
rampages of feudal lords and so provided conditions for the subsequent 
growth of industry and commerce, whereas the conquests of tyrants of 
the type of Ghenghiz Khan in Asia plundered and broke up the civilisa- 
tions on which they imposed themselves. Evidently there are important 
distinctions even between tyrannies. As for democracies, the democ- 
racy of ancient Greece (the road to which in Athens w T as in fact pre- 
pared by the former tyranny) provided methods of institutional con- 
trol for carrying on the exploitation of peasant proprietors and slaves, 
whereas the democracy we at present enjoy in Britain or the U.S.A. 
provides institutional methods for carrying on capitalist exploitation. 

There is, of course, a clear distinction between democratic and 
tyrannical methods in government, inasmuch as one can distinguish 
democratic and tyrannical elements in particular governments and, in 
some cases, describe governments as wholly tyrannical. But that does 
not mean that simply by distinguishing tyrannical and democratic 
methods all governments may be neatly divided into democracies and 
tyrannies, and still less that the distinction suffices to sum up the part 
which any particular government has played in the progress or other- 
wise of society, including in the political advance to “democracy and 
freedom”. 

Of primary importance in the assessment of governments is the 
distinction which Marx has the merit of stressing (he was not himself 
the first to recognise it) — the distinction between governments in 
terms of the class relations they foster and the classes whose interests 
they promote. When Dr. Popper says that “we need only distinguish 
between two forms of government . . . i.e. democracies and tyrannies” 
(2-OS. 161) he ignores the fact that there are also to be distinguished 
(amongst others) slave-owners’ governments, feudal governments, 
capitalist governments and socialist governments. If governments 
are considered in these terms, it is possible not only to distinguish but 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


263 

also to explain the varying democratic and undemocratic elements in 
their modes of operation, whereas if they are all lumped into the two 
exclusive categories of “democracy” and tyranny” not only are these 
important differences between governments obscured but a great 
many governments refuse to fit into either category. Dr. Popper rather 
pointedly suggests that Marx’s ideas about government were highly 
doctrinaire. But if by “doctrinaire” one means introducing hard-and- 
fast distinctions which do not fit the facts and cover up important 
features of the facts, it is Dr. Popper himself who is doctrinaire in his 
ideas about government. 

Thus Dr. Popper says roundly that in “a democracy”, as distinct from 
a tyranny, there is “public control of the rulers”. But how far and in 
what sense is this true in such a democracy as Britain or the U.S.A., for 
example? Such institutions as general elections establish public control 
inasmuch as rulers (meaning office-holders) have periodically to submit 
themselves to election. But “the public” are a very heterogeneous 
bunch in our class-divided society, including not only wage and salary 
workers and professional people, but bankers, industrialists and finan- 
ciers. The institutions which in their totality permit a certain amount 
of generalised “public control of the rulers”, permit a more continuous 
and stringent control over them by that section of “the ruled” who 
constitute the capitalist class — who for this very reason are described by 
Marxists as “the ruling class”, even though they do not count for much 
in terms of their votes. And furthermore, while the rest of “the public” 
are deciding how to vote, their sources of information, and the propa- 
ganda agencies which influence their ideas, are very little controlled by 
them. Democracy includes powerful institutions for controlling the majority of 
the nominal controllers , as well as for ensuring continuously effective control by 
a minority . So long as the -capitalist class within a democracy can hold onto 
these types of control it remains effectively the ruling class . 

Further, these characteristics of the actual methods of control in 
practice qualify that other property which Dr. Popper praises in demo- 
cratic institutions — that they “make it possible” to secure “reforms 
without violence”. 

True, in Britain the institutional rules of the democratic electoral 
system “permit the ruled” to vote into office a parliamentary majority 
to introduce any reforms they wish. But it does not follow from this that 
the British political system does not include institutions which might 
well not permit certain reforms to be operated. Thus while the finan- 
cial institutions, under present control, can do a great deal to sabotage 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


264 

many intended economic reforms, the judiciary, the civil service, the 
police and the armed forces are so controlled, despite their obligations 
to parliament, that at a pinch they could act not only to sabotage re- 
form but even to nullify it by violence. Thus independent action by the 
military has often been known in very recent times in democracies — 
for example, the action of the military in Ulster to prevent the opera- 
tion of the then British Government’s Irish policy, to say nothing of 
more recent examples in Africa, Asia and Latin America, and in Europe 
too. Are we quite sure that the present system of command in Britain 
and the United States could permit no similar actions in any cir- 
cumstances? 

Indeed, the management institutions of Britain and the United States 
in their totality are so constituted that even far less radical reforms 
than, say, socialising capitalist property have not been permitted with- 
out violence. The violent scenes often enacted when any considerable 
number of “the ruled” have attempted to exercise their democratic 
right to demand such reforms as the abandonment of nuclear weapons, 
or the ending of racial discrimination, or (in time of unemployment) 
work or full maintenance for the unemployed, bear witness to this. So 
how democratic is democracy? What some institutions permit and 
make possible, other institutions do not permit or make, if not im- 
possible, at least difficult and dangerous. 

Perhaps it is because he is so well aware of these features of our 
democratic system that Dr. Popper so earnestly advocates that no 
reforms should ever be attempted except very little ones. One must 
be as careful not to go too far in a democracy as under a tyranny, lest 
the powers that be are provoked to violence. 

Dr. Popper r who accuses Marxists of such dismal confusion of 
thought on the question of democracy, is not altogether clear himself. 
Thus he tells us that “the various equalitarian methods of democratic 
control, such as general elections and representative government, are 
to be considered as no more than well-tried and . . . reasonably effective 
institutional safeguards against tyranny, always open to improvement” 
(i-OS. 125). This statement has the undoubted merit of bringing out 
two important truths. One is that democratic institutions are evolved 
historically in the struggle against various forms of oppression — that 
they are not set up in accordance with some perfect model of “democ- 
racy” but in accordance with the conditions and needs of particular 
class struggles. The other is that democracy is not an “all or none” 
characteristic of political systems, but that particular political systems 


THE BATTLE OP DEMOCRACY 


265 

provide a variety of methods of institutional control over rulers, some 
more and some less democratic, and that the measure of control which 
may be exerted through one institution in the interests of one class 
may be counteracted by the greater measure of control exerted through 
another institution in the interests of another class. But yet in writing 
about democracy Dr. Popper postulates the existence of “a set of 
institutions which permit public control”, without taking into account 
the fact that society is divided into classes and that there are powerful insti- 
tutions for pushing the interests of classes — institutions for assuring that 
effective control , the last word , shall belong to one class and not to another . 

True, democratic institutions do provide “institutional safeguards 
against tyranny”. But that is not the same thing as providing “equali- 
tarian methods of control”. When he speaks of “equalitarian methods” 
Dr. Popper implies that no one class has more weight in the exercise of 
control than any other. But this could never happen, and certainly has 
never been known to happen, in a class-divided society in which an 
exploiting class, owning means of production, can exist only by 
maintaining its general management of the processes of production. In 
the system of control of the office-holders in such a society the insti- 
tutions of control allow to some groups among “the public” far more 
controlling influence than others, and their influence is measured not 
by their abilities or their devotion to the public welfare, but by their 
property. 


2. PUBLIC CONTROL AND CLASS CONTROL 

The fallacy in Dr. Poppers account of democracy (and not of his 
account alone) lies in his defining it simply as “public control of the 
rulers” without asking how, in a society divided into classes, such 
control is divided between the classes. 

It is because he ignores the existence of classes, and ignores the ways 
in which people in the aggregate work for and protect class interests 
through institutions, including democratic institutions, that Dr. 
Popper can counterpose as he does the issue of extending and strength- 
ening democracy and the issue of class-power. It is only another 
example of the fallacious posing of antitheses. If we think concretely 
about the real social relations and social processes which confront us, 
instead of engaging in merely abstract phrases, it becomes evident that 
the question of extending and strengthening democracy raises the question of 
class power , and does not supersede it. Similarly the question of class 


2 66 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


power raises that of extending and strengthening democracy . These questions 
mutally involve and do not exclude one another. This is what 
Marx discovered with his dialectical approach to the study of social 
questions. 

Dr. Popper counterposes to the issue of one class or another exer- 
cising power through the government institutions the issue of insti- 
tuting checks on the power of individual office-holders. He sees as all- 
important the question of whether such checks, or such control, can be 
exercised without violence or only by the use of violence. In the first 
case there is democracy, in the second tyranny. But the institution of 
non-violent methods of checking and controlling office-holders, 
including dismissing them, does not remove the issue of class power. 
For the issue remains of whether the political system permits or does 
not permit an exploiting class effectively to protect, through the insti- 
tutions of government, its property rights and its mode of exploitation. 
Marxists entirely agree about the desirability of instituting forms of 
democratic control over office-holders. But that does not prevent us 
from advocating effective measures to put an end to exploitation, 
including government institutions which will effectively enable those 
who were exploited to ensure that they shall be exploited no more. We 
agree with Dr. Popper in not wanting to be ruled by tyrants — whom 
he has defined as office-holders who cannot be removed from office 
except by armed force. But we do not want to be ruled by servants of 
the capitalist class either. 

Arguments about democracy are always deceptive when they ignore 
the existence of classes, class struggles and class power. This is what 
Dr. Popper ignores when he classifies all governments as democracies 
or tyrannies, and says that democracy is simply a system of institutional 
control over office-holders which permits them to be shifted without 
violence. And he goes on ignoring it when he holds forth about “the 
democratic principle” or “the principle of a democratic policy”. He 
represents democracy as the institution of “safeguards against tyranny”, 
paying no attention to the safeguards which continue to be required, 
and are always instituted, for class interests. 

When Dr. Popper says that “the principle of a democratic policy” is 
to develop and protect “political institutions for the avoidance of 
tyranny”, his “democratic principle” is so conveniently vague and 
abstract, in relation to contemporary problems, that it can be, and 
regularly is, appealed to in justification of political institutions to avoid 
damage to capitalist interests. This is represented as avoiding the tyranny 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


267 

of prohibiting one class from exploiting another. Of course a demo- 
cratic policy is opposed to tyranny, and will not permit rulers to rule 
without a measure of democratic control. But to establish political 
institutions to safeguard the majority from being exploited by the 
minority demands establishing a greater degree of democratic control 
than is permissible with political institutions that ensure that the major- 
ity shall go on being exploited. Marxism poses the issue of a policy to 
establish and build the former institutions, and to disestablish and 
destroy the latter. That is not opposed to any genuine democratic 
principle of public control over office-holders. 

Dr. Popper tells us that the policy advocated by Marx “amounts to 
doing the work of the enemies of the open society . . . And against the 
Manifesto which says ambiguously: ‘The first step in the revolution of 
the working class is to raise the proletariat to the position of the ruling 
class — to win the battle of democracy’, I assert that if this is accepted as 
the first step, then the battle of democracy will be lost”. Where Marx 
went wrong was in telling the working class “that there is only one way 
to improve things, that of the complete conquest of power. But tins neglects 
the one really important thing about democracy, that it checks and 
balances power” (2-OS. 162). If ever a single person, group or class 
achieves “the complete conquest of power” there is an end to democ- 
racy, and tyranny holds sway. Democracy is a matter of “checks and 
balances”. Rather than one person, one group or one class exercising 
unchecked and unbalanced power, different persons, groups and classes 
check and balance each other. 

However, there is a contradiction here, and Marxists see it quite 
clearly. On the one side is the demand in a capitalist society that the 
capitalist class shall always have its say in the control of government, 
and that government, while it may be got to do something to check 
the rapacity of individual capitalists and make them compromise their 
interests, will never suppress them. On the other side, in contradiction 
to this, is the demand that institutional progress shall continue towards 
“equal democratic rights” and “freedom from exploitation”. We 
cannot have both. If institutions are democratic in so far as all persons 
concerned have rights of control over the office-holders, it is these 
specific rights which are presumably to be classified as “democratic 
rights”. They are not equal so long as membership of a propertied 
class confers a power of control not possessed by other classes, any 
more than there is “freedom from exploitation” so long as the exploit- 
ing class retains the right and the power to go on exploiting. So if we 


268 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


are going to satisfy the demand of the capitalist class to retain its stake 
in society and the rights that go with it we must set strict limits to 
institutional progress towards “equal democratic rights” and “freedom 
from exploitation”. 

The establishment of democratic institutions has always been a 
matter of the fight for them against opposition; and Dr. Popper 
himself speaks of “the battle for democracy” (2-OS. 161). What he 
does not see is that this battle is always a class battle . Democratic insti- 
tutions guaranteeing democratic rights have been fought for and 
introduced by exploiting classes only when they were concerned to 
protect themselves and others from the oppression of some other form 
of exploitation than their own, and to secure at least their own control 
over the activities of persons placed in office. No more than this has 
ever been secured without organised pressure from the exploited, 
while the exploiters for their part contrive to limit the democratic 
features of government institutions and to rig them in their favour. The 
history of the working-class movement has been a history of organised 
class struggle, not only to secure better conditions in the face of capi- 
talist exploitation, but to win democratic rights and to have them em- 
bodied in law. Traditionally, the working-class movement has been 
democratic. It has fought for democratic rights because these are the 
political means to its economic emancipation. Its own organisations 
have been democratic too — so that for all their defects they have set the 
model for democratic methods of conducting business. The advice of 
Marxists to the working-class movement is, and has always been, to 
organise democratically, to fight for democratic rights, and to fight 
against every attack and restriction on these rights. But rights are won 
in order to be used. And Marxists advise the working class never to be 
kicked around by those who consider the interests of capital and 
profit paramount, and never to be duped into accepting their policies, 
but to use its organisation to defend and improve its standards and, 
by defeating the policies and overcoming the opposition of the capital- 
ist class, to lay the foundations of a co-operative socialist common- 
wealth. 

Dr. Popper says that there is “ambiguity” in the statement of The 
Communist Manifesto that “to raise the proletariat to the position of the 
ruling class” is “to win the battle of democracy”. There is considerable 
ambiguity in his own dispositions for winning that battle. On the one 
hand he is for “equal democratic rights” and “freedom from exploita- 
tion”; on the other hand he is for perpetuating capitalist control over 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


269 

government and capitalist exploitation of labour. There is no ambiguity 
at all in the programme of The Communist Manifesto. It is to continue the 
struggle of working people for democratic rights to protect themselves from 
exploitation and its consequences up to the point of abolishing exploitation 
and the power of exploiting classes . 

From his “democratic principle” Dr. Popper deduces the 
consequence that it is better to accept a bad policy in a democracy than 
to submit to a wise and benevolent tyranny. Why should we do either? 
And the choice is in any case a somewhat unreal one — for whereas we 
suffer much from bad policies in a democracy,- the prospect of relief 
through a “wise and benevolent tyranny” is remote. Dr. Popper is 
evidently merely counselling patience in putting up with bad policies. 
“You may not think much of the established parties but don't be 
kidded by the Communists who invite you to submit to a wise and 
benevolent tyranny administered by themselves. Democracy is always 
better than tyranny.” But it is Dr. Popper who is kidding us. Com- 
munists do not invite you to submit to a tyranny, whether benevolent 
or otherwise. They simply urge you not to accept bad policies. They 
point out that in a democracy we have democratic mass organisations, 
which we can use to compel a better policy, and to counteract the 
influence of those whose interests have dictated a bad policy. The work- 
ing class should use its democratic rights to enforce its interests when 
these are threatened by policies dictated by capitalist interests. 

Dr. Popper condemns the policy “of Marxist parties” because it 
“can be characterised as one of making the workers suspicious of democ- 
racy” (2-OS. 161). But Marxism does not make the workers “sus- 
picious of democracy”. It makes them suspicious of the capitalist class. 
It makes them suspicious of the ways in which institutions are managed 
and governments engineered in the capitalist interest. It makes them 
suspicious of the ways in which the agencies of information and propa- 
ganda are actually controlled, of the ways in which education is 
actually conducted, of the ways in which the judiciary actually 
functions. It makes them suspicious of the ways in which, whenever a 
crisis threatens the profit system, governments invariably launch attacks 
on the standards of the working class. It makes them suspicious of the 
ways in which the police break up peaceful protests against social 
injustices and preparations for war and spy upon and intimidate their 
organisers, and of the ways in which the armed forces are sent all over 
the world to protect the investment of capital. It explains how and why 
these things happen, and says that they had better be opposed and 


270 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


stopped, and that the only way to oppose and stop them is by demo- 
cratic mass organisation. 

Dr. Popper has told us himself, and with truth, that no democratic 
institutions are “foolproof”. The policies operated through them are 
not, he tells us, necessarily “right or good or wise”. It is up to us to try 
to make them so, he suggests, through the public control over policies 
which democratic institutions permit. But he might have added that 
there is another way in which democratic institutions are not foolproof 
— they can always be rigged. 

Everybody who has anything to do with any democratic organisa- 
tion knows very well that conferences, for example, can be rigged, if 
the organisers have decided beforehand what they want to put across 
and have managed to deceive the delegates either by lies or by with- 
holding information. Similarly governments are rigged when the 
electors return members to parliament who have promised to protect 
their interests, and then the majority party sets up a cabinet which 
works all the time in the closest consultation with a small gang of 
monopolists and uses all the powers of force and persuasion vested in 
the state machinery to put across the measures which they have agreed 
upon behind the scenes. If the people whose interests are at stake in the 
policies operated through democratic institutions are thus deceived into 
accepting policies contrary to their interests, they may be said to have 
been made fools of, if no worse. The value of Marxism to the working- 
class movement is that it teaches the workers not to be made fools of by 
those adept at rigging democracy against the workers, and to work for 
a democratic policy to defend the interests of working people against 
capital, and ultimately to emancipate society altogether from all forms 
of the exploitation of man by man. 

“We must learn”, says Dr. Popper, “that in the long run all political 
problems are institutional problems, problems of the legal framework 
rather than persons, and that progress towards more equality can be 
safeguarded only by the institutional control of power” (2-OS. 162). 
How very true that is ! With institutions as they are in Britain at the 
time of writing, if we vote out Mr. Wilson we will only get Mr. Heath 
instead — and a lot of good that will do us ! The real political problems 
for us are certainly not merely those of one person rather than another, 
but of “institutional control of power”. The same applies to Americans 
when it comes to a presidential election. That is exactly what Marxism 
teaches. But where Dr. Popper’s arguments, and all arguments like 
them, deceive us about democracy is in their assumption that the 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


271 


democratic “institutional control of power” operates independently of 
classes, class interests and class struggles. 

This assumption is not true, and could not be true so long as 
antagonistic class interests continue to exist. The “institutional control 
of power” presents a battle for control between different classes, each of 
which has its organisations and other institutional means for pushing its 
interests and aims. At the present time, in capitalist countries like 
Britain and the U.S.A., institutional control, as operated through the 
entire “legal framework”, is rigged in favour of the capitalist class, 
which through its organisations and institutional facilities maintains a 
pretty firm control over the conduct of affairs. This means that the 
institutions of government, in their totality, confer effective power 
upon the capitalist class. That class still virtually exercises, as Marx 
said, “a dictatorship”. Marxism poses the question of how to alter this 
state of affairs — of how to build a democracy in which the “institutional 
control of power” will ensure the advance from capitalism to socialism. 

3. POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC POWER 

One thing that stops Dr. Popper’s objections to Marxism from be- 
coming boring is that they are full of surprises. And perhaps one of the 
chief surprises is that, when he comes to explain the basic errors of 
Marx’s theory of “the dictatorship of the proletariat”, and to show how 
these led Marx to advocate replacing democracy by dictatorship, he 
informs us that Marx made the mistake of adopting a “disparaging 
attitude towards political power” (2-OS. 126), and that Marxism is 
a “doctrine of the impotence of political power” (2-OS. 129). 

This, he explains, was the result of Marx misunderstanding the 
distinction between “political” and “economic” power. Marx thought 
that economics ruled politics, so that political power was always secon- 
dary to economic power and impotent in face of it. Dr. Popper even 
has a kind word to say in excuse of this error. For Marx “discovered 
the significance of economic power; and it is understandable that he 
exaggerated its status. He and the Marxists see economic power every- 
where” (2-OS. 127). It was this that led him to “the dogmatic doctrine 
that economic power is more fundamental than physical power, or the 
power of the state” (2-OS. 128). 

But on the contrary, says Dr. Popper, “it is only the active interven- 
tion of the state — the protection of property by laws backed by 
physical sanctions — which makes wealth a potential source of power; 


272 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


for without this intervention a man would soon be without his wealth. 
Economic power is therefore entirely dependent on political and 
physical power” (2-OS. 128). 

If it were not that I hesitate to describe Dr. Karl Marx as Dr. Karl 
Popper’s grandmother, I would say that the latter is singularly unsuc- 
cessful in this attempt to teach his grandmother to suck eggs. It will 
perhaps be remembered that in contradiction to what he here tells us, 
Dr. Popper told us elsewhere that to say the state protects property is 
nothing but an “historicist” dogma about “the functions of the state”. 
Marx, on the other hand, always consistently maintained that the 
state protects property and that, without this role of the state, property, 
together with the wealth and economic power that accrues from it, 
could not be preserved. It was of course for this very reason that Marx 
concluded that we camiot make any fundamental change in institutions 
of property, or end the evil effects of the exercise of economic power 
by men of property, without the political power to make the change. 

It is not Marx but Dr. Popper himself who creates confusions by 
introducing the notion of “economic power” as a power separated 
from political power, and asking which is dependent on which. Marx 
never did so. He never wrote about “economic power” in this way. It is 
like asking which came first, the chicken or the egg. A dialectical 
approach to understanding human institutions in their real connections 
in processes of development saves Marxists from the puzzles resulting 
from such questions. Marx showed how from the formation of property 
and the ensuing conflicts of class interests there have resulted forms and 
operations of state power to protect property and to promote class 
interests. If a class is interested in furthering its economic power by 
either preserving or changing property relations, then it has to seek 
ways and means of doing so through the instrumentality of the state, 
that is, by controlling the operations of political power. And no political 
power has yet been known which did not serve, in one way or another, 
the furtherance of economic power. 

“Of course,” Dr. Popper continues, “in practice Marxists never 
fully relied on the doctrine of the impotence of political power. So far 
as they had an opportunity to act, or to plan action, they usually 
assumed, like everybody else, that political power can be used to 
control economic power. But their plans and action were never based 
on a clear refutation of their orginal theory, nor upon any well- 
considered view of that most fundamental problem of politics: the 
control of the controller, of the dangerous accumulation of power 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


273 


represented in the state. They never realised the full significance of 
democracy as the only known means to achieve this control” 
(2-OS. 129). 

Marxists never in fact needed any “clear refutation of their original 
theory”, because they never believed in any “doctrine of the impotence 
of political power”. And it is Dr. Popper himself who lacks “any well- 
considered view of that most fundamental problem of all politics : the 
control of the controller”. According to the way he sees it, “we” or 
“the public” must “control the controller”. We must do this by 
electing office-holders and controlling what they do. And the elected 
office-holders will then, on behalf of the electors, use their political 
power “to control economic power”. Marx (or so Dr. Popper says) 
could never grasp the significance of this democratic process because 
he believed that political power was impotent in face of economic 
power. Political power could not control economic power, but on the 
contrary, economic power controlled political power. The thing to do, 
therefore, was not to secure democratic control of political power, but 
to make a direct assault on economic power by a revolutionary 
uprising which would put paid to economic power by chasing away 
those who possessed it, locking them up, or hanging them on lamp- 
posts. Such a “doctrine” may well be considered hardly “well-con- 
sidered”. But Dr. Popper’s simple scheme of double control, where the 
public controls political power and political power controls economic 
power, is hardly well-considered either. 

What concerns us today in the matter of “economic power” is the 
power of capital. The economic power inseparable from ownership of 
capital is the power to accumulate surplus value from the exploitation 
of labour. In this process one capital swallows another, and an ever 
greater and more dangerous accumulation of economic power results 
in the hands of a few industrialists and financiers. To preserve and 
control it, there is the capitalist control of political power. For, as we 
discovered when we began to discuss democracy, what has actually 
happened is that the class which owns the means of production, and 
exercises the economic power which that ownership confers, has found 
its own ways and means to secure for itself effective “control of the 
controller”. One class is effectively in political control. And that is why 
that class continues to possess and control economic power. So “the 
fundamental problem of the control of the controller” is in fact the 
problem of which class is going to have political power. 

Marx therefore concluded, not that we must immediately attack 


274 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


economic power because so long as it exists political power is impotent, 
but that before any effective change can be made in economic manage- 
ment the “dangerous accumulation of power represented in the state” 
must be taken out of the control of the present possessors and benefici- 
aries of economic power, namely, the capitalist class. And so far was he 
from believing that “political power is impotent” in face of economic 
power, that his whole “doctrine” rested on the belief that a sufficient 
accumulation of political power in the hands of a revolutionary politi- 
cal movement could stop the nation’s economic resources being used 
for capitalist profit and use them instead for the people’s welfare. Such 
economic power as might still be left in the hands of private capital 
could then, he thought, be effectively controlled. 

4. SOCIALIST DEMOCRACY 

What is necessary, if it is proposed to do away with capitalism, is to 
break up the institutional ties of big business with the executive 
machinery of the state, and likewise with the organs of opinion for- 
mation. It is necessary to smash the whole organisation of control by 
big business, a control which is built into the entire machine. No elected 
administration, whatever its socialist aims, and no aspirants to political 
power, can end the domination of capital unless the organisation of 
this domination is smashed. That means that the strings of control must 
be cut, the channels of influence destroyed, the key personnel removed 
from their offices. The whole state organisation of administration and 
compulsion must be adapted, under a new command, to serve new 
purposes, dictated by working-class socialist organisations and not by 
big business. To accomplish this, however it is done, whether by 
armed workers storming government offices or by more constitu- 
tional means, is to establish “the dictatorship of the proletariat”. 

It is not only Dr. Popper who warns us that, whatever Marxist 
parties may say about their programmes and aims, whenever they are 
in the government they always try to turn it into a tyranny. Dr. 
Popper’s contribution is to demonstrate from first principles why this 
must always be so. It is because, following the alleged teachings of Marx, 
Communists insist on having “complete” and uncontrolled power, and 
to this end employ violence against democratic institutions so as to 
dismantle the controls of power and the “checks and balances” which 
such institutions impose. What Marxism teaches, however, is that we 
should dismantle the control of power by the capitalist class in order to 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


275 


build socialism, and to this end conduct a struggle for democratic 
rights and use them when we have got them. 

Organisation is needed both to smash the capitalist control of power 
and to control the exercise of power that replaces it. But in Dr. 
Popper’s account of democratic control it is never admitted that it is 
only organisation that can exert an effective control of power. Democratic 
control by unorganised individuals is a myth. They may express 
opinions and vote, but it is organisations that do the real controlling. 
And while individuals express individual opinions, it is through organi- 
sation that influential bodies of public opinion are formed. Without 
revolutionary labour organisations, then, majority public opinion will 
always be moulded by the great mass media whose propaganda serves 
the ruling class. People in the mass will only learn to turn a deaf ear to 
this propaganda when they have themselves in the mass entered upon 
an organised struggle. And without such organisation it is impossible 
to break and replace the highly organised control of the state machine 
by the ruling class. 

Dr. Popper says that militant mass organisation violates the prin- 
ciples of democracy and leads to dictatorship. On the contrary, it is 
the means to tear control of out the hands of a minority ruling class and 
exercise it on behalf of the majority. It means that working people have 
the democratic organisation to exert effective and continuous control over how 
affairs are run for them . 

In capitalist parliamentary democracy the mass of working people 
have the right to vote for members of parliament. But having done so, 
they exert practically no further control themselves until there is 
another general election — though of course they do have democratic 
rights to lobby their representatives and to protest against unpopular 
policies through mass meetings. It is this lack of organised popular 
control over the executive that allows, despite the democracy of 
parliamentary elections, effective continuous control over the executive 
by highly organised big business. Because it is this latter control that 
has to be abolished if we are to get socialism, the method of effective 
control which socialism demands is that of continuous control by mass 
democratic organisation. In socialist revolution the organisations which led 
the struggle against capital take over from the organisations of the exploiters 
both the offices of power and the control of power. It is from this that 
socialist democracy emerges as a system of government distinct from 
capitalist democracy. 

The central democratic achievement of the bourgeois revolution has 


PREMISES FOR POLITICS 


276 

been the institution of forms of representative government, in which 
the key institutions are parliaments or similar elected legislative 
assemblies. Such an assembly is distinct from the executive, from the 
“ bureaucratic and military organisation" of the state. But by making 
laws, by holding ministers and permanent officials answerable to it, by 
setting up committees and commissions, and prosecuting inquiries, it 
exerts powers of control over the executive. Of course, the individual 
electors do not exert such control directly: their representatives exert it. 

The fact that in the power structure of capitalist democracies the 
place of legislative assemblies is as instruments of control is clearly 
indicated in the history of the so-called “mother of parliaments" in 
Britain. The English Parliament began as a far from democratic 
institution by which the feudal barons sought to exercise a measure of 
control over the arbitrary power of the king. In the course of time the 
burgesses obtained entry into parliament, and its power increased 
especially by way of controlling the royal finances. Eventually it 
became the sole authority for making and unmaking laws, and assumed 
powers of control over every aspect of government without excep- 
tion. This is the “sovereignty" of parliament, and such is the position in 
Britain today. But at the same time as universal suffrage gave members 
of all classes the right to vote, and all classes the right to form their 
political organisations, the system of parliamentary control became, 
for the time being, a pretty effective system of control of government 
by big business. As we have seen, this took place as a result of the 
institutional links established between business interests and party 
machines, and of both with the entire “bureaucratic and military 
organisation" of the state. In the U.S.A. the constitutional relations 
between Congress and Senate, on the one hand, and the President, as 
chief executive, on the other show up even more clearly the controlling 
function of elected assemblies, just as political practice in the U.S.A. 
shows up even more clearly how big business controls government. 

The object of socialist revolution is not to destroy the democratic 
achievements of the preceding bourgeois revolution but, on the con- 
trary, to make use of them. Hence socialist revolution does not imply, 
as Dr. Popper seems to think, smashing up elected assemblies and 
parliaments and instituting a tyrannical rule not subject to any such 
form of control. Responsibility of the executive to a representative 
assembly, and its control by such an assembly, is necessary for the 
democratic government of a large modern community — for without it, 
as Dr. Popper absolutely correctly says, power could become uncon- 


THE BATTLE OF DEMOCRACY 


277 


trolled and the executive could do what it liked and trample on people’s 
rights. Hence the policy of socialists must always be — and this is what 
Marxism quite unambiguously advises — to make use of the controlling 
functions of representative assemblies where they already exist , and to carry 
out a fight to get them instituted where they do not exist. 

The point is not to get rid of representative assemblies and rule 
without them, but to turn them into effective instruments of popular 
democratic control. And that means defeating and putting out of business 
the old political party machines, and making the assemblies they 
dominated into institutions of control wherein the political represen- 
tatives of the organised majority of working people carry out the business of 
control in the interests of and under the instructions of the members of the 
organisations that sent them there. It is in this way that the organised masses 
can control government. They do it through the controlling power of a 
democratically elected assembly which their own organisations domi- 
nate — while at the same time their organisations can play a direct 
part in various functions of economic management, local government, 
the administration of the social services, control of the mass media, 
and so on. 

For Marxism, in all circumstances and all stages of “the battle of 
democracy”, democracy is not a matter of merely allowing individuals 
to vote while organisations of the exploiting classes take control of the execu- 
tive organs of power , but of the activity of popular democratic organisations 
and the control of power through them alone. 








PART THREE 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 














































I 


EQUALITY 


I. EQUALITY OF RIGHTS 

Like everyone who is in favour of democracy, Dr. Popper brackets it 
with equality and freedom. He speaks of “general elections and 
representative government” as “equalitarian methods of democratic 
control”, and of “the institutional control of power” as “progress 
towards equality”. According to his account of it, democratic institu- 
tions, with the provision of representation and a voice in the control 
of affairs to all persons of all classes, bring equality; equality is lost, 
just as freedom is lost, without democratic institutions; and democratic 
progress towards equality is at the same time enhancement of indi- 
vidual freedom. 

What is this “equality” which is somehow bound up with 
democracy, and towards which democracy progresses? 

It is evident enough that people are in fact unequal in respect of 
abilities, characters, bodily attributes, desires and needs; and that not 
only would it be impossible by any measures taken by democratic (or 
any other) institutions to remove such inequalities, but such removal 
would even be undesirable since, as Dr. Popper says (expressing 
agreement on this point with the philosopher Kant), “the variety 
and individuality of human characters and opinions” is “one of the 
main conditions of moral as well as material progress” (2-OS. 357). 

Equality is realised through the removal of inequalities. And the 
sort of inequalities we are concerned with in democratic progress 
towards equality are those inequalities which result from social 
institutions, as distinct from what may be called “natural” inequalities. 
Inequalities which result from social institutions may be removed, and 
equality instituted instead, by changing or reforming social institutions. 
So Dr. Popper very logically and properly concludes that, although 
there can be no question of removing the inequalities exemplified in 
the physical and mental make-up of human individuals, “this has no 
bearing upon the question whether or not we decide to treat men, 
especially in political issues, as equals, or as much like equals as possible ; 
that is to say, as possessing equal rights, and equal claims to equal 
treatment” (2-OS. 234). 


282 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


The inequalities which democracy removes are inequalities of rights , 
and the equality it brings is, Dr. Popper maintains, that of “equal 
rights” and “equality before the law”. “Equalitarianism proper,” he 
says, “is the demand that the citizens of the state should be treated 
impartially. It is the demand that birth, family, connection, or wealth 
must not influence those who administer the law to the citizens” 
(i-OS. 95). “Men are not equal,” he concludes; “but we can decide 
to fight for equal rights” (2-OS. 278). 

These explanations make it clear that democracy is indeed bound 
up with equality. For the democratic principle of establishing measures 
of institutional “control over the rulers by the ruled” implies that “the 
ruled” should possess equal rights of participation in this control: to 
the extent that that is not so, the instituted control is defective in 
respect to democracy. 

Understanding “equality” in this way, it is evident that “general 
elections and representative government” are indeed “equalitarian 
methods of democratic control”, and that universal suffrage is not 
merely “progress towards equality” but the establishment of a very 
important measure of equality. It means that everyone, irrespective 
of “birth, family, connection, or wealth”, and irrespective likewise of 
ability and personality (provided he is not a lunatic), has the equal 
right to vote, to make representations to his representative, and to 
seek nomination himself, and that no class is excluded from taking 
part in this democratic business of institutional control (as the slaves 
were, for example, in the imperfect and far from equalitarian 
democracy of ancient Athens). Similarly, the laws which the elected 
legislature enacts apply to everyone in the same way, so that everyone 
is entitled to the same legal protection for his person and property, and 
liable to the same penalties for breaking the law. 

Even when everyone has the right to vote, and a system of the 
impartial rule of law is well established, there is likely still to remain 
plenty of room for democratic reform, continuing the progress 
towards equality. For example, the electoral system can be made more 
democratic, and the equality of electors more equal, by rearrangement 
of constituencies, by devising systems of proportional representation, 
and so on. Loopholes in the law and in the administration of the law 
can be stopped up. Progress towards equality means removing 
inequalities, and we must always look out for the sorts of defects in 
organisation and administration which might make one vote count 
for more than another, or enable some people to evade theTaw or 


EQUALITY 


283 

to use it unfairly for their own gain and to the detriment of others. 
Dr. Popper therefore holds before us an invigorating prospect of 
continued democratic progress. 

But there still remains a question about equality of rights which 
Dr. Popper never asks, and this is the question pressed by Marxists. 
Even when everyone has the equal right to vote and join in political 
organisation, and when everyone is equally amenable to the laws (and 
Marxists have never doubted that these equalities are worth fighting 
for, and worth fighting to preserve), do there not remain other 
inequalities which it would be desirable to remove, quite apart from 
those individual inequalities which we all agree are characteristic of 
human nature and have “no bearing ,, on the political struggle for 
equality? 

Rights in general are not (as Dr. Popper would presumably agree, 
in view of his objections to “essentialism ,, ) inherent in men as men, 
by virtue of their common human essence. They correspond rather 
to definite social requirements of definite people situated in definite 
circumstances. Thus, for example, the right to own property in 
means of production and to hire labour is not an “inalienable human 
right” but a specific right applicable only in certain definite conditions 
of development of a commodity-producing economy. Such a right is 
unheard of in a primitive tribe, and is precluded by socialist relations 
of production. In general, when new relations of production supplant 
old, rights associated with old forms of property are lost. They are 
abolished, along with the old forms of property. Thus the rights of 
feudal lords, from “the right of the first night” to the right to levy 
private armies, were lost and, indeed, forcibly suppressed when 
capitalism was developed; and similarly, capitalists must lose their 
rights to own capital and exploit labour when socialism is introduced. 
Rights may be claimed to exact service from others and command 
their actions, or to live free from oppression and exploitation by 
others. Clearly, the first sort of claims are claims for unequal rights , 
and the second for equalisation of rights. And as clearly, these sorts of 
claims are contradictory. 

To discuss questions of equalisation of rights, as Dr. Popper proposes, 
it would be as well, therefore, to inquire into the source of removeable 
inequalities in social institutions. 

Marx undertook this enquiry, and reached very definite conclusions. 
There is a common source of inequalities, and they have all sprung 
from the institution of private property in means of production, class 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


284 

divisions, and the exploitation of man by man. Dr. Popper may have 
failed to take account of this because, although he begins by giving the 
word “institutions” a very wide reference, he most of the time confines 
his intention exclusively to institutions of management and govern- 
ment, and completely overlooks the institutional connections between 
these and such institutions as the institutions of property, class division 
and exploitation. 

No person of sense can object to one man’s possessing greater 
natural abilities than another, for this is due to no defect in social 
institutions but, on the contrary, with good institutions, encouraging 
the employment of all abilities for improving the human condition, 
we could all gain advantage from this sort of inequality. What we 
can reasonably object to is that one man should be provided with 
opportunities to develop his abilities denied to another, and still more 
than one man should be compelled to sell the use of his abilities for 
the profit of another. These are inequalities resulting from social 
institutions and the way they work, and could be removed by changing 
the institutions. Again, that people should receive unequal rewards 
for unequal contributions to social life may seem fair enough, but it 
represents a gross inequality in the distribution of the means of life 
when some receive a superfluity provided from the labour of others 
because they own property in means of production, while others 
receive much less because they can only work and own no such 
property. 

These inequalities are not removed simply by instituting general 
elections, representative government, equal political rights and 
equality before the law. But their source is the same as that of all 
inequalities of rights, namely, in the institution of property relations 
within which one class exploits another. 

If throughout the centuries until quite recently every political system 
was a system of unequal political rights, it was because exploiting 
classes preserved rights for themselves which they denied to others, 
as slaveowners denied rights to the slaves, or feudal lords denied rights 
to the serfs. Many political philosophers have tried to make out that 
political inequalities have natural causes. Aristotle, for example, tried 
to make out that the political institutions which denied political rights 
to slaves were a consequence of some people being natural slaves 
unfitted by nature to exercise the rights of free men. Similarly some 
theoreticians of racism today try to make out that the natural 
differences in the colour of men’s skins are differences which render 


EQUALITY 


285 

persons without pigmentation alone capable of exercising political 
rights. These sorts of natural disabilities on the part of whole classes 
and races do not in fact exist. What has happened is that the social 
institutions attached political rights to certain forms of property, and 
that is why rights were unequal. Similarly, certain forms of property 
carried with them their own law and exemptions from laws applicable 
to those without such property, so that men were not equal before 
the law. 

In democratic capitalist countries today the democratic process has 
at last removed most of these political inequalities. Such as remain are 
merely anomalies, hangovers from earlier times before democratic 
demands began to be won, but removeable without thereby altering 
the capitalist property relations — such as the double vote for business- 
men and members of universities, which was only a few years ago 
abolished in Britain; or such as the legal exemptions which peers still 
enjoy in Britain. Dr. Popper very rightly calls this “progress towards 
equality”. But the causes of inequalities in property relations and class 
relations remain. So long as the system of exploitation of man by man 
remains there remain gross inequalities between men, which are only 
glossed over, but not alleviated, by the existence of certain “equalities” 
of political rights and “equality before the law”. 

There are rights necessarily associated with property, so that the 
inequalities of private property entail inequalities of rights. When 
there is private property in means of production it confers upon the 
owner the right of appropriating the products, and therefore the 
right of appropriating the products of the labour of other people who 
work for him with those means of production. The capitalist class 
and the working class may all be “equal before the law” as citizens, 
and each individual may have a vote irrespective of his class, but they 
do not possess equal rights — for the one has the right to appropriate 
the products of labour, and the other has not. And this is inequality. 
It is impossible for there to be equality of rights as between exploiters 
and the exploited, whatever rights of voting, bargaining, striking, 
organising, protection of working conditions and provisions of 
services and holidays the exploited may have won. 

Dr. Popper and others may say that this sort of inequality does not 
matter, so long as wages, working conditions and social services are 
good. If that were true, we had best stop talking about institutional 
“progress towards equality”, since instituted inequality does not 
matter. But it does matter, because so long as it exists wages, conditions 


286 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


and social services are under threat, and can only be made good and 
kept good by a fight; and because this system of inequality has always 
been and still is inseparable from underemployment of resources, 
crises, poverty and wars. 

One may justly protest that the phrase “equality of rights”, as used 
by Dr. Popper as well as by many other people, is extremely vague 
and loose. Dr. Popper himself keeps on talking only of certain political 
and legal rights, and notably of the right by voting, and by political 
organisation, to elect, control and dismiss the “rulers”. These are 
rights which we in the democratic countries have won and value 
(though working-class organisations could still use them to consider- 
ably more effect, and though some democratic states still use all their 
power, including armed force, to prevent their being exercised in 
some other countries in which some of their citizens have invested 
their capital). But besides the right to vote and to organise, and 
“equality before the law”, there are other rights which people have 
sought to win through democratic institutions, namely, rights to 
education, health, social security, enjoyment of leisure, and free speech. 
How equal are these? 

In Britain, at all events, everyone not only nominally possesses but 
actually enjoys basic minimum rights of this kind. At the same time, 
there can be no doubt at all that the ownership of property, and the 
income accruing from it, confers the right to very substantial advan- 
tages in all these respects, quite irrespective of personal merit. The 
mere possession of enough money guarantees better opportunities for 
education, protection of health, security and enjoyment of leisure — 
while as to free speech, it is a well-known fact that wealth confers on 
its possessors very considerable privileges in the way of ownership 
and control of organs of propaganda and opinion-formation. Effec- 
tively, these rights are not equal, and cannot be so long as property 
relations remain unchanged. 

Dr. Popper has pointed out, and Marxists agree, because we knew 
it before, that there can be no question of removing all “natural” 
inequalities between persons in respect of characters, physical strength 
and abilities. But in this context it should also be said that even this 
is not true without qualification. What of the inequality between a 
well-nourished person and an under-nourished one, one who is 
crippled or suffers from congenital disease and a healthy man, the 
sound in mind and body and the sick? Much can be done to remove 
these inequalities. Even the inequality between clever and not so 


EQUALITY 


287 


clever people might be reduced by provision of equally good con- 
ditions of upbringing and education from conception onwards. Again, 
the disabilities which women naturally suffer as a result of the 
constitution of their bodies and of their bearing children can readily 
be compensated by providing special consideration, special services, 
special compensating advantages, for women. But effectively the right 
of those without money for assistance in these respects is not equal to 
that of those with command over money, social services or no social 
services. 

Money, the universal medium of exchange in commodity-producing 
society, is in one way a great equaliser — for everyone is equally entitled 
to receive money for whatever he has to sell, and to buy whatever he 
wishes with the money he has received. This entitlement has nothing 
to do with birth or rank, and applies to the beggar as much as to the 
millionaire, and to the peasant as much as to the lord. Former rigid 
divisions of rank broke down before the equalising power of money. 
At the same time commodity-production inevitably breeds inequalities, 
since when both means of production and labour-power are com- 
modities, some acquire means of production and appropriate the 
products, while others have only their labour-power to sell. These 
inequalities may then make no difference to either the right to vote 
or to “eqpality before the law”. They make a great deal of difference 
to other rights. In these there is still inequality. Everyone possesses 
certain basic and essential rights, but the institutions at the same time 
impose inequality, because they confer on the class that appropriates 
the products of the labour of the other the right to substantial 
advantages. 

Dr. Popper and others may justly praise such British institutions as 
universal free education, the national health service, and social security 
legislation, and point out what an advance they are over conditions 
that prevailed not long ago. Very good ! These institutions do indeed 
represent victories in the struggle for people’s rights. But only in a 
socialist Britain will we be able to cite them as examples of equality 
of rights. 


2. EQUALTY AND THE ABOLITION OF CLASSES 

But what of political equality itself? Is it true that the equal right to 
vote and to take part in political organisation amounts, within a 
capitalist organisation of society, to equal political rights in exercising 


288 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


control over the rulers? It is not true. As was already remarked in a 
previous chapter, the organisation for protecting and pushing the 
interests of the capitalist class exerts an overwhelming controlling 
influence over government, even though this control is that of a very 
small minority in terms of the numbers of electors. This control may 
be, and sometimes is, counteracted by the results of general elections; 
but it is reinforced and works through the operation of a whole com- 
plex of institutions, such as the party system and system of cabinet 
government, the entire system of backstage political intrigue, the 
entire layout of the so-called “corridors of power”, the organisation 
of the civil service, the judiciary, the police and the military, and, 
not least, the system of ownership and control of organs of mass 
information and propaganda, and the management of the educational 
system. All these institutions in their totality effectively institute 
inequality of control over government by the different classes, and 
make the capitalist class the ruling class. And, as Marxists have con- 
tinually insisted, this inequality cannot be removed simply by counting 
votes, but only by radical reforms in the entire working institutions 
of government, or in other words in the structure of the democratic 
state. 

Similar considerations apply to so-called “equality before the law”. 
Law is founded on rights, and exists to protect rights and ensure 
their exercise — so that if certain rights are to be abolished the corre- 
sponding law is changed or falls into disuse, if certain rights are to be 
established the law defining and protecting them is adopted, and unless 
there is a comprehensive and well-enforced system of law the “rights” 
people may exercise depend solely on their own strength in getting 
their way, and not on social institutions. So integral is this connection 
of law and rights that in some languages the same word does service 
for both. Unequal rights are therefore embodied in and protected by 
law, and when persons with unequal rights stand before the law they 
stand as unequals: they are “equal” only in the formal sense that each 
is equally amenable to the law which decrees their inequality. Dr. 
Popper lays it down that “birth, family, connection, or wealth must 
not influence those who administer the law to the citizens”. These 
are fine words, but how are judges to obey them when administering 
laws which concern precisely the rights of birth, family, connection 
and wealth? 

Of course, if someone commits a theft, or an assault or murder, 
or creates a public disturbance, his birth, family, connection or wealth 


EQUALITY 


289 

must not influence the magistrate or judge (at least, the law says it 
must not, although it often does, especially in cases of public disturbance 
and in minor cases of theft or assault). This is because the citizens’ 
rights of property and of personal security demand protection 
irrespective of the social status of offenders. And of course, through the 
development of class struggle in capitalist society, the law comes to 
protect not only the rights of capital but also rights of labour. This 
is because that protection can be afforded as an item of the protection 
of unequal rights based on capitalist property relations. The law 
protects the right of the owner of means of production to buy labour 
power and direct its employment, of the worker to sell labour power, 
and of each to organise to get the best terms he can in the bargain. 
That is the protection of unequal rights, and in affording it the law 
upholds the rights to services and respect, and to appropriate the 
products of labour, which accrue from birth, family, connection and 
wealth. 

There is no doubt that it is a great gain to have won and established 
in capitalist society a system of law within which all persons in 
authority have to act, which allows no exemptions, which allows not 
only the right of capital to make profits but of labour to organise, 
and which protects everyone’s personal property and personal security 
at least against assaults by individuals if not against the economic 
effects of the profit system. Marxists thoroughly agree with Dr. 
Popper that these are gains worth defending from persons misguided 
enough to wish to destroy them in favour of a lawless tyranny. He is 
mistaken in including us among such misguided persons. But we 
shall not boast that all this, good as it is, yet represents full “equality 
before the law”, so long as the law upholds the inequalities inseparable 
from capitalist property. Progress towards equality demands not only 
that the law shall apply universally and equally to everyone, but that 
laws which uphold inequalities shall give place to new laws which 
abolish inequalities. 

Progress towards equality has always been effected by the institu- 
tional removal of instituted inequalities. And the policies of revolu- 
tionary socialism which Marxists advocate are policies to continue this 
progress. If Dr. Popper denies it, it is because he supposes that “general 
elections and representative government” have done far more to 
remove inequalities than is actually the case — and he can suppose that 
only because he is blind to all inequalities except those which either 
deny rights to political representation, organisation and ownership of 


290 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


personal property to some classes or bestow on others exemptions 
from the law. Workers do vote, they are represented, they are allowed 
to organise, they have all legal rights to acquire and dispose of personal 
property, and no one is exempted from the law — but that does not 
bring equality between exploited and exploiters, nor make the classes 
equal either in the exercise of political control over government or in 
economic and cultural opportunities. There cannot be equality between 
exploiters and exploited, and exploiting and exploited classes cannot 
possibly be equal. 

For this reason Engels said that “equality must not be merely 
apparent, must not apply merely in the sphere of the state, but must 
also be real, must be extended to the social and economic sphere . . . 
the real content of the proletarian demand for equality is the demand 
for the abolition of classes” (. Anti-Duhring , Part i, Chapter io). 

Dr. Popper fears that to abolish classes would be so undemocratic 
a proceeding as to plunge us from the heights of democracy into the 
abyss of tyranny. But why should that be so? To abolish classes 
involves suppressing and abolishing all those institutional means by 
which the exploiting class maintains its control over government, 
establishing institutional means by which social production can be 
taken into social ownership and planned for social welfare, and 
instituting laws which prohibit the exploitation of man by man. 
Where is the departure from democracy? Such institutional changes 
could not possibly be effected without the support of at least the 
majority of the population, and there is nothing in them which 
requires the rule of any persons, or of any “strong man”, independent 
of popular democratic control through democratic institutions. The 
inequalities consequent on private property in means of production, 
including over-riding control of government by a small minority for 
its own profit, would be removed. But to remove these sorts of 
privileges for a minority at the expense of the majority, and even to 
take very firm steps to prevent the possibility of anyone ever being 
able to restore them, would not abolish democratic control of the 
rulers by the ruled but rather provide a basis for strengthening it. 

When Dr. Popper, like other supporters of the capitalist democratic 
establishment, speaks of “equality” and of “democracy” he speaks as 
though society consisted simply of an aggregation of individuals 
whose affairs are directed by certain persons holding government 
office and regulated by a set of laws. He says nothing about the 
property relations and consequent class relations which define the 


EQUALITY 


291 


economic structure of society, as an organisation of individuals based 
on the social production of the means of life. He is content to consider 
each individual, singly and individually, and to say that there is 
democracy and that each of them has equal rights when they each 
have the right to vote, to make representations to their representatives, 
to a fair trial if they commit an offence against other people and to 
legal protection if anyone else commits an offence against them. But 
just as it is deceptive to describe institutions in general as democratic 
without taking into account the class-controlled institutions which 
enable one class to exert an over-riding control of government in its 
own interest, so it is deceptive to describe rights in general as equal 
without taking into account the class relations which entail inequalities 
of rights. The institution of “equalitarian methods of democratic 
control” demands ending the unequalitarian control by an exploiting 
class, and “progress toward equality” demands ending the inequality 
of exploiting and exploited classes. Yet Dr. Popper and others not 
only ask us to accept inequality as equality, but warn us that to abolish 
it would be to destroy democracy. 


2 


FREEDOM 

I. FREEDOM AND RESTRICTION OF FREEDOM 

Passing in the discussion of democracy from the provision of equality 
to the provision of freedom, Dr. Popper reminds us of “the well- 
known paradox of freedom”, namely, that “the free man . . . may 
exercise his freedom, first by defying the law and ultimately by 
defying freedom itself and clamouring for a tyrant” (i-OS. 123). He 
concludes that “freedom defeats itself if it is unlimited . . . This is 
why we demand that the state should Emit freedom to a certain 
extent, so that everyone’s freedom is protected by law” (2-OS. 124). 
As for Marx, he “never grasped the paradox of freedom, and . . . 
never understood the function which state power could and should 
perform, in the service of freedom and humanity” (2-OS. 126). 

But Marxists would agree with Dr. Popper that “freedom defeats 
itself if it is unlimited”. For, as he goes on to say, if everyone is free 
to do whatever he likes “a strong man is free to bully one who is 
weak and to rob him of his freedom” (2-OS. 124). So if people 
together are to enjoy freedom, what they do must be limited by 
restrictions and rules. No man should be free to get hold of a club 
and beat other people over the head. Nor, Marx adds, should any 
man be free to acquire capital and exploit the labour of others. Marxists 
agree that there should be laws to stop strong men from bullying 
the weak, and they also conclude that there should be laws to stop 
exploiters from exploiting labour. To protect freedom, the law must 
take his club away from the bully, and also take his private capital 
away from the capitalist. Marx in fact grasped “the paradox of 
freedom” (“freedom defeats itself if it is unlimited”) with a rather 
more sure grasp than Dr. Popper. 

It is as obvious to Marxists as it is to Dr. Popper (indeed, one may 
think, rather more obvious) that the promotion of human freedom 
does not consist in establishing “unlimited freedom” for anyone to do 
anything, but consists in establishing the specific freedoms of specific 
people to do or not do specific things, and simultaneously in preventing 
anyone from hindering them. If freedoms are to be effectively provided 
that must be protected. Therefore the assertion of some freedoms 


FREEDOM 


293 


entails the denial of others, since protection entails prohibition. There 
is therefore no practical sense in talking about “freedom” unless one 
specifies freedom for whom to do what, and unless one is also prepared 
to accept prohibition of actions which would hinder these freedoms. 
In other words, freedom consists in the provision and protection of 
specific freedoms of individuals — in the provision of freedom of 
individuals to do or not do certain things, and in the prohibition of 
their doing things to hinder each other’s freedoms. 

Marxists are sometimes accused of proposing to deny freedom to 
individuals in order to dragoon them into courses of action which will 
somehow represent collective but not individual freedom. For instance, 
individuals will be conscripted to work, each as no more than a cog 
in the machine, so that social production of social needs can go freely 
forward. But just as collective action which is not the action of indivi- 
duals is an absurdity, so is collective freedom which is not the freedom 
of individuals — and it is a mockery of individuals too. A free society 
is nothing but an association of free individuals, for, as Engels remarked 
( Anti-Duhring , Part 3, Chapter 3), “it goes without saying that society 
cannot be free unless every individual is free”. Although Dr. Popper 
says that Marxism regards individuals as “pawns” and advocates the sub- 
ordination of the individual to the collective, he parenthetically admits 
that, nevertheless, “Marx was ultimately an individualist” (2-OS. 126). 
This does Marx no more than justice. Marxism is concerned to promote 
specific freedoms of individuals, which can only be won and protected 
by collective action and by the prohibition of whatever hinders them. 

The provision of freedom to individuals depends on their social 
institutions: so says Dr. Popper, and so also says Marx. 

Marxism advocates practical ways and means for establishing 
institutions which will ensure that social production will be carried 
on with the highest techniques and minimum expenditure of labour, 
so as to provide amply for material needs. With these, we need 
institutions for education and research, for the sciences and arts, for 
individual and group enjoyment of leisure, and institutions of manage- 
ment and administration. Such institutions can do the most to make 
people free — free from want, so that they can freely enjoy material 
necessities and comforts, which is the essential basis for every other 
freedom; free to amuse themselves in a variety of ways; free to take 
every advantage and benefit they can from the social development of 
technology, knowledge and culture, and to contribute to it personally 
in every way they are able. 


294 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


Marxism advocates establishing institutions to provide these free- 
doms, not for some people only, but for everyone. Free institutions 
provide freedoms equally for all citizens, and not just for a privileged 
few. Indeed, if institutions provided certain freedoms for some and 
denied them to others, it is evident that for the latter these would be 
institutions not to provide for their freedom but to deny it to them. It is 
very obvious, therefore, why demands for the maximum provision of 
freedoms should always be demands for equality. Marxism therefore 
links freedom with equality. 

The institutions through which human freedom may be secured (or, 
on the other hand, through which individuals are deprived of freedoms 
they might otherwise enjoy) include economic, sports, scientific, 
artistic, literary, educational and a host of other types of institution. 
But there can be no doubt, and Marxists certainly have never doubted, 
that the key institutions are those of government and law, the state 
institutions. The state can allow and assist the fullest development of 
institutions for freedom, or it can hinder or forbid it; and the govern- 
ment policies, the laws and the actions of the enforcers of the law can 
either uphold the conditions for individual freedom or can deny them. 
From this follows what Dr. Popper calls “the fimction which state 
power could or should perform, in the service of freedom and human- 
ity”, and which he says Marx never understood. 

So in this connection Dr. Popper asks “What do we demand from 
the state?” And he says that “the reply of the humanitarian will be ... I 
demand protection for my own freedom and for other people’s ... I am 
perfectly ready to see my own freedon of action somewhat curtailed 
by the state, provided I can obtain protection of that freedom which 
remains, since I know that some limitations of my freedom are neces- 
sary ... But I demand that the fundamental purpose of the state should 
not be lost sight of; I mean, the protection of that freedom which does 
not harm other citizens. Thus I demand that the state must limit the 
freedom of citizens as equally as possible, and not beyond what is 
necessary for achieving an equal limitation of freedom. Something 
like this”, Dr. Popper concludes, “will be the demand of the humani- 
tarian, of the equalitarian, of the individualist. It is a demand which 
permits the social technologist to approach political problems rationally, 
i.e. from the point of view of a fairly clear and definite aim” (i-OS. 
109-10). 

We too are humanitarians, equalitarians and individualists, we 
try to approach political problems rationally, and we make demands 


FREEDOM 


295 


upon the state for the furtherance and protection of freedom. Yet, for 
some reason or other, Dr. Popper thinks that his rational political 
question, “What do we demand from the state?” is posed as an alter- 
native to such rational sociological questions as “What is the state, 
what is its true nature, how did it originate?” He says that Marxism 
asks such “historicist” questions instead of asking “What do we demand 
from the state?” (i-OS. 190). But the fact that, as Marxism claims to 
demonstrate, the state originated out of the protection of class interests, 
and the capitalist state protects capitalist interests, does not preclude our 
asking ourselves “What do we demand from the state?” and concluding 
that one thing we demand is the protection of certain freedoms. To 
have asked and answered the other factual or so-called “historicist” 
questions does not prevent us asking “What do we demand from the 
state?”, but what it does do is to show us what we are up against in 
fighting to win our demand. 

Indeed, it is merely hot air to proclaim “We demand that the state 
should protect freedom”, unless we are prepared to make what Dr. 
Popper is pleased to call an “historicist” inquiry into the state in its actual 
developments up to the present day, to examine in what ways it falls 
short of protecting freedom, or hinders people from winning their 
freedom by protecting the freedom of others to exploit them, and to 
work out what can be done to get a state which will in the fullest 
sense protect freedom because it provides the necessary conditions 
for it. 

Dr. Popper further contends that if the state is to protect freedom, 
democratic institutions are necessary. Even without the benefit of Dr. 
Popper’s advice, this was Marx’s contention too. For those who want 
to ensure that their freedom is protected must see to it themselves, and 
not rely on protectors over whom they themselves have no control. If 
the masses of humanity are to live free from exploitation and free from 
want, they must see to it that those in charge of management and 
administration manage and administer accordingly — and that requires 
“equalitarian methods of democratic control”. To help demonstrate 
that this is so, Dr. Popper adds a good deal of useful argument to the 
effect that while uncontrolled power in the hands of exceptionally 
benevolent despots may occasionally be exerted to protect certain 
limited freedoms, the protection is at best extremely insecure except to 
the extent controls are instituted to ensure that it continues. 

But while Marxists agree with Dr. Popper that democratic insti- 
tutions are necessary to protect freedom, Dr. Popper does not agree 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


296 

with Marxism. For Marxism, he says, belittles the role of democracy 
even while claiming to be in favour of it — and from belittling democ- 
racy Marxism goes on in practice to try to overthrow it altogether. It 
calls the exercise of democratic rights “mere formal freedom”, and 
from this goes on to propose supplanting it with “real” freedom. But 
without this “mere formal freedom” whatever other freedom Marxism 
proposes cannot be freedom at all. 

“What Marxists describe disparagingly as ‘mere formal freedom*,” 
says Dr. Popper, is in fact “the basis of everything else. This ‘mere 
formal freedom*, i.e. democracy, the right of the people to judge and 
dismiss their government, is the only known device by which we can 
try to protect ourselves against the misuse of political power; it is the 
control of the rulers by the ruled. And since political power can control 
economic power, political democracy is also the only means for the 
control of economic power by the ruled. Without democratic con- 
trol, there can be no earthly reason why any government should not 
use its political and economic power for purposes very different from 
the protection of the freedom of its citizens** (2-OS. 127). 

But where and when did Marxists say that democratic control was 
not necessary for the protection of freedom? “It is the fimdamental 
role of ‘formal freedom* which is overlooked by Marxists**, Dr. Popper 
continues to fulminate, “who think that formal democracy is not 
enough and wish to supplement it by what they usually call ‘economic 
democracy’, a vague and utterly superficial phrase . . .**. But stop, Dr. 
Popper has been carried a bit too far by the exuberance of his verbosity. 
For it is not Marxists who usually talk vaguely and superficially about 
“economic democracy”, but Fabians and such-like “vague and utterly 
superficial” persons. 

By “economic democracy” is presumably meant measures of public 
control (or sometimes it means more narrowly “workers* control”) 
over the management of economic enterprises, just as by “political 
democracy” is meant measures of public control over government. So 
far as freedom is concerned, both are self-evidently in the same sense 
“forms” or “mere forms”. And^to call them “forms” is only to call 
them by their right name, not to “disparage” them. The freedom to 
vote, and to take part in instituted control, whether in general concerns 
of government or in particular items of economic management, 
appertains to the form of democratic control of institutions, which is 
necessary, as the form of control, in order that through the operation 
of those institutions people may enjoy the freedom associated with 


FREEDOM 297 

the exercise of their faculties and abilities, and the satisfaction of their 
needs. 

Dr. Popper himself continually talks about such freedoms as ‘ ‘free- 
dom from want” and “freedom from exploitation”, and says that these 
are the freedoms which democratic institutions should be designed to 
protect. In the context of freedom there is nothing “vague and super- 
ficial” in the use of such antithetical terms as “form” and “substance”, 
or “formal” and “real”; and it is a perfectly proper and precise use of 
language to say that formal freedoms, such as freedom to vote, 
appertain to the form of control of the working of institutions within 
which such real or substantial freedoms as “freedom from want” and 
“freedom from exploitation” may be realised. Marxism does not 
“disparage” mere “formal freedom”. But what it does say is that we 
must not let ourselves be tricked into accepting the form without the 
substance. 

It is perfectly true that “formal democracy is not enough”, whether 
it is “political democracy” alone or is supplemented by a measure of 
“economic democracy”. Marxism tells the workers that to have the 
right to vote and trade union rights is not enough; these rights must be 
protected ; but it is not enough to protect them, we should also use them ; 
we should also seek to win, and then to protect, all that substantial 
freedom which goes with “freedom from want” and “freedom from 
exploitation”. It is not Marxists who “overlook the fundamental role 
of ‘formal freedom* ” but Dr. Popper who overlooks it — for he over- 
looks that the role of “formal freedom* * is to enable us to establish and 
protect real freedom. 

Dr. Popper says that “the view of the state which I have sketched 
here may be called ‘protectionism***, and proceeds to explain that “the 
protectionist theory of the state** is not a theory about the origin of the 
state, nor about “the essential nature** of the state, “nor does it say 
anything about the way states actually function. It formulates a 
political demand , a proposal for the adoption of a certain policy** — and 
that demand and that proposal is that the state should protect freedom, 
and that everything it does to this end should be democratically 
controlled. It may perhaps be thought an odd use of words to call a 
demand or proposal “a theory*’, since for most people a theory is 
something on which demands and proposals may be based. However, 
Dr. Popper goes on to say that theories of the state must always “be 
translated, as it were, into the language of demands or proposals for 
political action before they can be seriously discussed. Otherwise, end- 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


298 

less discussions of a merely verbal character are unavoidable” (i-OS. 
m-12). 

We can certainly agree that theories of the state should be “translated 
into the language of demands or proposals for political action before 
they can be seriously discussed”, and that unless such a translation can 
be done theories are not worth serious discussion anyway. But if we 
are going to put forward the demand that the state should protect 
something, as a serious proposal for political action, we should at least 
have some idea as to whether the state is protecting it already, if so 
how effectively, or whether it is protecting something else. For political 
action has to start from an existing situation, and a proposal for it can 
hardly be serious unless it includes an estimate of the situation. The 
Marxist theory of the state can be and has been “translated into the 
language of political action”. What Dr. Popper deplores as its “ele- 
ments of historicism or essentialism” is that it not merely proposes 
political action but proposes it on the basis of an analysis of how things 
are and how they have come to be like it. Yet if political action aims 
at remedying an evil, it is as well to understand something of the evil 
it is proposed to remedy. 

So far as “protectionism” is concerned, Marxists agree that the 
state does fulfil a protective role, and we put forward political demands 
and proposals which concern its protective role. In that sense we are 
“protectionists” too, only we differ from Dr. Popper in that we think it 
necessary to examine “the way states actually function” in order to 
discuss seriously the way we propose to get them to function. 

According to the way Marxism interprets the historical evidence, 
states came into being as a result of the development of pfivate property 
and of classes, and have always fulfilled a primary function of protecting 
property and property relations. Exploiting classes have made them- 
selves ruling classes by means of the forms of institutional control they 
have exerted. This remains true of the ruling class in capitalist coun- 
tries today. As I have already pointed out more than once, the “equali- 
tarian methods of democratic control” which have been won in some 
capitalist countries are still strictly limited. The right to vote, the right 
to take part in political organisations, the trade union rights, and the 
rights of free speech and assembly, are limited and counteracted by the 
over-riding control which the capitalist class institutionally exerts over 
the organs of government, including not only the legislature and 
executive, but also the organs of information, education and propa- 
ganda. This control is exerted to protect capitalist property and the 


FREEDOM 


299 


freedom of capital to accumulate surplus-value and seek profitable 
investment. 

As a result, it is the same with the state today as it always has been: 
it protects property. There are various freedoms which individuals seek — 
freedoms to take part in the institutions of democratic control, and 
freedoms to dispose of their property and to develop their physical 
and mental capacities. The capitalist state actually allows and protects, 
and at the same time curtails and disallows these individual freedoms 
in so far as it accords with the preservation and development of the 
capitalist forms of property it protects. These are all facts, highly 
relevant to any “protectionist theory of the state”, which Dr. Popper 
overlooks. 


2. FREEDOM, RIGHTS AND SECURITY 

Recognising “that freedom must be limited”, Dr. Popper says that 
“it is certainly difficult to determine exactly the degree of freedom that 
can be left to the citizen without endangering that freedom whose 
protection is the task of the state. But,” he continues “that something 
like an approximate determination of that degree is possible is proved 
by experience, i.e. by the existence of democratic states” (i-OS. no). 
For this purpose he concludes that “the state should be considered as a 
society for the prevention of crime, i.e. of aggression”. For when the 
state is considered in that light, “the approximate degree of freedom 
that can be left to the citizens” is readily determined as a result of 
experience. To illustrate the practical principle on which such “approxi- 
mate determination” is made, he quotes “the famous story of the 
hooligan who protested that, being a free citizen, he could move his 
fist in any direction he liked; whereupon the judge wisely replied: 
‘The freedom of movement of your fists is limited by the position of 
your neighbour’s nose’” (i-OS. 111). 

No doubt. But even so it may be doubted whether the existence of 
democratic states has yet proved that they can always readily learn from 
experience how exactly to determine the limits of freedom. Experience 
has not yet taught the democratic American state that the freedom of 
its pilots to drop bombs should be limited by the position of its neigh- 
bour’s women and children. As “a society for the prevention of aggres- 
sion” this democratic state may be deemed a failure. Experience has 
not even taught some of the state legislatures that the right of their own 
children to education should not be limited by the colour of their skins. 

Furthermore, there is a difficulty in determining exactly what “that 


300 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


freedom” is “whose protection is the task of the state”. The American 
state, for example, considers that it must at all costs protect the freedom 
to invest capital — and that is why, far from considering itself guilty of 
aggression against some of its neighbours, it considers them guilty of 
aggression. Again, is the democratic state to protect the freedom of 
managements of private enterprises to declare workers redundant when 
they cannot make a profit out of them? If so, then this automatically 
curtails the freedom of workers to earn their living and contribute their 
working capacity to the social production of the means of life. For this 
right of private capital contradicts what in socialist countries is con- 
sidered a fundamental right, the right to work. 

Dr. Popper’s view about freedom and its limitations, and the role of 
the state, is summed up in his demand that the state should protect 
“that freedom which does not harm other citizens”. This is recognisably 
the same liberal view as was put forward by J. S. Mill On Liberty , when 
he said that the state should not interfere with the freedom of indi- 
viduals to conduct their affairs and dispose of their property as they 
please except in so far as experience showed was necessary to stop them 
from harming one another. But the fact is that the general concept of 
“harm” is by itself, in Dr. Popper’s phrase, far “too vague and utterly 
superficial” to serve as the key concept for deciding in what ways a 
democratic state should protect and should restrict freedom. 

A practical difficulty in the interpretation of Mill’s practical prin- 
ciple has always arisen over the decision of what sort of harm, and 
what degree or quantity of harm, should be done before the state is 
justified in interfering. People can and do harm one another in a 
variety of ways, so that if the liberal principle were taken literally it 
would suggest an intolerable amount of interference by the state in the 
private lives of citizens. This very point was touched on by W. S. 
Gilbert in The Mikado : in Gilbertian Japan flirting was made an indict- 
able offence, since it was judged to lead to harm being done to innocent 
maidens. As we have seen, Dr. Popper maintains that “experience” will 
always show democratic states where to draw the line ; and long before 
Dr. Popper began his elucidations, liberals, being commonsensical folk, 
were trying to draw some distinction between “public” and “private” 
life, with the proviso that the state should let the latter alone except in 
extreme cases. They likewise tried to draw some sort of balance 
between, on the one hand, the harm which could be done by permitting 
certain sorts of activity and, on the other hand, the harm done by 
interfering. For the liberal principle contains the implicit assumption 


FREEDOM 


301 


that state interference, being a restriction of liberty, is in itself harmful, 
and so should be practised only when a demonstrably greater harm 
would result from not interfering. Thus in a television discussion 
got up by the B.B.C. in the summer of 1966 the question was debated 
whether pornographic literature (prevalent in floods in England) 
ought to be banned — with one rather diffident and academic gentleman 
from Oxford arguing that it ought to be banned because of the harm it 
does, and all the other representatives of a free culture that it ought not 
to be banned because of the harm done by any form of censorship of 
publications. In political and economic debate, J. S. Mill's principle was 
used to argue the case for laissez faire ; but is is now generally agreed, 
and J. S. Mill himself was one of the first to argue the case, that a 
limited amount of state interference is desirable in economic affairs. 
But if socialists try to argue that any form of exploitation of man by 
man does harm, the counter-argument is that the state interference 
needed to stop it would do much more harm. 

The hidden reason why Dr. Popper and others think that neverthe- 
less experience in democratic states shows quite clearly what to allow 
and not to allow, in the light of their formula, is that they take it for 
granted that there should always be private ownership of means of 
production, buying and selling of labour power, and private appropria- 
tion of the products of socialised labour. On that assumption, experi- 
ence does indeed indicate the advisability of imposing certain restraints 
and not imposing others. But this is not at all the same thing as 
restraining people from harming one another. 

To determine the limits of freedom to be allowed by a democratic 
state is therefore not so easy nor so uncontroversial a task as Dr. 
Popper tries to make out. For what limits freedom is not simply the 
decision, wise or otherwise, of the legislature, which decides to allow or 
disallow individuals the freedom to do this or that. The laws must allow 
or disallow freedoms in accordance with the rights which go with 
different forms of property, so that what finally decides the limits of 
freedom is the institutions of property . The question is, shall the state 
legislate for the existing forms of property and continue to protect 
them, or shall it, on the contrary, legislate against them, promote the 
institution of other forms of property, and protect these other forms 
instead? This is the difficult question which has to be decided in order 
to determine the limits of freedom. And its decision invitably involves 
a struggle of classes for control of the state t and to preserve or change state 
institutions . 


302 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


Dr. Popper has correctly stressed the necessary connection between 
provision of freedom and limitation of freedom. And it is not difficult 
to see that this implies also, in practical discussion, a necessary connec- 
tion between the uses of the terms “freedom/’ “rights”, “law” and 
“security”. The freedoms to be provided correspond with rights — every- 
one is to be free to exercise and enjoy his rights; rights are embodied in 
law; and the enforcement of law brings security for the free exercise and 
enjoyment of rights. Thomas Hobbes was quite correct when he said 
that unless men’s actions were governed by social rules effectively en- 
forced, the lives of men would be “nasty, brutish and short”; it would 
not be a condition of freedom. As Dr. Popper’s wise judge recognised, 
a hooligan or thief is the enemy of men’s freedom, for he attacks their 
security. Similarly with military or economic aggression by states, in 
international affairs. And this, of course, is why Dr. Popper says that a 
democratic state should work “for the prevention of crime, i.e. of 
aggression”. Marxists entirely agree with that precept. But what Dr. 
Popper overlooks when defining “the function which state power could 
and should perform, in the service of freedom and humanity”, and 
the recognition of which made Marx understand this function rather 
better than Dr. Popper subsequently understood it, is that states always 
have to protect property rights and the security of property . It is therefore 
important to decide what sort of property rights are to be protected, 
and what sort of security is thereby to be provided. 

There are certain basic sorts of security which Marxism demands, 
voicing in these demands the immediate interest of the working class 
in modern society and at the same time stating the necessary condition 
for the unimpeded further development of social production. We 
demand for everyone the security of being able to find work to do, so 
as to contribute to social production and, as Marx put it in Capital 
(Vol 3, Chapter 48), “achieving this with the least expenditure of energy 
and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their human 
nature”. We demand for everyone the security of the use and enjoy- 
ment of personal property. And we demand for everyone security in 
conditions that will enable him to develop his capacities for life and 
happiness, both in his own person and in his personal relations with 
others. 

This, it may be said, is a rather tall order, human nature being what it 
is. Many argue that it is of no use demanding institutions which would 
provide such social security, because people as individuals are by 
nature far too bad or stupid ever to make them work. However, 


FREEDOM 


303 


Marxism opposes this kind of cynicism about human nature so long as 
there actually exist institutions which by their nature as institutions 
prevent such social security, whether individuals are by nature bad or 
stupid or not. And such are the institutions of capitalism. 

So long as the state protects capitalist property relations it must be 
concerned, whatever democratic demands are placed upon it, to 
provide as much security as it can for the accumulation and investment 
of capital, and for individuals, whether individually or through corpor- 
ate organisations, to enjoy freedom to accumulate and invest capital 
and to live on the surplus values accruing to them from the exploitation 
of the labour of others. 

This demonstrably goes counter to providing security of work. For 
employment depends on the vagaries of the crisis-ridden process of 
the circulation of capital; and so far as concerns working with “the 
least expenditure of energy and under conditions most worthy of their 
human nature”, the workers find progress in this respect impeded. 

Equally it goes counter to security of personal property. Although 
the state and the law protect personal property, one’s security of per- 
sonal property remains contingent on the insecurity of one’s job or 
one’s shares. The worker who has managed to acquire various per- 
sonal possessions, and even to buy a few shares, is in danger of losing 
the lot through inflation or unemployment. 

As for the more intangible goods of life and happiness and personal 
relations, it is a well-known fact, extensively demonstrated in socio- 
logical writings and explored in art and literature, that their sources are 
poisoned by the free-for-all competition and the monopolising of 
resources, the “I’m all right, Jack” and “dog eats dog” ethic, of capitalist 
society. 

By instituting social ownership of means of production we can 
institute social planning of production to employ available resources 
and labour to meet human needs. And the state which abolishes the 
rights of private capital and sets out to protect public property in 
means of production can then protect everyone’s right to benefit from 
social production and, by the social planning of production, can seek to 
establish and protect social security for everyone for work, personal 
property, and the pursuit of happiness. 

The freedom and equality which socialism can thus secure can be 
secured only be restricting and denying certain freedoms, as well as 
removing inequalities. Marxists have always said so, demonstrating 
therein a perfectly sound grasp of the so-called “paradox of freedom” 


304 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


and of ‘‘the function which state power could and should perform, in 
the service of freedom and humanity”. 

The sort of restriction of freedom which is exemplified by preven- 
ting fists from coming into contact with noses goes without saying — 
Dr. Popper himself agrees that that is “wise”. To secure freedom and 
equality based on social ownership of means of production demands 
also prohibiting private enterprises which make profits out of buying 
the use of labour-power and selling the products. It demands taking 
away the freedom of individuals, singly or in corporate organisation, 
to own such enterprises, or to buy and gamble with shares in them, or 
to display their initiative and competitive spirit by directing them. It 
demands taking away the freedom of one man to exploit another’s 
labour. It likewise demands the removal of all those institutional means, 
and the blocking up of all those corridors of power, through which a 
minority exploiting class can contrive to maintain its influence and 
control over government. All the rights claimed by representatives of 
that class to positions of influence and power are forfeited. And this 
forfeiture includes the rights to own and dictate the policies of news- 
papers and other means of propaganda, to control radio and television 
networks, to own and run publishing businesses and art galleries, to 
direct the organisation of science, and to exert censorship over what is 
taught in the schools. 

In such an undertaking of restricting freedom to secure freedom 
there is no doubt that, as Dr. Popper warns us, “many mistakes will 
be made”. And in fact many mistakes have been made already, and are 
still being made, by socialist states — hampered as they have been both 
by lack of democratic traditions and by an initially backward economy. 
But whatever mistakes have been made, or will be made in the future, 
they have at least got rid of property relations which block the road to 
security and freedom and established basic institutional forms of 
property and government within which the road ahead is open. And 
experience will show, and is showing, how to correct the mistakes. 

3. FREEDOM FROM EXPLOITATION 

When “freedom” is reckoned a social and political good, and preserv- 
ing and winning it set as a social and political aim, what do we mean 
by it? To explain what we mean it is necessary, not (as Dr. Popper has 
already explained in another context) to dig for and uncover the hidden 
“essence” of what the word stands for, but simply to state the impli- 


FREEDOM 


305 


cations of the uses of the word. If that is understood, then it is evident 
that when people say they want to be “free” they imply that they want 
either to cast off some constraint from which they are suffering or else 
to prevent some constraint from being imposed on them. Thus to be 
free implies to be free from constraint . 

Accordingly, Dr. Popper considers that the object of political action 
to promote freedom is to free people, so far as it can be done, from the 
constraints imposed upon them when they are ordered about and 
coerced by representatives of instituted power over which they have 
little or no control. So the political objective of freedom is realised 
by instituting democracy and self-government. 

There can be no doubt that this objective does correspond to most 
people’s actually expressed aspirations for freedom. For most people, to 
be “free” includes to enjoy democracy and self-government; and so 
long as they remain deprived of their own democratic institutions 
people do generally mean by winning “freedom” very little else than 
winning these institutions for themselves. As Dr. Popper has said, it is 
recognised that once democracy and self-government are won people 
may fail to make good use of them. But the first consideration in fighting 
for freedom is to win democracy and self-government . 

As against this it is sometimes argued that, according to Marxism, it 
is a mere “bourgeois” or “liberal” illusion to suppose that “freedom” 
implies freedom from constraint. But the concept of freedom, as 
understood by everyone who aspires to freedom and refrains from 
using the word in tricky senses designed to cheat people by foisting on 
them something they do not want by denoting it by the word they 
customarily use for something they do want, does bear the implica- 
tion that to gain freedom is always to throw off some constraint imposed 
on us. And if Marxism disagrees with “bourgeois liberalism” ’it is not 
because we advocate imposing all sorts of constraints on people which 
liberalism urges them to throw off, but because we advocate getting 
rid of constraints which liberalism is quite content to accept. 

Dr. Popper’s idea that “we demand that the state protects that free- 
dom which does not harm other citizens” leads him, like other liberals, 
frequently to argue as though the constraints placed on freedom were 
only political, that is, only impositions by the state. You have your 
freedom curtailed when the police come after you — and Dr. Popper 
insists that that should be done only to stop you harming anyone else. 
Apart from what the state, or officers of the state, may do to curtail our 
freedom, we are free. 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


306 

But quite apart from such constraints on freedom as may be imposed 
by the state and the police, is not our freedom to do as we please, and to 
enjoy and cultivate the advantages which individuals can gain from the 
amenities of civilisation, very severely constrained by long hours of 
work, arduous, dull and unrewarding jobs, lack of good food and living 
conditions — and even more constrained when the individual cannot 
find work? Is it not limited, too, by lack of education, and by people 
being subjected to a multitude of propaganda influences which 
stultify therr minds, condition them to believe what they are told, and 
lead them to believe they are living well when in fact they are only 
grabbing what they can get in a competitive scramble with their 
fellows? All these limitations exist. But because they, or even worse 
ones, have always existed they are taken for granted, as natural features 
of the human condition. So long as techniques were comparatively 
primitive such conditions were unavoidable, and to do away with them 
was not within the range of practical politics. But it is within the range 
now — and Marxism is the working out of the theory and practice of 
of such politics. 

For that matter, it is equally true that institutions of democratic 
control, in which the whole population to some extent participates, 
and not merely those privileged by owning property, were not within 
the range of practical politics in earlier times. Such institutions of 
freedom have fairly recently begun to be established. Liberals, enthusi- 
astic as they rightly are about the gains of freedom made by democracy, 
and prepared, as they say, to fight to the death to preserve even such 
limited items of democracy as we have so far got (and Marxists join 
them in this), make the mistake of thinking that because controlling 
the power of rulers to dictate to citizens is a necessary condition for 
the citizens’ freedom it is the whole of their freedom. It is nothing of the 
sort. For even when we have gained a measure of control over how 
far we may be dictated to by the decrees of rulers, that is to say, have 
gained political freedom, we may still be relatively unfree, and under 
heavy constraint, on account of our production relations and of the 
whole way in which we organise social production and the distribution 
of the means of life and enjoyment of life. Liberals accept this constraint 
and this unfreedom. Marxists seek the ways of ending it. 

Marx and Engels were of opinion that, as a result of socialist owner- 
ship and management of social means of production, and the restric- 
tions which that would imply on the freedom of individuals to own 
means of production and buy and sell labour-power and its products, 


FREEDOM 


307 


an organisation of social production could be achieved on the basis of 
which all individuals could enjoy a freedom they cannot enjoy in any 
society based on the exploitation of labour. And in Anti-Duhring (Part 
3, Chapter 3) Engels proceeded to spell out the conditions for such 
individual freedom, and in what it consists. 

The main thing, he explained, is that “in making itself the master of 
all the means of production, in order to use them in accordance with a 
social plan, society puts an end to the former subjection of men to their 
own means of production”. Thus “productive labour” is no longer “a 
means to the subjection of men”. 

In order that the human race should exist at all, and that anyone 
should be able to live, let alone live freely, productive labour has got 
to be done. The ways in which it has become “a means to the subjec- 
tion of men” are all, so Engels gives us to understand, consequences of 
the social division of labour. First, individuals have become tied to 
particular jobs in such a way that all opportunities for development of 
abilities and personality, and for enjoyment of goods, have been con- 
ditioned and restricted by the job to which each individual is tied: thus 
the peasant is tied to the land, the worker to the bench, and the mana- 
ging director to the board room, all being equally in a state of “sub- 
jection to their own means of production”. Second, some individuals 
live by exploiting the labour of others, so that the latter are tied down 
by having to work for the benefit and under the direction of the former. 
Third, individuals are compelled to devote the greater part of their 
energies to socially necessary labour, with little time or energy left to 
devote to avocations freely chosen by themselves. 

Engels argued that “the present development of productive forces is 
already adequate” for us to do away with all this subjection. Starting 
with the third item, he pointed out that the social development of 
modern productive forces can now “reduce the time required for 
labour, with every individual taking his share, to what on our present 
conceptions would be a small amount”. So everyone can be given 
plenty of time and opportunity to live a good life as he chooses. 
Second, all exploitation of man by man can be abolished. And third, 
it is possible with modern productive forces to do away altogether with 
the former crippling effects on individuals of the division of labour. 
“Modem industry, indeed, compels society,” Marx had written in 
Capital (Vol 1, Chapter 14, section 9), “under penalty of death, to 
replace the detail worker of today, crippled by life-long repetition of 
one and the same operation and thus reduced to the mere fragment of a 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


308 

man, by the fully developed individual, fit for a variety of labours, 
ready to face any change of production, and to whom the different 
social functions he performs are but so many modes of giving free 
scope to his own natural and acquired powers/’ In particular, the 
development of techniques and of people’s mastery of them can end the 
two greatest divisions which impose restrictions and inequalities upon 
individuals — the divisions between mental and manual labour, and 
between town and countryside. 

So, said Engels, the individual freedom which people can get as a 
result of socialist ownership of means of production is the correlative 
of the removal of these forms of subjection. What it amounts to, he 
said, is “giving each individual the opportunity to develop and exercise 
all his faculties, physical and mental, in all directions”. 

Marx explained the same point, but perhaps with greater eloquence 
and less attention to detail, at the end of the third volume of Capital 
(Chapter 48). 

“The realm of freedom actually begins,” he wrote, “only where 
labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations 
ceases; thus in the very nature of things it lies beyond the sphere 
of actual material production. Just as the savage must wrestle with 
nature to satisfy his wants, to maintain and reproduce life, so must 
civilised man, and he must do so in all social formations and under all 
possible modes of production. With his development this realm of 
physical necessity expands as a result of his wants ; but, at the same 
time, the forces of production which satisfy these wants also increase. 
Freedom in this field can only consist in socialised man, the associated 
producers, rationally regulating their interchange with nature, bringing 
it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the 
blind forces of nature ; and achieving this with the least expenditure of 
energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their 
human nature. But it nonetheless remains a realm of necessity. Beyond 
it begins that development of human energy which is an end in itself, 
the true realm of freedom, which, however, can blossom forth only 
with this realm of necessity as its basis. The shortening of the working- 
day is its basic prerequisite.” 

Thus Marx and Engels both made very clear that what they regarded 
as freedom — a goal worth striving for, and which could be realised 
only on the basis of social ownership of means of production — con- 
sisted in each individual enjoying equally the possibility “to develop 
and exercise all his faculties”, and to engage in “that development of 


FREEDOM 


309 


human energy which is an end in itself” and which is done, not because 
one has to, but because one chooses to. The necessary condition for this, 
they explained, was something which could only be realised by social 
action — the fullest development of social production on the basis of 
social ownership of means of production and planning, overcoming 
the crippling effects of division of labour, abolishing all exploitation of 
man by man, and reducing to the minimum the hours of necessary- 
labour for each individual and the individual energy expended in 
them. 

As Marx suggested in his Critique of the Gotha Programme , individuals 
would then hardly begrudge the time spent in social labour, under 
orders within a social production plan, for they could recognise that 
work is “the prime necessity of life”. Moreover, as Engels pointed out, 
with the fullest use and development of techniques “labour will become 
a pleasure instead of a burden”. 

It is for these reasons that Marxists maintain that it is only by the 
institution of socialism that men can make a real beginning to the 
achievement of a free society. For as Engels said, it is only after “the 
seizure of the means of production by society” that “in a sense man 
finally cuts himself off from the animal world, leaves the conditions of 
animal existence behind him and enters conditions which are really 
human. The conditions of existence forming man’s environment, 
which up to now have dominated man, at this point pass under the 
dominion and control of man, who now for the first time becomes the 
real conscious master of nature, because and in so far as he has become 
master of his own social organisation. ... It is only from this point that 
men, with full consciousness, will fashion their own history; it is only 
froih this point that the social causes set in motion by men will have, 
predominantly and in constantly increasing measure, the effects willed 
by men. It is humanity’s leap from the realm of necessity into the realm 
of freedom” (. Anti-Duhring , Part 3, Chapter 2). 

To achieve such freedom as this, not only must more effective forms of 
democratic control of rulers be introduced but social relations must be changed . 
Denying this, the liberals not only justify political constraints associated 
with the existing capitalist relations as necessary to prevent harm, but 
also accept the powers and privileges of the existing ruling class, and 
the subjection of the majority of people to the cramping conditions of 
exploited labour, as normal features of the working of a democratic 
political system. So far as freedom is concerned, their horizons are 
extremely limited. 


3io 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


It is, indeed, always important to remember that what is called 
“liberalism” is in fact often far from liberal. Liberalism in social and 
political theory is often as hidebound and stuffy as the great Liberal 
Party itself. 

Liberal myosis as regards the bounds of freedom is due to their 
accepting capitalist relations as those within which human freedom 
must be confined. Dr. Popper talks, indeed, of “freedom from ex- 
ploitation”. But, for him, it is only unorganised workers, who lack 
bargaining power against unscrupulous employers, who get themselves 
exploited; when there is organisation, and wages and hours are settled 
by collective bargaining (or, perhaps we should now say, by the in- 
comes policy decided on by a democratically elected government), 
there is already an end to exploitation. On such a view, freedom does 
indeed seem to be in the main a matter only of political and economic 
democracy. The essential freedoms are seen as freedom of individual 
enterprise, freedom for individuals with a common interest to organise 
for the promotion of their interest and to bargain with other interests, 
freedom both by individual initiative and by collective organisation to 
better one's condition. But yet within the capitalist relations the utmost 
betterment that can be hoped for is only a little easing of the constraints 
of economic necessity and the demands of one’s job. And in these 
conditions people naturally see as objectives of all their efforts only the 
grabbing for themselves of such satisfactions as they can get amid the 
free-for-all, and grab and consume these the more greedily because 
their possession of them is constantly being thwarted and threatened 
by the economic crises, and crises in political and international relations, 
which capitalism engenders and the onset of which no-one can control. 
Such, for liberalism, is the inescapable human lot. 

Marx, as Dr. Popper admits, saw all these evils of capitalism 
clearly enough — but he saw beyond them, towards how to overcome 
them. He did not disparage the political freedoms associated with 
democracy. On the contrary, he advocated enlarging them be re- 
moving the political and economic controls of the ruling class. But he 
saw clearly that political power must be used to change social relations in 
order to set men free — that is to say, to make men individually free on the 
basis of their co-operation in social techniques to produce the means for 
satisfaction, and collectively secure by their control over their means of 
livelihood and their own social organisation. 

The account rendered by Marx of freedom, and of the constraints 
which must be removed to win it, is of profound importance because it 


FREEDOM 


311 

sets before us an aim of political action. Dr. Popper is very scornful 
about aims and ideals because, he says, the object of political action 
should not be to realise ideals but to remove evils. However, Marxists 
fight harder than most to remove evils because that is the practical 
way of fighting to realise ideals. One’s idea of what is an evil to be 
removed can never be dissociated from one’s idea of what good is to be 
got by removing it. For if one lacks the conception of what good is to 
be got by removing evils one may well think it not worth the trouble 
of removing them, or even fail to see them as evils at all. By demon- 
strating something of the full potential scope of human freedom Marx- 
ism urges us to go on removing what blocks our freedom. And while 
it urges that we value and defend the freedoms already won, it does not 
teach us that in winning them we have won all the freedom we want 
or could get. 

In capitalist conditions, therefore, Marxism urges that we should 
organise to protect the democratic freedoms already won, or to win 
them if they are still lacking ; that we should organise to defend our 
standards of life and to improve them ; and that we should organise to 
deprive the ruling class of its powers to protect its own privileges at 
the expense of the freedoms of the majority, and, having done so, 
institute socialist relations of production. And when socialism is won, 
Marxism urges that we should go on working for the conditions of 
individual freedom , defined not simply in terms of democratic rights, 
though those must be established where they are lacking, but defined 
also in terms of conditions of work “worthy of human nature”, and 
of the production of plenty “with the least expenditure of energy”, so 
that “that development of human energy which is an end in itself. . . 
can blossom forth”. 

It is a very well-known fact today that under socialist governments, 
in the first fifty years since the first was established, people have lacked 
many conditions of freedom, even some which they have got in 
capitalist countries, not only because of unavoidable economic and 
political difficulties, but because of misconceived policies of socialist 
governments. But whether all who hold office in socialist countries are 
as yet aware of it or not, Marxism presents to the whole great move- 
ment of peoples in revolt against exploitation their goal of freedom, 
their conception of freedom in terms of which they can continue to 
judge what has still to be done to establish free institutions. 


4 


312 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


4. FREEDOM AND NECESSITY 

Dr. Popper quotes some parts of the observations by Marx and 
Engels about individual freedom and a free society quoted in the last 
section. And he then comments that “as far as I am able to see” Marx 
“followed Hegel’s famous equation of freedom with spirit, in so far as 
he believed that we can be free only as spiritual beings” (2-OS. 103). 

This seems a surprising interpretation of Marx’s view, even for 
Wonderland. But, continues Dr. Popper, Marx described all that 
pertains to material life, material conditions, and the production of the 
material means of life, as “a realm of necessity”, and said that “true 
freedom” only begins “beyond it”. So Marx evidently supposed that 
true freedom can come only in so far as we “emancipate ourselves 
entirely from the necessities of our metabolism”, For Marx, in fact, 
just as for “any Christian dualist”, freedom consists in “the emancipa- 
tion from the flesh”. And Engels expressed the same concept when he 
wrote that, to win freedom, man must “cut himself off from the animal 
world”. 

Of course, Dr. Popper adds, Marx and Engels knew well enough that 
we could never achieve one hundred per cent “emancipation from the 
flesh”. So what they advocated was simply that we should spend as 
little time and energy as possible on fleshly concerns, so as to leave all 
the rest for “true freedom” (2-OS. 103-5). He supposes that Marx 
regarded human metabolism, our material existence, “the flesh”, as 
unavoidable limitations on our freedom from which we should try to 
emancipate ourselves. Alas, we can never emancipate ourselves entirely, 
and so we are always forced to devote a certain amount of attention 
to material necessities. 

The view which Dr. Popper tries to foist onto Marx that “we can be 
free only as spiritual beings”, can justifiably be regarded, as Dr. Popper 
regards it, as not merely nonsense but pernicious nonsense. He tends to 
call any such nonsense “Hegelian”, regardless of whether Hegel 
actually propounded it or not. But this view is in fact considerably 
older than Hegel, since it is to be found rather forcibly expressed in 
writings attributed to Saint Paul. The pernicious practical implication 
hidden behind its high-sounding spiritualistic phraseology is that 
because the body limits and fetters the freedom of the spirit it is as well 
to chasten the body in order to free the spirit. Thus the view that “true 
freedom” is “spiritual” can be (and often has been) used to justify all 
kinds of oppression and cruelty in the name of “true freedom”. 


FREEDOM 


313 


Dr. Popper has already warned us that the practical outcome of the 
Marxist advocacy of revolution as the means for securing freedom from 
exploitation can only be tyranny. But now he has shown how Marx 
and Engels tried to cover up this unpleasant fact with a load of non- 
sense about ‘‘true freedom”. 

The idea that only “spirit” is free, whereas “the flesh” is unfree, 
which Dr. Popper rather arbitrarily ascribes to Hegel and still more 
arbitrarily to Marx, has become associated in modem times with certain 
philosophical arguments about freedom and causality. 

Put in its simplest terms, the argument that “we can be free only as 
spiritual beings” goes like this. Material events have causes and take 
place in accordance with causal laws. In so far as we are material 
organisms, therefore, we are subject to causal laws, so that if the cause 
of an action is present the action necessarily follows as the effect, and if 
the cause is not present the action does not follow. If the cause is 
present there is therefore nothing we, as mere material organisms 
existing in a material environment, can do to stop the effect from 
following; and if the cause is not present, there is nothing we can do to 
bring the effect about. In either case we have no choice, no freedom in 
the matter. Hence if we are in any way free in what we do, it can only be 
as spiritual beings, because there is some spiritual principle in us which 
acts independently of the chain of causation in material processes. 

The answer to this argument is pretty obvious, to such an extent that 
it has today become even a commonplace in philosophy. So far from 
causality and causal law precluding our being able to choose to do 
something and then to do it, it is the necessary condition for such free 
action on our part. It is only because causes produce effects, and in so 
far as we know what effects given causes will produce, that we can 
decide on a course of action and carry it out. For if we could never 
know what causes produced what effects, how could we possibly 
deliberate on any course of action, or embark on any undertaking 
whatever? Men are material organisms and, as such, our activities and 
the effects of our activities are subject to causal laws. But that does not 
imply that we can only be free in our choice of activities if there 
exists some part of us which is free from the chain of material causality 
On the contrary, when we know what causes will produce what 
effects, that is the cause of our freely producing such effects as we choose. 

Professor Ryle, of Oxford, has illustrated this line of argument by 
examples from the free play of games. He pointed out (in The Concept 
of Mind) that the fact that both billiard balls and billiard players are 


3 H 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


subject to the laws of mechanics does not prohibit the free play of 
billiards but is its necessary condition. “The billiard player asks for no 
special indulgence from the laws of physics any more than he does 
from the rules of billiards. Why should he? They do not force his hand.” 
That players exercise freedom in pushing billiard balls where they 
want them to go does not imply that the players are “spiritual beings”, 
nor that to play billiards well “we must emancipate ourselves from the 
necessities of our metabolism”. With that admirable facility for stating 
the obvious which is characteristic of the school of philosophy to 
which he belongs, Professor Ryle further pointed out how baseless is 
the assumption that “a golfer cannot at once conform to the laws of 
ballistics and obey the rules of golf and play with elegance and skill”. 

It is the same in more serious affairs as in these examples of games. In 
so far as an effect follows from our own deliberate action, rather than 
from external causes independent of our deliberations, we may be said 
to be responsible for it — it was our own choice of action that brought 
it about. And in so far as we have learned from experience what to do 
in order to bring about one effect rather than another, we have made 
ourselves free to act upon and realise our own purposes, and so “eman- 
cipated ourselves” from conditions in which what happens to us, and 
what happens as the effect of causes we have set in motion, depends not 
on ourselves but on external forces beyond our control. 

Understanding all this, Marx and Engels did not regard material 
existence and its necessities as limitations on what, without them, 
would be our freedom as “spiritual beings”. Obviously, since man is a 
material and not a spiritual being, his freedom is that of a material 
and not of a spiritual being. His material existence is not a limitation on 
his freedom, but its condition. For example, breathing and having air 
to breathe is not a limitation on our freedom, but is is a condition for 
its exercise. According to Marx and Engels, therefore, man makes 
himself free by his control and use of material conditions for his own 
purposes, to satisfy his own needs. The achievement of freedom depends 
on understanding and mastering the necessities of material existence. 

A word in time here about this use of the word “necessity” may 
save some misunderstanding. It is, of course, a word which may be used in 
several different senses in different contexts. Neither Marx nor Engels 
ever went to the trouble of splitting hairs in the distinction between 
these different senses — an omission for which they may perhaps be 
reproached by contemporary philosophers, and which affords ample 
scope for much lively nonsense at mad tea parties. The sense given to 


FREEDOM 


315 


the word “necessity” is quite clearly the sense of “necessary condition” 
or “necessary conditions”. Thus if we say that eating is a necessity of 
life, that does not mean that we necessarily eat, but that unless we eat 
we do not stay alive. Again, if we say that to construct aircraft we must 
understand and master the natural necessities expressed in the laws of 
aerodynamics, that does not mean that those laws are “necessities” in 
any more abstruse sense than simply that they express the conditions 
for controlled flight of bodies through the air. 

So when Engels said that “man leaves the conditions of animal 
existence behind him” he did not mean that man achieves “the emanci- 
pation from the flesh” by freeing himself from the necessities of his 
material existence, but he meant exactly what he said, namely, that 
“the conditions of existence forming man’s environment, which up to 
now have dominated man, pass under the dominion and control of 
man”. Leaving “the conditions of animal existence” behind us is not a 
matter of our spiritual being overcoming our material being and 
escaping from its limitations, but of our learning, as animals which live 
by satisfying their needs and creating new needs for themselves by 
social production, how to develop our social and personal relations and 
activities so as to satisfy our needs. 

As Marx explained, when men learn rationally to regulate the 
“interchange with nature” which is necessary to support human 
existence they thereby make themselves free to engage in many 
pursuits which they undertake, not because they are forced to do so 
in order to support life, but because their success in producing material 
necessities leaves them free to devote energies to other pursuits of their 
own choosing. So when Marx said that “the shortening of the working 
day” is a condition for “true freedom” he meant simply that it would 
allow more time in which to do things, not because we have to do them 
whether we like it or not, but because we like doing them and choose 
to do them. This is a pointnvhich most industrial workers can readily 
grasp, even if it is beyond the compass of Dr. Popper’s understanding. 

Dr. Popper’s statement that Marx “followed Hegel’s famous 
equation of freedom with spirit”, and believed that we are truly free 
only in so far as we somehow cut ourselves off from the necessities of 
material existence and emancipate ourselves from them, is the more 
surprising because in Anti-Duhring (Part 1, Chapter n) Engels had 
already succinctly and explicitly explained that exactly the opposite is 
true. Dr. Popper perhaps failed to notice the significance of what 
Engels had to say in Anti-Duhring because he dismisses that work as 


31 6 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


mere “apologetics”, and also because, believing correctly that in 
certain respects Marx and Engels “followed Hegel”, his own lack of 
understanding of Hegel precludes him from all possibility of under- 
standing what following Hegel meant. 

“Hegel was the first to state correctly the relation between freedom 
and necessity. To him, freedom is the appreciation of necessity,” 
Engels wrote. He then continued: “Freedom v does not consist in an 
imaginary independence of natural laws, but in the knowledge of these 
laws, and in the possibility this gives of systematically making them 
work towards definite aims .... Freedom therefore consists in the 
control over ourselves and over external nature which is founded on 
knowledge of natural necessity.” 

In talking about freedom Dr. Popper follows the well-worn liberal 
tradition of dealing exclusively with political questions about how far 
the state should prevent anyone doing just as he pleases, and demanding 
that people should be forbidden to do some things only to protect 
their freedom to do others. As a result, and as I have already noted, he 
fails to take into account the very fundamental fact of human life 
that, quite apart from any notices the state posts up about what is 
permitted or prohibited, people’s freedom is restricted by their relation- 
ship to their own means of production, so that each enjoys only that 
unequal area of freedom which is allowed him by his ownership of 
property and position within the social division of labour. Now it may 
further be noted that in talking about freedom Dr. Popper fails to 
take into account an even more fundamental consideration, namely, 
that before anyone is free to do anything, the means must be available 
to enable it to be done, and also the knowledge of how to do it. 

To make ourselves free to carry out activities we must get control 
over the necessary means for activities. People must have done this 
collectively before individuals can be free to engage in those activities. 

This consideration underlines and explains the fact that men can be 
said to seek and to exercise a freedom in their activities of a kind not 
attainable by other animals. This fact is misunderstood by Dr. Popper 
when he assumes that the creation and extension of human freedom is 
entirely a matter of politics, an activity in which other animals do not 
engage, quite as much as it is misunderstood by those who say our 
freedom is “spiritual”, whereas other animals are not “spiritual beings”. 
Men are animals. But the species Homo sapiens , with upright stance and 
human hands and brain, distinguished itself from all others by the 
method of social production of the means of life. To do this men 


FREEDOM 


317 


learned how to make tools and construct the means to bring about 
various effects, and to represent to themselves (a first indispensable 
means to this was the institution of language) effects which they wished 
to produce and the actions necessary to bring them about. Thus they 
developed the ways of purposive action in which human freedom 
resides, whether in the production process itself, the management of 
public affairs, or the pursuit of personal desires and aims. This consists 
in making means available and knowing how they can be used to 
produce various effects, so that one can choose whether to produce 
those effects or not. 

In the passage in Anti-Duhring quoted above, Engels said that human 
freedom is people's own creation, and we create it by learning to 
master and control material causes so as to set them to work for our own 
purposes. To the extent that we learn how to use objects for our own 
purposes our freedom of action is expanded. There is more we can do. 
And this expanded freedom depends on our having acquired, as 
Engels put it, “the capacity to make decisions with real knowledge of 
the subject" — so that instead of being compelled to act all the time 
simply in response to external stimuli, in which case our activity “is 
controlled by the very object it should itself control", we are able to 
select practicable purposes and set causes in motion and control their 
effects so as to realise our purposes. 

This freedom, Engels continued, “is a product of historical develop- 
ment. The first men who separated themselves from the animal king- 
dom were in all essentials as unfree as the animals themselves, but each 
step forward in civilisation was a step towards freedom.” The “first 
men" were “unfree" simply because in all their activity they remained, 
like other animals, tied to their natural environment. They lived a free 
life in the sense that they could roam around as they chose, and no one 
oppressed them. But there was nevertheless very little they had made 
themselves free to do, and as a result their lives were confined within a 
very restricted round of tribal activities. 

Material objects are the objects of our activity, and their laws are the 
laws on the operations of which we rely in deciding how to act. It 
would therefore be absurd to say (as Dr. Popper seems to suppose 
Marx to have been saying) that the material world and its laws con- 
stitute a restriction on our freedom — as though we could enjoy “true 
freedom" only if there were no material world or if we ourselves were 
not part of it and subject to its laws. But what is true is that material 
objects and their laws are obstacles to our freedom of action, and their 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


318 

presence ties down our action, except in so far as we can find out how to 
use them and master them. 

This, no doubt, is one reason why the more people become con- 
scious of themselves as free agents the more imperative becomes their 
urge to explore and master the environment. Thus quite apart from 
considerations of economic or political advantage people form expedi- 
tions to climb a mountain “because it is there”: there it is, an obstacle 
to men going wherever they wish on our planet, so they feel deter- 
mined to find the way to get to the top of it. Similarly, we feel it to be 
worth while in itself to get to the moon, and then to other planets, and 
then maybe outside the solar system. Apart from any other considera- 
tions, it is a matter of demonstrating that the ruggedness of mountains 
and the vacuity of space will not be allowed to prevent men’s freedom 
of movement. 

But to find out how thus to master the environment is not a matter 
of finding out how to cancel or evade the laws of material existence, 
nor is it a matter of simply pitting our own will and endurance against 
the resistance of natural forces. It is a matter of finding out how to 
construct the means. 

In general, the basic condition for the expansion of human freedom 
has been the advance of technology and the sciences. As Engels pointed 
out: “On the threshold of human history stands the discovery that 
mechanical motion can be transformed into heat: the production of 
fire by friction. And at the close of the development so far gone 
through stands the discovery that heat can be transformed into mechan- 
cal motion: the steam engine.” The discovery of how to produce fire, 
he continued, “gave man for the first time control over one of the 
forces of nature, and thereby separated him for ever from the animal 
kingdom”. And so he concluded: “All past history can be characterised 
as the history of the epoch from the practical discovery of the trans- 
formation of mechanical motion into heat up to that of the transfor- 
mation of heat into mechanical motion” ( Anti-Duhring , Part 1, Chapter 
n). 

Thus, according *:o this account of it, the freedoms won by men up 
to the latter part of the last century were those made possible by men’s 
initial conquest of “control over one of the forces of nature”, developed 
from transforming mechanical motion into heat to transforming 
heat into mechanical motion. This is what made men free to do all the 
things they could do up to the time Engels was writing. And this, he 
added, “shows how young the whole of human history still is”. 


FREEDOM 


319 


Since Engels' time the next great technological revolution has begun 
with the discovery of how to generate and control nuclear energy, 
coupled with the discovery of techniques of automation. This is fully 
comparable with the initial discovery of fire. And its implications for 
the expansion of human freedom are even greater. The development of 
this technology is what can give substance to Marx's idea of men 
“regulating their interchange with nature with the least expenditure of 
energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their 
human nature”. If Marx and Engels themselves could talk of the future 
“realm of freedom” only in rather general terms, not readily under- 
stood by Dr. Popper, that was because they died before the present 
technological revolution began. The freedom which can be achieved on 
the basis of future socialist production surpasses anything that could 
have been made possible by even the most rational employment of 
steam and internal combustion engines, and comprises all that is made 
possible by the employment of nuclear energy and computers. This 
means that men can draw on almost limitless sources of energy, and 
apply them, not to powering machines which have all the time to be 
arduously fed, repaired and controlled by human labour, but in pro- 
cesses which are made self-feeding, self-repairing and self controlling 
in the service of human purposes and needs. 

5. THE MEANS AND OPPORTUNITIES FOR INDIVIDUAL FREEDOM 

All the freedom which people win, and can win, is not won by each 
individual for himself, but it is, as Engels stressed, a social product of the 
combined efforts of many individuals over a long period of time. This 
does not imply, however, that the freedom won consists of anything 
else than a variety of specific freedoms enjoyed by individuals. On the 
contrary, it is human individuals, and only human individuals, who 
enjoy and exercise human freedom. But they enjoy and exercise it 
thanks only to their living within, and their lives being regulated by, 
social institutions. 

The freedom which we want and strive for is the freedom of indi- 
viduals: there is no other human freedom. But if individuals are to get 
all, or even any part of, the freedom which could be theirs, it is essen- 
tial to recognise that the freedom of each individual depends on what 
has been and will be done by all individuals taken together, associated 
in society. It depends on the opportunities for activities and choices of 
activity which the individual enjoys. And in turn the opportunities and 


320 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


choices open to each individual depend on what means for activities 
and satisfactions have been created in the society to which he belongs, 
and on what other members of that society permit and do not permit 
him freely to do. 

There is no doubt that individual freedom implies freedom of choice 
for the individual. Thus to claim freedom is to claim individual freedom 
of choice, that is, freedom to choose what to do without being exter- 
nally constrained to do one thing and not to do another. Hence to be 
free also implies personal responsibility. The free person chooses and 
decides for himself, and does not merely do what he has been ordered 
to do. 

This is a point heavily and, we must agree, rightly stressed by Dr. 
Popper when he writes about “the open society”. There must be 
“personal responsibility” in a free society, he says, rather than indi- 
viduals being instructed in all they should do (i-OS. 113). Such a 
society, he insists, is one “in which individuals are confronted with 
personal decisions” (i-OS. 173). 

However, for the very reason that freedom implies personal res- 
ponsibility, though freedom is proclaimed as a fme tiling it often 
appears as something of a burden. It is, indeed, a hard fate to have to 
choose what to do and bear responsibility for it, under circumstances 
when one is beset w T ith all sorts of personal problems and lacks means 
and opportunities to solve them, and also, very likely, is so deprived of 
education that one does not even know what the problems are, let 
alone how they might be solved. For this reason, people are sometimes 
apt to welcome lack of freedom as a sort of refuge, and to advocate 
depriving others of freedom for their own good. As Tolstoy wrote of 
the army: “Here in the regiment all was clear and simple . . . there was 
nothing to think out or decide” (War and Peace , V.15). 

Dr. Popper himself recognises this difficulty when he goes on to talk 
about “the strain of civilisation” consequent upon our having as 
individuals “to look after ourselves and to accept responsibilities , 
(i-OS. 176). It would seem, therefore, that when individuals take upon 
themselves the onus of personal responsibility they would be well 
advised at the same time to do all they can to assist one another by 
socially providing all possible means and opportunities for each 
individual to benefit from it rather than harm himself and others. 

Evidently, then, if social institutions are to promote and support 
individual freedom, we must demand more of them than only that 
individuals should be left free to act as they choose, on their own 


FREEDOM 


321 


responsibility, and not be pressed or constrained to perform various 
actions whether they choose to or not — with the proviso (on which 
Dr. Popper and other liberals strongly insist) that if, nevertheless, they 
act so as to harm others the police will be after them. We must demand 
that all individuals should have access to the means and opportunities 
for a variety of activities in which they can “develop and exercise all 
faculties, physical and mental”, in co-operation and not to each other's 
detriment; and we must demand that they should be afforded that 
education which will enable them to “make decisions with real 
knowledge of the subject”, and not be forced to make their decisions in 
a random way, or on impulse or relying on the prejudiced advice of 
others, uncontrolled by knowledge. 

Recognising all this, what Marxism is therefore concerned about in 
the matter of freedom is not only to decrease the number of constraints 
imposed on individuals, but also to increase the opportunities and 
choices available to each individual. This implies deploying the techni- 
cal resources of society and organising education so as to provide all 
with the means to a full life, and arranging social relations so that 
each individual is able to take the fullest advantage of his opportun- 
ities. 

To work this out, the first question to tackle is the question why the 
opportunities for individuals have in fact remained so very restricted, 
and why people, whose freedom depends on each other, have done 
so much more to hamper and restrict each other’s freedom than to 
enlarge it. The Marxist theory of “the laws of social development” (in 
Dr. Popper’s view so irrelevant on account of its “historicism” to any 
questions of what is to be done to create a free society) not only supplies 
the scientific answer to the question of why we have not yet a free 
society, but also answers the question of what we must now do to 
get one. 

In brief, during the whole period of social development from men’s 
first discovery of how to turn mechanical motion into heat up to the 
discovery of how to turn heat into mechanical motion, the condition 
for the social production of the means of life and enjoyment for indi- 
viduals was that the great majority of people should be continuously 
engaged in arduous labour. Hence whereas on the one hand people were 
learning how to control forces of nature so as to produce what they 
wanted for themselves, on the other hand the condition for this pro- 
duction was that the great majority became tied to their own means of 
production by bonds which condemned them to unremitting tod. As 


322 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


Marx and Engels showed, the necessary division of labour consequent 
upon the development of social production led to private property in 
means of production, a separation of functions of ownership and man- 
agement from those of productive labour, and the division of society 
into exploiting and exploited classes. The exploiters and masters then 
appropriated to themselves the opportunities for free activities and 
enjoyments accruing from production, together with access to culture 
and education, and the labouring classes, from whose labour these 
opportunities were created, necessarily went without. Thus the con- 
dition for the freedom of the few was the unfreedom of the many. The 
many were driven to toil, whether by the physical force which oppres- 
sed slaves and serfs or by the economic compulsion which compels free 
wage-workers to sell their labour-power. They had no choice but to toil 
for most of their lives. 

It is in this that the unfreedom of the labourers has essentially 
consisted. Superimposed on it have been the various political forms of 
bondage, consisting of deprivations of rights, and oppressions and 
coercions of various kinds, imposed on them within the social 
institutions. 

Throughout this period of history the class struggle has always taken 
the form of struggles for freedom, or rather for specific freedoms which 
people fought to retain or saw the possibility of winning. Such free- 
doms can always be characterised in two ways, negative and positive, 
“freedom from” and “freedom for”. People seek to free themselves 
from specific impositions and restrictions on their activity, and to win 
(or retain) conditions in which they are free to do specific tilings which 
they want to do and in which they see advantage. Thus in class struggles 
people have managed to free themselves from specific forms of political 
oppression, and at the same time to win specific rights. The winning of 
rights for some has always and necessarily meant the cancelling of rights 
for others — for instance, the rights won when slavery was ended can- 
celled the rights of slaveowners, the rights won in connection with the 
establishment of capitalism cancelled feudal rights, and so on. But 
whatever impositions and restrictions were shaken off, and whatever 
rights were won, the fact remained that the exploited classes never won 
freedom from exploitation, and the rights of the exploiters continued. 
Hence whatever freedoms the exploited classes won (and in some 
countries they have won a lot) were always limited by their being 
driven to work for the greater part of their lives for the benefit and 
under the orders of others, and the most cherished freedom of the 


FREEDOM 


323 


exploiting classes has always been their freedom to direct and appro- 
priate the labour of others. 

The great contribution of the social researches of Marx was not 
simply that he expounded these facts about freedom and lack of free- 
dom in the historical development of the past, but that he showed that 
private property in means of production, and exploitation, originally 
necessary consequences of the division of labour, and necessary con- 
ditions for the development of social production, have now become so 
far from being necessary that they act as fetters on the further develop- 
ment of social production. He recognised the fact (which none who 
take into account the potentialities of modem technology can deny) 
that with the modem development of forces of production it is no 
longer necessary that the majority of the human race should devote the 
greater part of their lives to labour, nor that the opportunity of educa- 
tion and leisure to enjoy most of the advantage accruing from it 
should belong to only a few. The conditions are present for the human 
race finally to free itself from the age-old bondage of labour. And what 
Marx did (Dr. Popper mistakes this for an historicist unconditional 
prophecy of a violent revolution) was to work out the foundations of 
the theory of how to win this freedom. 

On the basis of his scientific social and historical analysis, Marx 
demonstrated the necessary condition for it. This is that the modem 
working classes must carry through what, when it is done, will be the 
last act of the class struggle — to bring an end to private property in 
means of production and the exploitation of labour, and establish 
social ownership of means of production and planning of production 
to satisfy human needs. 

Then it will be possible (but not, of course, without considerable 
collective efforts over a long period of time, nor without “many 
mistakes” being made) to bring about the organisation of a free 
society, in which collective management of the production of all the 
necessary means to free activities is done and controlled with no other 
object than the provision of those means to individuals. Then every 
individual can enjoy for the greater part of his life all the opportunities 
for unconstrained free human activity afforded by “the associated 
producers rationally regulating their interchange with nature, bringing 
it under their common control instead of being ruled by it as by the 
blind forces of nature, and achieving this with the least expenditure of 
energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their 
human nature”. 


324 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


This freedom which individuals can then enjoy comes from their 
togetherness. It is the product of their working together. And only by 
working together, obeying the rules of communal life, educating 
themselves, and each contributing all he can to producing the satis- 
faction of the needs of others, can they enjoy that freedom. 

As regards work, or social production, Marx emphasised that in this 
matter men do not have and cannot have a free choice as to whether to 
engage in it or not. In this sphere, as he said, the only freedom that can 
be won is the freedom of being able to work in the best obtainable 
conditions, and of being able to contribute to the best of one’s abilities. 
This is the point which Dr. Popper fmds so incomprehensible that he 
can only interpret it as meaning that “true freedom” consists in “the 
emancipation from the flesh”. But the point is simply that we are not 
free to choose whether or not to engage in social production, because 
if we are to enjoy any social life, and the freedoms obtainable in social 
life, we have got to work for it. The means must be supplied, the work 
has got to be done. So as human freedom springs from appreciation of 
necessity, and not from any imaginary emancipation of any of our 
activities from their necessary conditions, men and women in a free 
society will regard work as a necessary condition for all their freedom. 
Consequently, if they follow Marx’s advice, they will arrange for it to 
be done as expeditiously, efficiently and effortlessly as possible, and to 
this end will share it out on equalitarian principles according to a 
rational plan. 


3 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 

I. THE CLOSED AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 

“We can return to the beasts**, so Dr. Popper tells us. “But if we wish 
to remain human, then there is only one way, the way into the open 
society** (i-OS. 201). 

According to him, “the open society’* is something w r e find our 
way into by getting out of “the closed society**. So its characteristics 
are defined in opposition to those of the closed society. A “closed** 
society is, he explains, a “primitive tribal society” which “lives in a 
charmed circle of unchanging taboos, of laws and customs which are 
felt to be as inevitable as the rising of the sun, or the cycle of the 
seasons, or similar obvious regularities of nature”. It is characterised 
by a “magical attitude”, as opposed to a scientific one. Its members 
think that the rules current in their tribe w T hich “forbid or demand 
certain modes of conduct” are as fixed and inviolable as natural laws 
(i-OS. 57). So they never think of altering them, and anyone who 
disobeys them is strongly disapproved of and punished for his audacity. 

The attitude of the closed society, Dr. Popper next explains, is 
continued in societies in which the state undertakes to regulate more 
or less the whole of the citizens* lives. This, he warns, is to “replace 
personal responsibility by tribalistic taboos and by the totalitarian 
irresponsibility of the individual” (i-OS. 113). In the closed society 
all the “norms” of conduct are laid down and strictly enforced, so that 
individuals are not allowed to exercise their personal judgment as to 
what is right. The results are generally bad. In the open society, on 
the other hand, individuals exercise their own judgment, and so far 
from their having to renounce personal judgment in subordination 
to the state, the state is answerable to their judgment. 

This contrast between the principles of operation of an open and a 
closed society is pointed by Dr. Popper (i-OS. 7) in two quotations 
from the ancient Greeks. One is a statement by Pericles: “Although 
only a few may originate a policy, we are all able to judge it.” The 
other is taken from Plato: “The greatest principle of all is that nobody 
. . . should be without a leader. Nor should the mind of anybody be 
habituated to letting him do anything at all on his own initiative . . . 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


326 

even in the smallest matter he should stand under leadership. For 
example, he should get up, or move, or wash, or take his meals . . . 
only if he has been told to do so. In a word, he should teach his soul, 
by long habit, never to dream of acting independently, and to become 
utterly incapable of it.” 

In contrast to “the magical or tribal or collectivist” closed society, 
then, the open society is “the society in which individuals are con- 
fronted with personal decisions” (i-OS. 173). 

“In the light of what has been said,” Dr. Popper continues, “it will 
be clear that the transition from the closed to the open society can be 
described as one of the deepest revolutions through which mankind 
has passed” (i-OS. 175). According to his reading of history, this 
revolution got under way in ancient Greece in the great days of 
Athenian democracy. For it was there and then that “there rose a new 
faith in reason, freedom and the brotherhood of all men — the new 
faith and, as I believe, the only possible faith of the open society” 
(i-OS. 184). 

But the breakdown of the closed society, that is to say, the breaking 
of its “charmed circle of unchanging taboos, of laws and customs” 
within which everything individuals had to do was settled for them, 
leads to individuals feeling a “strain” due to difficulties encountered 
in trying to use their own judgment (i-OS. 176-7). Hence the con- 
tinued urge is expressed to get back again somehow to the security of 
a closed society, and to reimpose its fixed rules of life. This is expressed 
in doctrines of “totalitarianism”, which echo the creed of the closed 
society “that the tribe is everything and the individual nothing” 
(i— OS. 190). It is likewise expressed in “nationalism”, which “appeals 
to our tribal instincts, to passion and to prejudice, and to our nostalgic 
desire to be relieved from the strain of individual responsibility which 
it attempts to replace by collective or group responsibility” (2-OS. 
49 ). 

That is the sum-total of what Dr. Popper has positively to tell us 
about the open in contrast to the closed society. What it amounts to is 
that society is “open” when individual members of society are con- 
strained by no externally imposed laws and customs in forming 
judgments, and when not only is each individually responsible for his 
own actions but exercises his independent judgment in approving or 
disapproving public policies. To make such a society work, reliance is 
not placed on inviolable law or custom or on the dictates of traditional 
or any other authority, but on “faith in reason, freedom and the 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


327 


brotherhood of all men”. For it can flourish only when the members 
of society try to form judgments by the exercise of reason, value the 
freedom of each and all, and agree to live in brotherhood. On that 
condition they can not only each exercise his individual judgment but 
together preserve conditions of security for enjoying their freedom. 

From this premise Dr. Popper concludes that, firm in “the faith of 
the open society” we “must go on into the unknown, the uncertain 
and insecure, using what reason we may have to plan as well as we can 
for both security and freedom” (i-OS. 201). 

Always anxious to be fair to Marx, even while exposing his errors 
as sins against the open society, Dr. Popper allows that “he admitted 
his love for freedom . . . Marx’s faith, I believe, was fundamentally a 
faith in the open society” (2-OS. 200). But, he warns, “in spite of his 
merits, Marx was ... a false prophet . . . responsible for the devastating 
influence of the historicist method of thought within the ranks of those 
who wish to advance the cause of the open society” (2-OS. 82). 
Just as the “historicist” doctrine that society progresses from stage to 
stage by inexorable necessity teaches individuals that their personal 
decisions can count for nothing and they cannot be responsible for 
what happens, so the dictatorship which Marx advocated would 
actually deprive them of all responsibility. “The prophetic element in 
Marx’s creed was dominant in the minds of his followers”, Dr. Popper 
concludes. “It swept everything else aside, banishing the power of cool 
and critical judgment and destroying the belief that by the use of 
reason we may change the world.” Marx left us with “an oracular 
philosophy” which “threatens to paralyse the struggle for the open 
society” (2-OS. 198). 

We have seen, however, that Marxism in fact investigates the 
conditions for obtaining security and freedom for individuals, and 
advocates the conquest of political power in order to plan the bringing 
of these conditions into existence. Dr. Popper makes a great point of 
emphasising “security and freedom” when he holds forth about what 
we must plan for. Quite so. And a merit of Marx which Dr. Popper 
does not share is that Marx did work out the necessary conditions for 
planning for just that. 

We may perhaps detect in Dr. Popper’s statement about “die way 
into the open society” a certain vagueness, and even a combination of 
big words with little meaning. For if we are to use “what reason we 
may have”, not simply to protect our security and freedom when they 
are in danger, but “to plan as well as we can” how to advance them, 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


328 

then surely we must work out what conditions are required for 
maximising both security and freedom and strive to bring them about. 
And if that is a practical objective, then what we are heading towards 
cannot be so entirely “unknown” as Dr. Popper says. True, it cannot 
but remain “uncertain” because we cannot know how well we shall 
succeed, and “insecure” because of the unexpected difficulties we may 
encounter. But if Dr. Popper is right in saying that “the way into the 
open society” leads “into the unknown”, his advice that “we should 
plan as well as we can” how to take it is mere hot air. For how well can 
we plan the way to go when we do not know where we are going? 
Although Dr. Popper says that the route mapped out by Marxism is 
to be avoided, because by taking it we shall only “return to the beasts”, 
Marx’s views are still perhaps worth more serious consideration than 
his own, because Marx did at least try to use such reason as he possessed 
to work out what were the practical conditions for security and 
freedom which we can now try to bring into existence. 

Dr. Popper has written two volumes on “the open society and its 
enemies”, comprising 481 pages of text plus 221 pages of notes. But 
if one searches in them for information about how to go forward into 
the open society and get rid of some of the deprivations of material 
necessities, education and opportunity which individuals continue to 
suffer on a large scale, one is left with nothing but generalities about 
“individual responsibility”. One may well be tempted to echo Prince 
Hal’s exclamation when he examined the record of his mentor’s 
proceedings: “O monstrous! but one half-pennyworth of bread to 
this intolerable deal of sack!” 

2. THE WAY INTO THE OPEN SOCIETY 

Dr. Popper assures us that “the transition from the closed to the open 
society can be described as one of the deepest revolutions through 
which mankind has passed”, but has little to say about how it happened. 
In one of his luminous and voluminous notes, however, he supplies us 
with a “criterion”. “It seems to be possible to give some useful criterion 
of the transition from the closed society to the open. The transition 
takes place when social institutions are first consciously recognised as 
man-made, and when their conscious alteration is discussed in terms of 
their suitability for the achievement of human aims or purposes. Or, 
putting the matter in a less abstract way, the closed society breaks 
down when the supernatural awe with which the social order is 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


329 


considered gives way to active interference, and to the conscious 
pursuit of personal or group interests” (i-OS. 294). 

As he told us at the start, in the closed society institutions are not 
recognised as man-made, but are regarded as fixed and inviolable 
parts of the order of the universe. So they cannot be interfered with, 
and their alteration cannot be discussed. When there enters into men’s 
heads the consciousness that their institutions are man-made, they can 
start discussing how to alter them. After that, Dr. Popper concludes, 
the chief tiling that has continued to obstruct our going foward with 
the conscious and rational alteration of institutions “for the achieve- 
ment of human aims or purposes” has been the dead weight of pre- 
historic beliefs left over from tribalism and elaborated by enemies of 
the open society as doctrines treating institutions as other than man- 
made. 

Dr. Popper’s statement that people came to recognise their insti- 
tutions as man-made and advanced out of the closed society by 
altering them to suit the various purposes suggested by personal or 
group interests is not very illuminating as a description of what 
happened, and even less as an explanation. Marxists may perhaps be 
excused for suspecting in this account of what happened in history, if 
not an “historicist” doctrine about the “pattern” of historical develop- 
ment, at least a considerable oversimplification. But that Dr. Popper 
does not himself altogether share the idealist doctrine that great changes 
in human social behaviour can be described and explained simply as 
the spontaneous generation in some men’s minds of new ideas about 
their social institutions is shown by his own statement in the text, that 
“perhaps the most powerful cause of the breakdown of the closed 
society was the development of sea-communications and commerce” 

(i-OS. 177). 

The point was made a long time ago by Marx, and is now generally 
agreed (including, it seems, by Dr. Popper), that what makes “tribal 
society” break down and other more “open” forms of society emerge 
is the development of technology. Sea-communications and commerce 
are, of course, a part of this, and have had a very disturbing effect on 
societies in which they were developed — though tribalism in fact 
began to break down before sea-faring commerce got under way. 
Anyway, where technology has not been developed, there tribalism 
with its “charmed circle of unchanging taboos” has not been disturbed. 
Marx showed, and subsequent researches have continued to show, that 
technological innovations proved incompatible with many of the laws 


330 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


and customs previously held inviolable in tribal society, as a result of 
which the laws and customs were violated. This circumstance broke 
into the “superstitious awe” with which the tribal order was sur- 
rounded. And because the use of new technology, with division of 
labour, set up personal and group interests as distinct from the single 
tribal interest, it led to “the conscious pursuit of personal or group 
interests”. 

The consciousness that social institutions are man-made is indeed, 
as Dr. Popper says, of vital importance for human progress, because 
of the implication that what man made man can improve on. But if 
we are to understand the real issues and problems men have faced 
since the breakdown of tribalism, and still more what it is possible to 
do now to alter institutions to suit human purposes, and what is 
necessary in order to do it, it is hardly sufficient simply to be conscious 
that institutions are man-made. As I have said before, we need to 
know the laws and conditions of their making. 

Dr. Popper says with truth that when tribal society breaks down 
there ensues “the conscious pursuit of personal or group interests” — 
though this statement could be qualified by remarking, with Marx, 
that consciousness of interests often takes a disguised form. If in 
primitive tribal society there was as yet no attempt made to alter 
institutions to suit personal or group interests, that was not so much 
because the tyranny of tribal custom forbade it as because there were 
no separate personal or group interests to be suited. Obviously, once 
separate interests had arisen, to get institutions altered to suit them was 
an example of “the achievement of human aims or purposes”, because 
the interests were human ones. But as obviously, it is a far cry from 
“the pursuit of group interests” to “the achievement of human 
purposes” in the sense that the achievement suits the interests of all 
human beings and not only of one group of them in opposition to 
another. In fact the “pursuit of personal or group interests” which 
ensues upon the breakdown of tribal society led invariably, and quite 
inevitably, to the forcible subordination of the interests of persons to 
the interests of groups, and of the interests of one group to those of 
another. So far as most persons were concerned, the kind of class- 
divided society which succeeded tribalism was very far from “open”, 
not because their opportunities for “personal decision” in the conduct 
of life were thwarted by tribal taboos, but because they were thwarted 
by the subjection of their personal and group interests to those of the 
ruling class. 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


331 


Marx demonstrated clearly enough how it was that “personal or 
group interests” came to be pursued, and what were (and still are) 
the overall results of this pursuit. The cause was the development of 
the social forces of production. And Marx pointed out that this 
development was not simply a process of invention of new teclmiques 
but a change in the sum-total of activity of human beings in obtaining 
and distributing the means of life. 

The primitive tribe, living by food-gathering and hunting, consti- 
tuted a single group of people banded together to produce and appro- 
priate their own product for their own use. Its unchanging taboos, 
laws and customs represented no tyranny practised against individuals 
but rather the means of maintaining the tribal solidarity on which the 
very existence of every individual in such conditions depended. The 
invention of teclmiques of cultivating the land, domesticating animals, 
handicrafts and metalworking broke up the closed society of the tribe, 
because they entailed the division of labour. This differentiated people 
from one another in their ways of obtaining the requirements of life. 
It brought property in means of production and in products, exchange 
of products, and the production of a surplus out of which owners and 
managers could be supported. 

This in turn meant that while social wealth increased, and con- 
sequently the scope of the activities and enjoyments possible for 
individuals, the producers collectively lost control over their product. 
For it was no longer a collective product but a sum of individual 
products passing into the process of exchange. And those who owned 
property acquired separate interests in augmenting it. Some persons 
could acquire property in means of production to the exclusion of 
others, and in that way command the labour of others and appropriate 
its surplus for themselves. The labourers were then placed in a position 
where they had to work to supply products to owners and managers, 
as directed by the latter. Their working capacities were no longer 
exerted by them after the tribal custom as part of the collective effort 
to supply the collective need, but were appropriated by an owning 
and managing class for its own enrichment. 

Thus the antagonisms of classes were created, and the history of 
society became the history of class struggles. With this, the whole 
business of social management changed. The state came into existence, 
as an institution through which some men rule over the rest. 

With the capitalist economic formation, the changes winch were 
set up by the breakdown of tribal society eventually come to a head. 


332 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


All products are produced as commodities for exchange, which means 
that the entire social product passes out of the control of the producers. 
The producers’ own labour-power becomes a commodity, so that 
the direction and control of their personal abilities to produce what 
each needs is entirely lost to them. People cannot now decide to work 
to produce what they want, since they have to work for whoever will 
buy their labour-power; and the increase or decrease of the total 
product, the proportions of different branches of production, and the 
eventual destination of products are all outside the producers’ control 
and settled by economic laws of the market which operate independ- 
ently of the voluntary actions of men. The class struggle is polarised 
into a single antagonism between the class which sells its labour-power 
and the class which buys it. And finally, the state, as a power which 
men have set up over themselves to rule them, becomes greatly 
strengthened and centralised; and the more it intervenes in economic 
production and distribution, the more does it stand over the producers 
as an organisation which rules them but which they do not 
control. 

In all these respects, the social relations which obtain under capitalism 
are the complete negation of those which originally obtained under 
tribalism or primitive communism. In moving away from the tribal 
order, the social formation has gone as far as it can go, into the direct 
antithesis. In men’s social development, capitalism stands at the furthest 
remove from tribalism . Where before nothing was produced as a 
commodity, now everything is produced as a commodity. Where 
people appropriated and consumed their social product as they 
produced it, now it has gone out of their control. Where people 
banded together to try to produce what they wanted, now each 
worker has to do what work he is told. Where there was no division 
of class interest, now there is a deep class division cutting right through 
society. And where people decided their common affairs for them- 
selves according to their own tribal laws and customs, now they are 
subject to the rule of an all-powerful state. 

Since, then, Dr. Popper identifies “the closed society” with tribalism, 
it is natural that he should see in the antithetical conditions obtaining 
under capitalism the realisation of “the open society”. For him, indeed, 
“the open society” is only another name for capitalism. 

But he never sees that the development of forces of production 
and of relations of production, which led from the breakdown of 
primitive communism to the establishment of capitalism, was a 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


333 


development of different methods of exploiting labour. He only remarks 
superficially on some of their effects in institutions of social manage- 
ment, in ideologies and in the lives of individuals. Hence he sees the 
antithesis between tribalism and capitalism only as the antithesis 
between a society which “lives in a charmed circle of unchanging 
taboos, of laws and customs which are felt to be as inevitable as the 
rising of .the sun”, and one where institutions can be regarded as 
“man-made” and people can discuss their alteration to suit their 
personal or group interests. For him, capitalism is “the open society” 
because there are separate personal and group interests inside it and 
people can organise to press them ; and because no human institutions 
are any longer regarded as sacrosanct but everyone can discuss whether 
it is best to keep them as they are or alter them. In that sense, it is 
“open”. But yet the way the institutions of the production and dis- 
tribution of the means of life are fixed prevent people from being able 
to take personal decisions and to accept individual responsibility for 
working together for the production of their needs. 

In the light of these considerations we cannot but view with scepti- 
cism Dr. Popper’s contention that all those institutions and ideologies 
which have oppressed individuals since the demise of tribalism are at 
bottom hangovers from the tribe, dragging mankind backwards to the 
tribal closed society. One may freely admit the obvious fact, which 
Dr. Popper vigorously affirms, that ideologies and institutions im- 
posing beliefs, taboos, laws and customs to be accepted and obeyed 
without criticism are incompatible with individual responsibility, 
personal decision and rational judgment. One may agree that such 
were the ideologies and institutions in tribal societies. And one may 
agree, too, that subsequent' exemplars have often and regrettably 
appealed to the same irrational fear and hatred directed against taboo- 
breakers and outsiders which tribesmen sometimes evince. But that 
does not mean that all subsequent repressive ideologies and institutions 
have been hangovers from tribalism. On the contrary, the shut-down 
they impose on individuals has had no tendency towards restoring 
the primitive communal way of life. The state of affairs which the 
hymn “All Things Bright and Beautiful” finds so admirable 

“The rich man in his castle, the poor man at his gate, 

God made them high or lowly, and ordered their estate” 

is absolutely foreign and unknown to tribesmen. The ideas and institu- 
tions of tribalism were those of the solidarity of small groups in 


334 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


which no one pursued personal or group interests in antagonism to 
his fellows. These subsequent ideas and institutions were consequent 
upon the destruction of that primitive human solidarity and the 
dominance in society of acquisitive class interests. 

Dr. Popper tries to make out that such modern phenomena as 
“totalitarianism” are a return to tribalism, induced by people feeling 
“the strain of civilisation” in an open society. But the facts make it 
clear that the repression of individuals under modern totalitarianism 
has little in common with primitive tribal solidarity but represents 
the violent assertion of the interests of an aggressive group of exploiters. 

Having identified “the struggle for the open society” as the attempt 
to alter institutions to suit personal or group interests, and “the closed 
society” with the suppression of separate interests, which in turn is 
identified with tribalism, Dr. Popper then goes on to contend that 
the policies of a militant labour movement are another sort of totali- 
tarianism which will likewise lead us back to tribal conditions. For 
these policies will suppress certain interests, and subordinate personal 
and group interests to a common interest. It would seem that a delegate 
conference is like a tribal jamboree, and that in every militant mass 
demonstration civilisation is threatened by the primitive horde run 
riot. So by representing “the struggle for the open society” as the 
struggle finally to overcome tribal hangovers, consummated in the 
capitalist antithesis to primitive communism, Dr. Popper ignores and 
obscures completely the struggle to overcome the forms of class domination 
which superseded tribalism, and the resistance it meets with from the 
forces which organise to maintain class domination. 

In capitalist society the “open” conditions have been created where 
people can organise to change their social institutions in a way con- 
sciously decided to suit their interests. And the class struggle has 
reached a stage where the working class emerges as an organised force 
equipped with a scientific theory of how social changes can be brought 
about. So the issue which insistently arises in this society is that of 
organised action by the working class to throw off the fetters of capital- 
ism, take control of the state into the hands of its own democratic 
organisations, and institute social measures to bring social production 
under the control of the organised producers. The very “openness” 
of capitalist society provides the conditions for ending the exploitation 
of man by man which supervened on the break-up of the “closed 
society” of tribalism. The issue therefore posed by “the open society” 
as it actually exists at the present day is not that of defending it from 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


335 


reversion to tribalism but of going forward to socialism and com- 
munism. 

The progress of mankind from the animal condition from which 
we sprang is progress in the human activity of socially producing the 
means of life, and of increasing the scope of human activity and 
achievement as we get further from the animal condition by mastering 
the materials and forces of the natural environment for human pur- 
poses. It is in this progress that there is made possible the individuality 
of the human person, as distinct from the animal as a member of the 
species conditioned to the unchanging habits of the species. Human 
individuality is the product of the increase of mens collective powers 
and of the increased supply of the means to a more varied life. Dr. 
Popper says that “if we wish to remain human” we must go forward 
“into the open society”. If we wish to remain human we must go on 
producing our needs, and we shall go forward with this the better if we 
manage by human co-operation to control the product so as to supply 
everyone’s needs and thus allow to the development of everyone’s 
individuality full scope. That means we must overcome the exploitation 
of man by man , and the divisions of class-society. 

The poor life of primitive communities, when all individuals had to 
be much the same as one another and cling together in a common 
observance of taboos and customs, was overcome by the development 
of new forces of production, which in turn led to the negation of the 
tribal solidarity of primitive man by class divisions. The poverty- 
stricken subsistence economy was negated by commodity production. 
The close ties of kinship between individuals within the tribal organ- 
isation were negated by making all individuals living and working 
in a territory the subjects -of a state. But these negations must be 
negated by the working people of today asserting their control as 
producers over the socialised production of modem industry, equipped 
as it is with techniques capable of producing plenty, thus instituting 
once more the social appropriation of the social product, and taking 
over organised democratic control of state power. Then the future 
conditions for the freedom of human individuals, with their individual 
responsibilities and personal decisions, will be secure. 

This is what Dr. Popper, with his abstract description of “the open 
society” as the antithesis of the tribal or “closed” society, entirely fails 
to understand. He simply fails to comprehend what Marx demonstra- 
ted, namely, that the negation of the “closed society” of tribalism only 
led to class divisions and exploitation, and that the way forward 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


33<5 

“into the open society” now demands the negation of this negation. 
Shocked by such Hegelian horrors, Dr. Popper protests vociferously 
that this is nothing but an “historicist” doctrine cooked up by dog- 
matically applying to human development the arbitrary pattern of 
“thesis-antithesis-synthesis”. To end the conditions of the pursuit of 
antagonistic personal and group interests which superseded tribalism 
will, .according to him, only land us back into a worse sort of tribalism. 
But it is in these capitalist apologetics of Dr. Popper that an uncom- 
prehending dogmatic attitude is to be found, not in the scientific 
socialist theory of Marx. Marx did not deduce the course of history 
from any Hegelian formula. He examined how men actually made their 
institutions , and saw that the time had come when the exploitation of man by 
man could and should be ended. 

This being so, to go forward “into the open society” is not to go, 
as Dr. Popper says, “into the unknown”. On the contrary, there are 
definite issues to face, a definite job to do, and an organisation to be 
built to do it. 

3. RESPONSIBILITY, INDIVIDUAL AND COLLECTIVE 

In Dr. Popper’s conception, the essential feature of “the open society” 
is that individuals in it bear personal responsibility and make personal 
decisions. With him, this suffices to define “the open society”: a 
society is “open” when it allows enough scope for personal responsi- 
bility and personal decisions. His objection to Marxism is so strong 
because he says Marxists hatch plots to take personal responsibility 
away from individuals, and to prevent their making personal decisions, 
by enforcing on them a tyranny similar to that which he says existed 
in tribes — the tyranny of collective taboos, laws and customs. But let 
us agree with him in calling society “open” when it allows scope for 
responsibility and decisions ; then far from objecting to society being 
made “open” in that sense, Marxists agree with him that the more 
“open” it can be made the better. Apologists for capitalism have no 
monopoly in wishing society to be “open”. Still less have they a 
monopoly in policies of how to make it so. 

“Our own ways of life”, Dr. Popper freely admits (meaning the 
ways of life in capitalist democracies), “are still beset with taboos. . . . 
And yet . . . there is between the laws of the state on the one hand and 
the taboos we habitually observe on the other, an ever-widening field 
of personal decisions, with its problems and responsibilities.” This field 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


337 


of personal decisions and responsibilities is not just the field of private 
life, for “many of us make rational decisions concerning the desirability 
or otherwise of new legislation, and of other institutional changes; 
that is to say, decisions based upon an estimate of possible con- 
sequences, and upon a conscious preference for some of them. We 
recognise rational personal responsibility” (i-OS. 173). The great 
point which we have won is that we recognise that institutions are 
man-made and that it is open to us to alter them, so that there exists, as 
Dr. Popper goes on to point out, “the possibility of rational reflection 
on these matters” — rational reflection consisting of estimating possible 
consequences and formulating conscious preferences. So although we 
“are still beset with taboos”, everyone can judge for himself as to what 
is best in the way of “new legislation and other institutional changes”, 
and is not bound to submit his judgment to that of anyone placed in 
authority over him. 

This personal responsibility and freedom of personal decision in our 
open society is opposed by Dr. Popper to “the totalitarian irresponsi- 
bility of the individual” where individuals are not allowed to judge 
or decide anything for themselves. In the open society choices are open 
to individuals as to what they shall do and what they shall make of 
their lives, as individuals, and also as to what they shall think and what 
public policies they shall support or oppose, so that in deciding all 
these matters for themselves there is also open to them “the possibility 
of rational reflection”. 

That being so, he opposes “collective” to “individual responsibility”. 
He sees the collective as a tyranny, or at all events a potential tyranny, 
over the individual, which would force the individual to abandon his 
personal judgment to a collective judgment, his individual responsibility 
to a collective responsibility, and his personal choice as to what he 
should do to a collective instruction as to what he should do. To call 
for “collective responsibility” is, he implies, a case of reintroducing 
“the totalitarian irresponsibility of the individual”. 

It is of course perfectly true that in “our own ways of life” there is, 
exactly as Dr. Popper says, “an ever-widening field of personal 
decisions, with its problems and responsibilities”. How r much this 
field has widened in the case of working people in particular can be 
readily appreciated by comparing the conditions of contemporary 
wage-workers with former serfs. When in the year 1381 the English 
King, Richard II, told the defeated remnants of the peasants’ revolt 
“serfs ye are, and serfs ye shall remain” he meant, among other tilings, 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


338 

that they should make no personal decisions as to whom they worked for 
or where they worked. The serf was in fact allowed very little personal 
responsibility for anything. The contemporary wage-worker is, by 
comparison, a very responsible person with scope for a large number 
of personal decisions on matters ranging from where to apply for a 
job to whom to vote for in parliamentary elections. 

If Marxists now sought to deprive workers of the individual re- 
sponsibilities and scope for personal decisions they have won it would 
be a strange inconsistency, considering that Marxists have always 
fought to help win them and in that sense have been among the fore- 
most champions of “the open society”. But Marxists do say that for 
individuals to have individual responsibilities and make individual 
decisions is not enough. We want to institute forms of the exercise 
of collective responsibility and collective decision. The reason why we 
want this is that individuals live, and can only live, within a frame- 
work of the social production of the means of life. And this reason also 
defines the sphere within which we think that collective responsibility 
should be exercised. But this is what causes Dr. Popper to conclude 
that we are heading straight back to tribalism. For according to him, 
individual and collective responsibility are incompatibles. He sets them 
in antithesis, so that anyone who calls for collective responsibility is in 
effect calling for an end to individual responsibility and its replacement 
by “the totalitarian irresponsibility of the individual”. It is also the end 
of rationality. For it puts an end to “the possibility of rational reflec- 
tion” which resides in the making of personal decisions. 

One ought to ask what exactly can be meant by “collective responsi- 
bility”. Dr. Popper cites “nationalism” as a case where it takes over. 
Though he is far from explicit as to his meaning, it seems a fair guess 
that his reference is to cases where a large number of persons constitute 
themselves into a mob, activated by a common sentiment. It is true 
that in such cases the individuals concerned can hardly be credited with 
“rational responsibility” for what they are doing, and that together 
they bully, intimidate and coerce any other individuals who try to 
think for themselves and oppose themselves in any way to the clamour 
of the mob. It is also true that when such a tyranny of the mob occurs 
it can provide the opportunity for a “strong man” to step into the 
leadership and exert his own personal tyramiy, so that the tyranny 
of the mob leads to “the rule of the strong man” and “the strong man” 
makes use of mob sentiments in order to enforce his own rule. But 
while it may be true that this type of social behaviour “appeals to our 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


339 


tribal instincts, to passion and to prejudice, and to our nostalgic desire 
to be relieved from the strain of individual responsibility which it 
attempts to replace by collective or group responsibility”, it is hardly 
true that it presents an example of anything that could reasonably be 
called “collective responsibility”. Indeed, one of the chief objections 
to letting ourselves forgo our “individual responsibility” and be 
carried away by mob sentiments is that the result is not “collective 
responsibility” but collective irresponsibility. 

Collective responsibility is created where and only where people are united 
in democratic organisation. In that case they can engage in rational 
discussion and debate as to what to do as an organised body. And when 
they do it, it is done as a result of a collective decision arrived at as 
the product of the organised accumulation of a number of individual 
decisions. Clearly, collective responsibility exercised through democratic 
organisation is not incompatible with individual responsibility . On the 
contrary, it follows from the exercise of responsibility by individuals united 
in an organisation . And it is not incompatible either with “the possibility 
of rational reflection”, but furthers it. 

Marxists, therefore, who favour the development of democratic 
organisation, are not, as Dr. Popper alleges, seeking to replace “in- 
dividual responsibility” and “personal decision” by a fictitious “collec- 
tive responsibility” which only masks the tyranny of the mob or “the 
rule of the strong man”. On the other hand, to set the one against the 
other, as Dr. Popper does, is in effect to seek to limit the sphere of 
responsibility. For the truth is that there exists a large sphere of matters 
of public concern for the continuous control of which no one 
can be held responsible unless there is organised collective responsibil- 
ity- 

Dr. Popper sees responsibility and decision exclusively as individual 
matters. Thus in public affairs certain persons, namely, those who hold 
offices of power, make decisions and are responsible for making them ; 
and other persons, when there are democratic institutions, control 
them by casting their votes in accordance with individual “decisions 
concerning the desirability or otherwise of new legislation and of other 
institutional changes”. And that is “the open society”. But, we may 
ask, who is responsible for the forms taken by our social relations of pro- 
duction? In our present capitalist way of life, where it is open to in- 
dividuals to make so many “rational decisions”, no one is responsible. 
Of course, decisions taken by numerous individuals in the pursuit of 
their personal or group interests resulted in these social relations being 


340 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


instituted. But no individual or collective decision was ever taken to 
institute these kinds of social relations, in which social production is 
fettered by the private appropriation of the social product by owners 
of capital. The fact is that, as Marx pointed out, men have entered into 
relations of production independent of their will. The way people 
conduct themselves to produce and distribute their means of life has 
not been and in capitalist countries still is not decided upon in the light 
of any rational estimation of consequences. Marxism is concerned with 
ways and means of remedying this deplorable situation of irresponsi- 
bility in the most basic affairs of social life. Marxists work to build 
organisation by means of which the conduct of social production can be 
collectively decided and its management collectively controlled . Only within 
such organisation can it become open for individuals to discuss and take 
rational collective decisions as to how the common social resources are to be 
used to meet individual needs . 

Once again, it is not liberals and individualists like Dr. Popper who 
advocate the extension of “rational responsibility” for all members 
of the human race, while Marxists oppose it. It is exactly the other way 
round. 

When writing about institutions, Dr. Popper himself clearly re- 
cognised that, because institutions are man-made, it does not follow 
that anyone is responsible for the decision to make them or for de- 
cisions as to how they are altered. As he said, many “just grow”. 
But when it comes to writing about the “open” and “closed” societies, 
and contrasting capitalist society as “open” with tribal society as 
“closed”, he forgets this simple truth. For he fails to notice that a 
similar condition of irresponsibility as regards the most important 
institutions — those concerned with relations of production — continues 
throughout the development of social formations from tribalism or 
primitive communism to capitalism. In tribal society the “taboos and 
customs” were certainly “man-made”, but because no one was 
consciously responsible for making or altering them the tribesmen 
thought of them as inescapable conditions of human life which men 
were bound to accept. Thus they were closed in by rules of their own 
making which nevertheless ruled them like an external power de- 
termining their personalities, their relations with each other and their 
conduct of life. When tribal society broke up as a result of the develop- 
ment of the forces of production people made for themselves the rules 
of property, of exploitation of man by man and of the division of 
classes. And these have ruled them just the same, and closed them in, 


THE OPEN SOCIETY 


341 


even though (for some people at any rate) there is greater scope for 
personal decisions and personal responsibility. 

In our capitalist society we are still ruled and closed in in the same 
way. Thus in social production people have to sell their labour-power, 
so that they have to work on tasks set for them and not on producing 
what they have decided to produce to meet their needs. Everyone 
concerned, whether worker or manager, is driven to work for the 
accumulation of capital. The product of labour is put into the market, 
so that neither whose who make it nor those who need it have overall 
control to ensure that what is made shall get to those who need it and 
that what is needed shall be made. Again, the relations which people 
have entered into in producing the means of life create divisions 
between them so that they fmd themselves in dispute and at enmity, 
and are driven to injure one another, for reasons for which they are 
in no way personally responsible. 

In all this, where is the rational responsibility, open to all individuals 
to accept and exercise, for arranging social relations so as to make the 
most rational use of social resources? It is not open to us, and cannot be 
until we organise to assume it collectively. 

In our society these conditions are what we accept and are used to 
and adapt ourselves to, as to the weather or the constitution of our 
bodies. So they generally seem to us “as inevitable as the rising of the 
sun, or the cycle of the seasons, or similar obvious regularities of 
nature* \ and as much an unalterable element of “human nature” as 
having a head, two arms and two legs. Hence doctors of philosophy 
and of science are judged to advise us wisely when they say that any 
radical alterations are out of the question, just as were doctors of magic 
in more primitive communities. They exclude human relations from 
the sphere of human responsibility. 

The fact is that in these and other ways we are now, as men were 
originally in tribal society, in the grip of man-made conditions which 
men made for themselves independent of their will. These man-made 
conditions are to us like an external power for which no one can be 
held responsible. And this external power rules us with laws of its 
own, imposing on us our relations with one another, compelling us 
to do what we do and treat one another as we do, and determining 
the consequences of social actions irrespective of intentions or desires. 

To talk about increasing the scope for responsibility and decision 
in making and altering social institutions, and in the activity of in- 
dividuals within these institutions, therefore, leads us to the fundamen- 


342 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


tal question of how to organise “rational responsibility” for our 
institutions, and especially for the basic institutions of relations of 
production, so that rational decisions about them can be- made and 
carried out. Great as may be the scope for the pursuit of “personal 
and group interests” in existing capitalist society, and for “personal 
decisions” and “individual responsibility” in their pursuit, our society 
remains closed in the sense that there is no organisation through which 
rational responsibility can be accepted and exercised for conducting 
the basic business of social production for satisfying human needs. 

Part of Marx's great achievement was that he devoted to the 
conditions of “the closed society”, and to their historical development, 
an analytical investigation more penetrating than that now deemed 
convenient and sufficient by Dr. Popper. He studied how men have 
come to make for themselves these conditions which have always 
closed us in, and still do. And this led to the conclusion that mankind 
is at last in a position where they can be overcome. 

The issue posed by Marx was that of the organised working-class 
movement, in conscious pursuit of an interest scientifically defined 
and understood, taking control of political power so as to plan social 
production. That would mean that at last people would begin collec- 
tively to take responsibility for arranging the basic relations of property 
in means of production so as to get control over the whole process of 
social production and direct it to meet human needs. As Engels said in 
Socialism , Utopian and Scientific , “men’s own social organisation, which 
has hitherto stood in opposition to them as if arbitrarily decreed by 
nature and history, will then become the voluntary act of men them- 
selves”. And if we adopt Dr. Popper’s quite suggestive terminology, 
we shall conclude that this is the great step to be taken out of the 
“closed” into the “open” society. The production of the means of life 
is then controlled by collective decisions, in the making and carrying 
out of which individuals bear personal responsibility, as responsible 
members of the organisations that see to it. And the overcoming of 
want, of exploitation and of enmity, with the sharing and lightening of 
labour, brings to everyone far greater opportunities and choices for 
personal activity than heretofore, and therefore more personal responsi- 
bility and more freedom in personal decisions. 


4 


COMMUNISM 

I. THE RATIONALITY AND PRACTICALITY OF COMMUNISM 

I shall now return to the question of whether, to “plan as well as we can 
for security and freedom”, we have to “go into the unknown”. 

Marx quite clearly defined where we have to go in terms of commun- 
ism, explaining that the socialist organisation of social production 
which must immediately replace capitalism is only a transitional 
stage towards a communist society. His advice about the socialist 
planning of production and distribution was therefore based on the 
idea that this should be planned with the end in view of creating 
communism. The transition from socialism to communism is explained 
in the simplest terms by stating that it is the transition from a society 
ruled by the maxim “from each according to his ability, to each 
according to his work” to one ruled by the maxim “from each accord- 
ing to his ability, to each according to his need”. When by the rational 
planned development and use of techniques there is being produced an 
abundance of everthing people need, the communist maxim becomes 
the one to adopt. 

Dr. Popper’s objections to communism are based on saying that it 
is “utopian”. A communist society sounds attractive as Marx describes 
it but, says Dr. Popper, the thing is impossible. It is only a dream. It is 
the dream of returning to the primitive tribal condition of everyone 
working together and sharing — but with the whole human race 
engaged instead of only a few kinsmen, and with mechanised pro- 
duction to produce plenty instead of crude implements to eke out a 
bare living in the bush. If we try to realise such a dream, he'informs us, 
we are in for a rude awakening. For it would involve forcibly suppress- 
ing all that “pursuit of personal or group interests” which has now 
become the chief engagement of citizens of “the open society”. We 
would be back into “the closed society”, but under a tyranny much 
worse than the old tribal “taboos, laws and customs”. There would 
take place, “the most brutal and violent destruction of all that is 
human” at the hands of “the Inquisition, the Secret Police and a roman- 
ticised gangsterism” (i-OS. 200). 

Dr. Popper’s grounds for saying that the goal of communism is 


344 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


utopian are entirely political. He says that the concentration of political 
power required as a preliminary would necessarily be uncontrolled, 
and seeks to portray, in the customary language of anti-communist 
politics, the inevitable consequences of any such uncontrolled con- 
centration of political power in the hands of the working-class move- 
ment. I think I have already written enough in rebuttal of his deposi- 
tion that communist politics is the politics of violence and tyranny, 
suppressing all rights, all freedom, all democratic control, all indi- 
vidual responsibility and personal decision. He is mistaken in supposing 
that Marxism advocates or communism requires such politics. He is 
additionally mistaken in supposing that the argument as to whether or 
not communism is a practical goal is or could be primarily a political 
argument. Marx's reasons for putting forward the communist pro- 
gramme were economic. They were, in brief, that with socialised 
production carried on with techniques eventually capable of producing 
abundance of all we need, the form of social organisation eventually 
required will be one which permits everyone to contribute to social 
production to the best of his ability and derive from it the satisfaction of 
his needs. 

Dr. Popper blames Marx for holding that economics rules politics. 
But yet the problems which political policy has to solve are derived from 
the state of the economy. Marx worked out the politics based on 
recognising the economic facts of our time, the politics for instituting 
that control and that planning of social production which is required to 
make the fullest social use of it. He clearly recognised the economic 
fact that modern production techniques are capable of development to 
produce abundance to satisfy human needs. That being so, what is there 
utopian in proposing the social aim of actually producing abundance 
and satisfying needs out of it? The proposal is to engineer institutions 
through which we can work together to satisfy needs in the way we 
know well they can be satisfied, instead of institutions which leave us 
to “go into the unknown” and accept “personal responsibility” for the 
inconveniences which ensue when one does not know where one is 
going. 

The opinion that communism is nevertheless a utopia boils down to 
the opinion that the “pursuit of personal and group interests” which 
has predominated since the establishment of “the open society” 
precludes the practical possibility of our working together for the 
common benefit. It is a poor advertisement for “the open society” if 
that is so, and if we cannot accept “individual responsibility” and make 


COMMUNISM 


345 


“personal decisions” without mismanaging our economic affairs in the 
way they are mismanaged under capitalism. This opinion fails to take 
account of the issues of the class struggle under capitalism. Marx 
pointed out that so long as control is exercised by competing interest- 
groups, each bent on its own power and profit, it is indeed not only 
unlikely but impossible that production should be developed as it is 
capable of being developed to satisfy needs — but that the democratic 
class struggle and democratic control of power by working-class 
organisations, under scientific socialist political leadership, could 
manage it. 

The fact that the working class exists as a social force opposed to 
capitalism, and willy-nilly pursues a class struggle disruptive of capi- 
talism, is what makes the ending of capitalism and social advance to- 
wards communism a practical proposition in our society. For if no 
interest were interested in it, such an advance could not take place in a 
society where “pursuit of personal or group interests” predominates. 
The working-class interest is the class interest in capitalist society 
which demands the use of social production to meet social needs, 
whereas the other class interests interpose considerations of their own 
preservation against such a demand. Anyone who proposes to work for 
communism today must therefore join in with the working-class 
movement. 

But so far as the goal is concerned, and the contention that the 
foundation of a communist order of society is the known objective to 
be gained in order to establish security and freedom, the case for 
communism is based on considerations about technology, and the 
communist programme is a programme for making use of modern 
technology. To appreciate the case for communism, and to appreciate 
that the revolutionary movement which aims at communism is the one 
which knows how to solve the problems and realise the possibilities 
now presented by the economic development of the forces of pro- 
duction, it is only necessary to employ, quite disinterestedly, “what 
reason we may have”. 

2. SOCIAL IMPLICATIONS OF MODERN TECHNIQUES 

Marx based his conclusions on examining the techniques of the indus- 
trial revolution of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Two defini- 
tions which he gave are of especial importance. One is that of “an 
instrument of labour”, as “a tiling, or a complex of tilings, which the 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


346 

labourer interposes between himself and the subject of his labour, and 
which serves as the conductor of his activity” ( Capital , I, 7, 1). The other 
is the definition of “a machine”: “All fully developed machinery 
consists of three essentially different parts, the motor mechanism, the 
transmitting mechanism, and finally the tool or working machine . . . 
The machine proper is therefore a mechanism that, after being set in 
motion, performs with its tools the same operations that were formerly 
done by the workman with similar tools” ( Capital , I 15, 1). 

In the industrial revolution machinery replaced hand tools. And 
while the motive power for the simplest machines is supplied by human 
or animal muscle-power, once machinery began to be widely intro- 
duced in industry men began to look for other motive power to drive 
it — and discovered it in such inventions as the steam engine, the internal 
combustion engine and the generation of electricity. 

Marx observed that at first a manufactory contained a number of 
separate machines set side by side, as in a weaving factory or a sewing 
factory. But in various branches of industry there was soon built up “a 
real machinery system ... to take the place of these independent 
machines”. In this “the subject of labour goes through a connected 
series of detail processes, that are carried out by a chain of machines 
of various kinds, the one supplementing the other”. Finally, “as soon 
as a machine executes, without man’s help, all the movements requisite 
to elaborate the raw material, needing only attendance from him, we 
have an automatic system of machinery, and one that is susceptible of 
constant improvement in its details” (ibid). Marx concluded, in lan- 
guage perhaps slightly reminiscent of William Blake, that “an organised 
system of machines, in which motion is communicated by the trans- 
mitting mechanism from a central automation, is the most developed 
form of production by machinery. Here we have, in the place of the 
isolated machine, a mechanical monster whose body fills whole 
factories, and whose demon power, at first veiled under the slow and 
measured motions of liis giant limbs, at length breaks out into the fast 
and furious whirl of his countless working organs.” 

In the machine system the role of the individual worker becomes 
more and more reduced to that of “attendance” on the machine. He has 
lost the freedom of the independent craftsman, and his own life of 
personal decision and responsibility is lived only outside his working 
hours. Even the serf who was forced to toil from dawn to dusk for the 
whole of his life on the same piece of land was the owner and master of 
his own implements of labour and did his own job in his own way. But 


COMMUNISM 


347 

the worker who is employed to work in a machine system is forced to 
match his own motions to those of the machine whose servant he has 
become during his working hours. 

Meantime someone has to take responsibility for management and 
take decisions about production, and this function is separated from 
that of attendance on machines. The subjection of the worker to the 
machine, denial to the worker of all responsibility of management, and 
separation of management from labour have been inescapable conse- 
quences of machine production. 

When the machine system began, the responsibility of management 
was vested in the individual capitalist who purchased machines, hired 
labour to work with them as he directed, and sold the product with a 
view to realising a profit on his capital investment. Subsequently the 
means of production owned by individual capitalists were taken over 
(as Marx saw beginning and predicted would continue) by larger and 
larger companies. These are, of course, purely corporate individuals — 
not persons of flesh and blood, and born of women, but institutions 
which people set up over themselves to regulate the social activities of 
producing and distributing the means of life. These corporations own 
and control blocks of capital and^ invest it, thereby increasingly 
monopolising whole branches of production. 

As a result, individual responsibility for directing labour and mana- 
ging the disposal of products is separated from individual owners of 
means of production just as it is from individual workmen. It falls on 
those who hold controlling positions in the corporate capitalist insti- 
tutions, and those whom they appoint. The situation that results is one 
in which management of machine production remains distinct from 
and antagonistic to labour, and the aim of management remains that of 
realising the maximum profit for the corporate owner out of the sale 
of the product. But if the owner is a fleshless corporation, the men in 
control still receive the wherewithal to put on plenty of flesh. 

A further and immensely far-reaching consequence of the develop- 
ment of machine industry was noted by Marx. This is the development 
of the sciences. And in this development, as he noticed, a change takes 
place in the role of science in relation to industry. Initially, the sciences 
studied the processes — mechanical, physical and chemical — employed 
in industry, with a view to understanding them better and formulating 
their laws. Inventions were rather due to the ingenuity of men engaged 
in industry than introduced into industry by the creative intervention of 
specialised scientists. But this situation changes into one in which 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


348 

science becomes the pacemaker, the leading agency in the development 
of techniques, rather than an auxiliary. This change is also a change in 
the structure of institutions. From independent individuals interested in 
studying the constitution of nature and the laws of operation of natural 
forces, scientists become enrolled as members' and employees of great 
research institutions feeding know-how into social production, and 
these in turn are ever more closely linked with the great corporations 
which own the means of production and direct the processes of industry. 

Marx designated scientific research as itself one of the modern forces 
of production, and one that makes itself more and more into the leading 
revolutionising force. While others were regarding (and still regard) 
the sciences, in abstraction from their social function, in the light of a 
methodology for framing hypotheses which it is interesting to verify 
or falsify, Marx appreciated from the outset the revolutionising role of 
science in relation to social production. This led him to conclude that 
the further development of the social forces of production, begun 
under capitalism, would be such as to end the need for either arduous 
or mindless labour, end the subjection of the worker to the machine and 
the separation of the tasks of labour from managerial responsibilities, 
and finally achieve the planned social production of abundance to 
satisfy human needs, 'these consequences, as he saw clearly enough 
even though not able to specify the exact forms which technological 
development would take, must follow from science taking the leading 
place among the forces of production. They are incompatible with the 
survival of capitalist relations of production. 

The character of the scientific-technological revolution which has 
got under way in the second half of the twentieth century confirms 
Marx’s forecasts and conclusions in the nineteenth century. 

The principal feature of the contemporary technological revolution 
is the leading role of science in relation to industry. This accounts 
for the very rapid pace of technological progress today compared with 
anything experienced before throughout the whole history of mankind. 
Of course, though the change has been so marked during the past 
twenty years, this is a situation which has been developing for some 
time — for instance, radio technology and a lot of electrical technology, 
or again medical techniques, were introduced as direct results of 
scientific research. But now the long sequence of scientific discoveries 
has rather suddenly culminated in a situation where the dominant 
pattern is that of new techniques being fed into industry by science 
rather than being evolved in industry with science undertaking investi- 


COMMUNISM 


349 


gations attendant on them. This sudden change is dated, and recorded 
in quantitative terms, as a sharp and accelerating increase in the rate of 
introduction of technological innovations. 

The innovations now introduced can be classified under three 
headings. First, there is the introduction of new types of tools, for use 
both in production and in research — including not only extremely 
ingenious and adaptable implements and gadgets of one sort and 
another, but new agencies (lasars, for example). Second, there is the 
tapping of new power sources, namely nuclear energy. Third, there 
is the introduction of techniques of automation and computation. 

It is evident that, provided the forms of organisation and co-operation can 
be established through which it can be done , the combined use of these 
innovations would enable mankind as a whole to do a lot more than 
could be done hitherto, and to know a lot more. All these means are 
useful, moreover, not only for production but for research, which 
itself will contribute new means to production and to the activities of 
human beings — so that the prospect is not that of an advance followed 
by settling down at a new level, but of continuous sustained advance. 
Already, for example, people are building vehicles to take off into 
surrounding space and expect soon to make themselves at home on the 
moon. Possibly of greater practical consequence, new instrumentalities 
of research are penetrating the secrets of the constitution of living 
matter and of the formation of organisms on the earth. Evidently, 
there has already been created the possibility of a vastly increased 
production of things people need for far less expenditure of human 
labour-power and physical wear and tear of human bodies, which 
would bring to all individuals the material requisites, the time and the 
opportunities for indulgence in tree activities on their own responsi- 
bility and decision. The age-old condition of poverty of human 
resources is already ended which made it necessary for anyone, let alone 
the majority of the human race, to earn a mere pittance by the sweat of 
his brow, or to live in an environment not thoroughly reshaped by 
human agency to suit his needs and tastes, or to suffer the ravages of 
disease or premature old age. 

So far as the opening up of real possibilities is concerned, all this is 
what Marx predicted would happen; and it has happened. But to 
understand the problems of social reconstruction inherent in the pro- 
cess of realisation of these possibilities, we must look more closely at 
certain features of the contemporary technological revolution. 

This revolution is not only a further development of the design and 


350 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


use of machines, though that is included in it. It really is a revolution in 
technology in as much as it introduces into the process of social pro- 
duction something new to supersede machines, just as the machines of 
the industrial revolution introduced something new to supersede 
hand-labour. This gives us grounds to conclude that it requires as 
great, if not greater, changes in the relations of men in the social use of 
the new forces of production. To think otherwise is indeed to remain 
blind to the implications of the technological changes going on under 
our eyes. 

To appreciate how revolutionary the technological revolution is we 
must go back to definitions. The innovations comprise new or im- 
proved tools, new and greater sources of motive power, and techniques 
of automation. A machine, as we saw, consists of a motor transmitting 
motion to a tool or set of tools. Bearing this in mind, it is clear that a 
new element is added by the techniques of automation. These have been 
defined (for instance by Sir Leo Bagrit in his 1964 Reith lectures, The 
Age of Automation) as techniques of “communication, computation and 
control”. 

Of course, no social production of any sort is possible without 
employment of these three interrelated functions. In social production 
a number of people work to try to produce a product decided upon at 
the start of the operation. For this purpose there must be communication 
from one phase of the operation to another — so that, for example, a 
new job can be started when the preceding job is done, or when 
something goes wrong steps can be taken accordingly. There must be 
computation y so that the operations of the job can be fitted together. 
And there must be control sufficient to carry through all the motions 
required for the work from beginning to end. 

These functions have always been performed by human agency; and 
they are so performed in machine production, since machines do not 
include any apparatus to perform them for themselves, automatically 
throughout, without the need for human intervention. But the tech- 
niques of automation add these functions to the performance of the 
material structures which men design and build for purposes of social 
production. 

In automated production the motive force employed sets in motion a 
process of communication, computation and control guiding the 
motions of the tools to which the motion is transmitted. This is a 
system which replaces a machinery system, even of the most automatic 
kind, just as a machinery system replaced a gang of hand-labourers. 


COMMUNISM 


351 


An automated system contains a fourth component added to the 
machine. And just as the machine system frees the productive worker 
from having to transmit motion to the tool by his own bodily exertions 
and to guide it with his hand, so does the automated system free him 
from the burdens of ‘'attendance’ \ 

The very revolutionary character of the automated system, as com- 
pared with all previous material means men have constructed for the 
purposes of social production, is revealed by the fact that the relation- 
ship which has always been the basic one within the social forces of 
production, between men and their instruments of production, is 
changed. 

According to Marx’s definition, an instrument of labour is “a tiling or 
complex of things which the labourer interposes between himself and 
the subject of his labour as the conductor of his activity”. Marx stressed 
that the distinguishing feature of human actvity in social production is 
that men formulate a plan of what they want to do to the subject of 
their activity. Having formed a plan in their heads, men use instruments 
of labour for the purpose of altering the subject of labour in accordance 
with their plan. It is in this sense that instruments are interposed as 
conductors of human purposive activity. Men set themselves a task (or 
some men are set a task by others), and then use the instruments of 
labour to carry it out , as the conductors of the human activity of carrying 
out alterations of the environment corresponding to the tasks we set 
ourselves. It is in this way that men have used first very crude tools and 
subsequently elaborate machine systems as instruments of labour. But 
with a complete automated system we do not thus set ourselves a task 
and then use instruments of labour for our carrying out of the task. No, 
we set a task to the system which we have designed and built to perform such a 
task for us y and it carries it out for us. Automated systems are instruments of 
production designed to carry out the tasks we set them. And such 
“instruments of production” are different from the “instruments of 
labour” which were formerly the only known instruments of produc- 
tion. They supersede the instruments of labour the operative use of 
which entails a task set to the labourer, which the labourer must per- 
form by his own exertions, the expenditure of his labour-power. 

What we have to realise, therefore, is that the scientific-technological 
revolution now being begun by men is altering the part which men 
themselves have to play in the process of social production. Men have 
always been both designers and artificers of instruments of production 
and labourers who use them as instruments of labour. Now men’s part 


352 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


is to design, build and supervise the operations of instruments of 
production which can operate effectively without the intervention of 
men as labourers equipped with instruments of labour. 

3. THE COMMUNIST PROGRAMME 

Hitherto mankind has been split into two antagonistic parts in the 
production process. On the one hand there have been the people (the 
majority) who had to wear themselves out wielding the tools or attend- 
ing the machines. On the other hand there have been the owners and 
bosses who governed their fellow men and appropriated a large part 
of their labour. The communist programme follows from the fact that 
this is becoming an anchronism. For if the technological revolution is 
pushed on to embrace more and more of social production, there will 
be a new sort of work, consisting of people co-operating to design, 
build and supervise material systems to produce for them what they 
have agreed they want; and a new sort of management consisting of 
the co-operative arrangements people make to build these material 
systems and keep them in motion. The labourer who is set a task to 
perform with instruments of labour will become redundant, and the 
boss at whose behest the task is set will become redundant too. 

What therefore becomes necessary is for men to agree amongst 
themselves on the purpose to be served by production, and co-operate 
to design, build and supervise the instruments which will carry out our 
purpose. This purpose can only be the satisfaction of human needs. To 
achieve it, everyone must work to the best of his ability to help with 
the design and maintenance of the productive system. 

The guiding principle of a communist society thus turns out to be 
no unworldly ideal, but the statement of how human relations will 
have to be arranged to adapt to the uses of a very highly automated 
system of production. To build such a system is not a problem of 
building utopia, but a problem of engineering. 

If, then, we care to follow Dr. Popper in importing the same word, 
“engineering”, into the definition of problems of managing social 
institutions, we can conclude that the engineering involved in building 
a fully automated system of production sets engineering problems as 
regards social institutions, namely, to adapt these to the requirements of 
people getting on with production engineering and using the instru- 
ments of production. The problems of “social engineering” are 
formulated inadequately if we pose them only abstractly, as problems 


COMMUNISM 


353 


of changing institutions so as to allow people “security and freedom”. 
For what is necessary for this security and freedom? It is to adapt the 
social institutions to the system of material production. Dr. Popper and 
other objectors to communism have failed to notice the fundamental 
fact, that it is impossible to solve the problems of production engin- 
eering which will enable us to produce abundance for human needs 
without breaking up those institutions through which one class of 
men exploits the labour of another. For there is a formal contradiction 
between some men setting others to work on tasks of labour to pro- 
duce goods which they appropriate and sell for profit, and a production 
system in which the tasks of labour are transferred to the material 
instruments of production. 

The fact is, that a society in which full use is made of modern 
methods of production can only be a communist society. Conversely, 
the full use of the productive techniques which are now being evolved 
and introduced can never be achieved unless we succeed in changing 
our relations of production into communist relations, unless classes 
are abolished and all men co-operate on the communist principle “from 
each according to his ability, to each according to his need”. Hence, on 
the one hand, the development of the full economic potential of produc- 
tive techniques now depends on the political struggle to overcome the 
capitalist rule which upholds capitalist relations of production. We shall 
never succeed in carrying those techniques forward unless we take up 
and win the political struggle for communism, with all its difficulties 
and dangers. On the other hand, the economic fact that the greed for 
capitalist profit and the competition of capitalism with socialism, as 
well as of rival blocks of capital with one another, drives capitalist 
managements forward to improve productive techniques will face the 
masses of people more and more urgently with the necessity of political 
action to defend themselves from the consequences of capitalist free 
enterprise. 

That communism is the social form necessary for the full use of 
modern techniques does not imply that communism will be achieved 
simply as the result of modern techniques being introduced. Far from 
it, for communism can come, if it does come, only as a result of pro- 
longed political struggles. And while the introduction of new tech- 
niques may stimulate and aid that struggle, at the same time lack of 
resolution and defeat in the struggle may inhibit and in the end entirely 
prevent the introduction and full use of techniques. The point is that 
the goal of communism, and the ideas we can already project of how a 


354 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


communist society would be practically arranged, are not dreamed up 
as ideals of utopia but are strictly deducible from the actual character 
of technological progress and the requirements for continuing it. A 
communist society is not utopia, but one in which relations of produc- 
tion and methods of distributing the social product have become 
adapted to the productive forces created by the contemporary scientific 
and technological revolution. 

We can proceed to examine in more detail consequences of an 
advanced technology, which further define the character of a com- 
munist society (which is nothing but a society employing such tech- 
nology) and differentiate it from earlier modes of production. 

Products will no longer be produced as commodities for exchange. 
For the production complexes from which different products issue 
cannot exchange these products as men do, as values embodying 
labour, but must rather be programmed to put them into distribution 
according to a plan. And this plan of supply of needs will be computed 
like everything else in the production process in accordance with the 
purpose for which men have designed the production process and set 
it in motion. Commodity-production will therefore be entirely 
superseded. The mode of production in which men or groups of men 
produced goods by their labour and exchanged the products of labour 
will be superseded by a mode of production in which the products are 
distributed amongst men according to their needs. One rather striking 
consequence is, of course, that there will be no such thing as money, as 
the measure of value and medium of exchange. 

Advanced technology likewise supersedes the division of labour 
amongst human beings which every invention of new instruments of 
labour has hitherto entailed — and of which commodity production and 
private property in means of production were consequences. New 
instruments of labour mean new jobs, and since the instrument is 
specially constructed for the job so must the labourer specialise in 
the use of that instrument. The multiplication of instruments of labour 
gives rise to the division of labour amongst the human beings who make 
and use them. In the fully automated system, on the other hand, the 
division of detailed and specialised functions in the operations of 
social production is transferred in its entirety from human beings to the 
material instruments of production, the various parts of which each 
specialises in its particular job without requiring any man to specialise 
in the same way. As for men, one man will not be required to specialise 
in turning a screw or tightening a bolt, another in adding up figures and 


COMMUNISM 


355 


another in the work of overall management of a production complex, 
but all will share the common human function of being designers, 
masters and beneficiaries of the instruments of social production. This 
does not mean, of course, that all will have to do the same things or 
be exactly like each other. On the contrary, the differentiation of 
human abilities, pursuits and enjoyments is not the same thing as 
division of labour in social production, and its condition is that 
individuals should be freed from the stultifying effects of the division 
oflabour. 

Ending the division of labour implies two specially important 
consequences, on which Marx laid considerable emphasis. One is the 
abolition of the division between town and countryside. This does not 
mean that all land will be covered with streets and buildings — though 
with new techniques of food production it may well happen that 
agriculture as we know it will disappear and the earth be turned into a 
sort of park (those who find it tame will perhaps go mountaineering on 
Mars or swimming in a sea of ammonia on Jupiter). It implies that the 
division between rural communities labouring on producing food- 
stuffs and raw materials, and urban ones consuming their produce, with 
the superior amenities concentrated in the latter, will be ended. This 
raises an issue among the most pressing we face in the contemporary 
world. It means ending the division between “underdeveloped” and 
“developed” nations, where the former are kept down as suppliers of 
food and raw materials to the latter. It means raising the productivity 
and welfare of all human groups to a common level. It also implies, as 
has often been pointed out lately, instituting rational measures of 
population control. 

The other consequence Marx stressed is the abolition of the division 
between mental and manual labour. Once again, this does not mean 
that there will be no difference between mental and manual skills — for 
obviously this difference is inherent in the circumstance that people 
have brains and hands, and no doubt some people will always take 
more delight in the one than in the other. For example, there will no 
doubt always be a difference between, say, people who especially like 
doing higher mathematics and use their hands mostly to scribble 
symbols on bits of paper, and people who especially like painting 
pictures or making sculptures and use use their brains to guide their 
hands in producing the effects they want — though perhaps the latter 
will not remain ignorant of the uses of the calculus and the former be 
well capable of doing jobs about the house. At the risk of labouring 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


356 

the point, I repeat that such differences in individual pursuits and skills 
are not the same thing as division of labour as it has been forced on 
people hitherto by the development of the forces of production. What 
the abolition of the division of mental and manual labour means is the 
abolition of the division between people who act as managers and 
others whom they manage, and of the division between the common 
herd who labour with their hands and are educated for not much else, 
and the elite who are educated to other pursuits. 

Finally, all these changes imply what Marx and Engels described as 

“the withering away of the state”. In Engels* words, “the government 

of persons is replaced by the administration of things, and by the 

conduct of processes of production” ( Socialism , Utopian and Scientific y 

Chapter 3). Managing the general affairs of society will no longer 

entail any exercise of coercion, to force one set of people to perform a 

task of labour under the orders of another, or more generally to force 

one set of people to compromise or subordinate their interests in what 

they obtain from social production in deference to the interests of 

another. Hence no “public force** will be required to exercise and 

enforce its authority over individuals and, as Engels said in The 

Origin of the Family , Private Property and the State (Chapter 9), the 

“whole state machinery** will be put “where it will then belong — into 

the museum of antiquities, next to the spinning-wheel and the bronze 
>> 

axe . 

Naturally, there will still be social management. It will be a co- 
operative management, in which everyone has a say or vote, and in 
which what is set in train will be done in the light of thorough 
computation of requirements and consequences, and not blindly as at 
present, according to the will of one interest against another. The 
concurrence of individuals in what is decided will be secured by educa- 
tion, habit and argument, by each recognising his responsibility as a 
member of society, and without holding a big stick over anyone or 
depriving anyone of his opportunities for cultivating his individual 
bent. This means, incidentally, that individual responsibility will indeed 
become the general rule of an open society. Not only will the social 
organisation grant to individuals responsibility rather than making 
them do whatever they are told, but this individual responsibility will 
be the main thing on which the whole co-operative social organisation 
depends. 

The idea that communism is a mere utopia is attributable to the fact 
that for a very long time there were imaginative thinkers who dreamed 


COMMUNISM 


357 


of a communist society although there existed no practical possibility 
of realising it. Conscious of the irrationality and brutality of people 
oppressing and exploiting one another instead of co-operating for the 
common welfare, they dreamed of a society in which all would 
co-operate to produce social wealth, and wealth would be owned in 
common and shared out according to individual needs. These imagin- 
ings have been rightly regarded as mere utopias because there was no 
technological basis in prospect for the communist organisation of 
society, and so nothing could be done to organise for it politically. 
Communism was not a practical proposition, only an impractical 
ideal. But in modem conditions it has become not only practically 
possible but necessary . It is a practical possibility because we know how 
to set about building the technological basis, and know what political 
moves to make to start changing social institutions in the communist 
direction. And it is necessary because unless we start moving towards 
communism we shall be hindered from developing and using modem 
technology. 

But even so, many remain of opinion that communism is something 
to be realised, if realised at all, so far in the future that it is unpractical 
to start seriously organising for it at present. One reason for this opinion 
is to be found in the contrast between the selfish modes of behaviour at 
present in vogue and the socially responsible behaviour which would 
have to become universal if a communist society was ever to work. 
It is thought that if “human nature” is to change so much it will take a 
very long time to change, and meantime we had best accept unchang- 
ing human nature for what it is and always has been. 

These opinions, which those who hold them regard as realistic 
facing of facts, are really based on nothing but a refusal to face facts. 

As regards “human nature”, it may be stated at once that we posit no 
such extraordinary change as is imagined. We do not suggest that 
people must change from caring only for themselves to caring for 
others, for in fact most people have always cared for both. We are only 
of opinion that if there is interesting work to be done people will like 
doing it and want to do it if they get the chance; and that if needs can 
be satisfied without people having to compete with one another to 
get their satisfactions they will not go out of their way to grab things 
from each other. 

It is not Communists who ignore the facts of human nature, but 
sceptics about communism who ignore the fact of the very rapid pace of the 
contemporary scientific-technological revolution . This fact demands that at 


358 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


our peril we do something now to cope with its consequences. The 
need for organisation for that purpose is urgent. And in face of this 
urgency, the bungling and complacency of politicians and business 
managers as they practise 4 ‘social engineering” in the capitalist world 
is alarming. 

If technology could be developed and put straight into full use 
without check, it would probably not be unrealistic to say that a con- 
dition of world communism could be established within fifty years. 
Allowing for plenty of time for necessary social readjustments, it 
would perhaps be more realistic to put the period of change-over at, 
say, a hundred and fifty years — which is not long on the scale of histori- 
cal change, though occupying the energies of several generations. So 
political organisation to carry through these readjustments is not 
utopian politics oriented to a far-distant ideal goal, but the practical 
politics of the century we Hue in. The fact we have to face is not that 
communism is such a long-term goal as not to be worth bothering 
about at present, but that the actual and accelerating rate of technologi- 
cal change is already so impetuous that we will face the most serious 
social consequences if we do not commence the practical organisation 
of communism. 

Technological change cannot be halted without (as Dr. Popper so 
eloquently puts it) destroying our civilisation. So our civilisation must 
be adapted to technological change. The technological revolution will 
within a few decades render most of the old equipment, the current 
layout of services, and the current ways of training, directing and 
deploying labour completely obsolete. Their retention will not stop the 
advance of technology, but it will inevitably cause greater and greater 
difficulty and conflict in the management of social production and 
distribution. Increasing mismanagement is the prospect if the bosses of 
corporations competing for private profit try to manage in their own 
way an economy which requires integration in a single plan of social 
production. If it is left to them we are in for worse and worse conflicts 
as it becomes more and more evident to the masses of working people 
that their affairs are being mismanaged. Worse still, there will inevit- 
ably be continuous international conflict as people in the “under- 
developed” countries grow more and more intolerant of the contrast 
between their poverty and the affluence and greed of those who, 
pretending to aid them, forcibly intervene in their affairs to hold them 
down. What is desperately urgent is to establish right away that measure 
of democratic control by informed working-class organisations which 


COMMUNISM 


359 


can begin the planning of production in the industrially developed 
countries and offer real aid to the underdeveloped. 

Nearly everyone recognises that the present is a time of transition. 
The claim of Marxism is to have demonstrated scientifically where 
we are heading, and to have set out the real problems of the transition. 
The communist programme is the imaginative forecast of the road 
we must take, not because it is our inexorable fate, but because the 
means we are creating to produce our needs demand it. The modern 
working-class movement, able on the basis of scientific information to 
see the road clearly in imagination so as to take it in practice, can by its 
mass democratic organisation sweep out of office the fumbling admini- 
strators of the old order, and bring into actual existence the rational 
and open society which was only a dream for so many who have 
gone before. 


5 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 

I. DEMOCRATIC SOCIALIST PLANNING 

If we discount his more phrenetic utterances about returning to 
tribalism and thence “to the beasts”, Dr. Popper’s chief misgivings 
about the communist programme arise over two points : the dangers 
inherent in economic planning and in attempting to control thoughts. 
But on these contentious points, too, his arguments can scarcely pass 
muster as “rational”. 

He objects to “planning on a very large scale”, such as Communists 
advocate, because it “must cause considerable inconvenience to many 
people” (PH. 89). If this were a rational argument he must say why it 
must ; but he does not, and merely asserts it with all the perseverance of a 
Conservative backbencher. 

He then goes on to say that to get a plan operated the planner “must 
suppress unreasonable objections” — which is true enough. “But with 
them he must invariably suppress reasonable criticism too.” In the 
name of reason, why should one invariably have to overrule reasonable 
criticism whenever unreasonable objections are overruled? It is only by 
entering into critical discussion, and making it as reasonable as one can, 
that it is possible to decide which objections are in fact unreasonable. 
Dr. Popper lays it down that the planner can never allow any dis- 
cussion at all about the plan. In that case it is only too probable that he 
will “cause considerable inconvenience to many people” and his plan 
will come to grief. But those who seek to operate “planning on a very 
large scale” will, if they know their business, do exactly what Dr. 
Popper says they cannot do (because he says only “social engineers” 
who operate planning on a very small scale can do it) : they will make it 
their business “to look out for mistakes, to find them, to bring them 
into the open, to analyse them, and to learn from them” (PH. 88). And 
to this end they will encourage “reasonable criticism” in every way 
they can. 

Dr. Popper does, it is true, attempt to assign a reason why learning 
from mistakes is possible only in small-scale or “piecemeal” planning, 
and not in “holistic” planning “on a very large scale”. He says there is 
a “technical” reason: “Since so much is done at a time, it is impossible 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


361 

to say which particular measure is responsible for any of the results" 
(PH. 88-9). This “technical" reason is on a par with saying that pro- 
ductive apparatus must never be let grow too large and complicated, 
for if so it will become impossible to fmd the cause of a breakdown. 
Dr. Popper should certainly have known better than that, for it is the 
reasoning of a man unacquainted with scientific technology. Just as 
very large-scale production engineering has to master the intricacies of 
how the many different parts of an apparatus fit together in their 
operations to produce the desired results, so must competent planners 
master the intricacies of how the many different things done at a time 
fit together to produce results. Indeed, the science of planning as it is 
being successfully developed now in socialist countries is concerned 
with precisely that problem. The result is not “considerable incon- 
venience" but lightening of labour and increase of articles of consump- 
tion. 

From these very insufficient objections to “planning on a very large 
scale" Dr. Popper deduces what he takes to be the worst and most fatal 
consequences of indulgence in such planning. For this purpose he 
introduces a premise with which one can hardly disagree. It is “im- 
possible", he says, “to centralise all that knowledge which is dis- 
tributed over many individual minds" (PH. 89-90). So what follows? 
The “holistic planner", who will not listen to anyone else’s advice and 
supresses all criticism, reasonable as well as unreasonable, denies him- 
self access to accumulated knowledge. Therefore “he must try to 
simplify his problems". And refusing to let other people express 
themselves, he must take energetic steps to shut them up and “to 
control and stereotype interests and beliefs by education and propa- 
ganda. But this attempt to exercise power over minds must destroy the 
last possibility of finding out what people really think, for it is clearly 
incompatible with the free expression of thought, especially of critical 
thought. Ultimately, it must destroy knowledge" (PH. 90). So “plan- 
ning on a very large scale" leads first to tyrannical measures of thought- 
control and suppression of all freedom of thought, and then to the 
destruction of all the human knowledge on which successful manage- 
ment must rely. 

A less reasonable argument than this would be hard to put together. 
For since it is plainly impossible for a single “holistic planner" to 
know everything relevant to the operation of a successful plan, 
planning demands the widest consultation amongst all those people in 
whose minds relevant knowledge resides. A person responsible for 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


362 

planning will therefore not “simplify his problems” by shutting 
everyone else up, but will do his utmost to draw in the maximum 
number of people to help. The idea that planning on a very large scale 
should ever be done by a single “holistic planner”, or plans be made up 
and dictated without consultation by an institute of “centralised 
power”, is merely one of Dr. Popper’s fantasies, with the aid of which he 
works himself up into a state of alarm and indignation about com- 
munism. It is obvious that large-scale planning demands a very far- 
flung apparatus of consultation at all levels, between economists, 
administrators, scientists, technicians, works managers and ordinary 
workers. 

The fact that mistakes of over-centralisation were made in planning 
in the Soviet Union is no excuse for Dr. Popper’s nonsense, even 
though he did not know at the time he was writing that these mistakes 
would soon be remedied. Right from the start in the Soviet Union 
planning was done on the basis of wide and elaborate consultation. 
This was the basis for a real science of planning being instituted there, 
and for earlier mistakes being later corrected. 

But even though Dr. Popper’s charges against planning must be 
ruled out of court (except, indeed, in the Wonderland court of his own 
book, where he is not only the prosecutor but the judge and jury too) 
there are real problems connected with planning, and related problems 
connected with the control of thoughts, which are worthy of attention. 

Planning on a very large scale has become necessary because of the 
socialised character of modern industrial production. The fact is that 
Marxists are not doctrinaire busybodies who want to make everyone 
do as we say instead of letting them do as they please. We advocate 
planning because it is necessary, as a condition for managing modem 
production to meet human needs. But how can planning be made 
effective and at the same time not encroach on democratic rights and 
the freedom of the individual? 

The reason why planning on a large scale has become necessary for 
the use of modern forces of production can be appreciated by com- 
paring modem conditions of production with those that have gone 
before. 

In primitive conditions of subsistence economy, for example, 
questions of planning hardly arose. People produced what they could 
with their primitive equipment and consumed it as they went along. 
Planning only came in by way of trying to preserve as much stock as 
possible, so as to have a chance of survival when the next season came 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


363 

round. Again, there could not be much planning in the commodity 
production of peasants and handicraftsmen, since these people could 
only go to the market and sell their product for whatever price was 
offered. Individual merchants planned to buy cheap and sell dear, but 
there could be no overall planning. Feudal lords planned busily but 
their plans took the form of conspiracies to grab each other’s lands and 
possessions. When capitalist production appeared on the scene, large 
numbers of workers were collected together and set to work in indus- 
trial enterprises, and within these enterprises a great deal of planning 
was at once required — aimed at keeping production going, increasing 
it and increasing the rate of exploitation. The product was all taken to 
the market, just as with pre-capitalist commodity production. And it 
was from this circumstance that the need for some kind of overall 
planning of production and distribution became apparent. As Engels 
pointed out in Socialism , Utopian and Scientific , a contradiction now 
became manifest between the planning of production in each indi- 
vidual enterprise and the anarchy of production within the sphere of 
production and distribution as a whole. 

The necessity for overall planning of modern production arises from 
two related conditions, both of which Marx analysed in the three 
volumes of Capital First, production is now divided into two great 
departments, producing respectively means of production and goods 
for consumption. Unless due proportions (which are calculable 
mathematically) are maintained between the production of these 
two departments, production as a whole must suffer dislocations and 
interruptions. For instance, the production of consumer goods cannot 
be maintained or increased unless sufficient means of production are 
produced for the purpose. And again, if the effective demand for 
consumer goods is not sufficient to use up all the means of production 
that are being produced, then production in the department producing 
means of production will be interrupted because its products are not 
for the time being wanted. Therefore, secondly, production will suffer 
interruptions unless arrangements are also made so that the members of 
society are actually able to buy and consume all the consumer goods 
that are produced. Clearly, neither of these necessary conditions can 
be satisfied if every independent enterprise is left to plan its own pro- 
duction entirely at the will of its own management. There must be 
some sort of overall economic plan. 

Throughout that phase of capitalist production known as laissez 
faire this need for overall planning was denied by capitalist manage- 


364 TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 

ments. Their idea (worked out for them by professional economists) 
was that the conditions of the market would automatically bring about 
the necessary adjustments. For instance, if relatively too much or too 
little of something was being produced, the market conditions would 
automatically cause capital in search of profit to flow from one branch 
of production to another. This sort of adjustment proved in practice 
extremely painful and injurious, and took place only through a 
series of economic crises with wastage of productive equipment and 
unemployment. Today, when whole branches of production have 
come to be monopolised by very big capitalist corporations which plan 
their own production and marketing arrangements in a big way, the 
corporation managements have come to recognise the need for at 
least a certain amount of overall economic planning (and professional 
economists have duly criticised old-fashioned economic theories and 
worked out new ones). At the same time, the corporations consider 
that they can do whatever is necessary themselves, with the aid of the 
state over which they exercise so considerable a measure of control. 

Recent experience is making plain the limitations of monopoly- 
capitalist economic planning. This so-called “indicative planning” is 
not so much planning as forecasting. On the basis of data about past 
and present resources forecasts are made of what would have to be 
produced in all the main branches of production, and how it would 
have to be marketed, in order to bring about a given rate of increase of 
total production. Government then takes various measures by way of 
offering incentives such as credits and tax relief to encourage the enter- 
prises concerned to behave according to the forecast, and at the same 
time to gear nationalised industries and services to it. But there is no 
overall control to ensure that what is forecasted is done. Experience 
to date has shown that in no case are the forecasts of a capitalist national 
plan ever realised. Something always goes wrong — even though not 
always so rapidly as was the case with the national plan announced in 
1966 by the Labour Government in Britain, which collapsed within a 
few months. 

It might be thought, incidentally, from his strictures about “planning 
on a large scale”, that Dr. Popper would disapprove of all such planning 
as altogether too “holistic”. However, he professes to disapprove of 
laissez faire and to approve of capitalist overall planning on the good 
grounds that it is still “piecemeal social engineering” and contains so 
little of the element of compulsion . But it is in these very qualities which 
meet with his approval that its limitations show themselves. In the 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


365 

fierce market competition of so many profit-seeking enterprises it is 
not possible for them all to keep to plan, even if their managements 
intended it, and the same types of maladjustment as have always 
shown up in capitalist production continue to take place. Meantime 
the organised workers who demand that conditions of work, wages 
and social services shall be improved are subjected to a restraint and 
compulsion not applied to their employers, on the grounds that their 
demands will divert resources from production to consumption, 
render industries uncompetitive especially on export markets and 
prevent the national economy from paying its way. If capitalist 
planning increases employment it increases the incidence of industrial 
disputes, so that some begin to think a dose of planned unemployment 
would be advisable as a means of bringing industrial workers to 
heel. 

By one of those twists of the meaning of words which are the 
stock-in-trade of capitalist apologetics, capitalist planning has been 
called “democratic”. As well as never working, it suffers from the 
drawback of being undemocratic. For it is most emphatically not 
under democratic control. The job of drawing up the plan is done by 
experts of the corporations and the government, and its operation is 
left to the managements of the corporations and nationalised industries, 
without any exercise of democratic control apart from drawing in a few 
trade union officials. To say that this represents a measure of demo- 
cratic control over the managements of corporations, or that it is demo- 
cratic because permanent civil servants constitute key personnel, is to 
accept a very meagre and remote form of popular control as sufficient 
to qualify as “democracy”. Many advocates of capitalist planning (for 
example, Professor Galbraith in his B.B.C. Reith lectures of 1966) now 
recognise this fact, and are saying that “democratic planning” is 
nonsense because planning is an expert business and experts should be 
controlled only by their fellow experts. Others, however, continue to 
maintain that capitalist planning is democratic because economic 
decisions remain voluntary, and the plan only offers guidance to the 
corporations and not instructions; it is thought democratic to allow 
individual decision of this voluntary kind and undemocratic to use 
compulsion. But why it is democratic to allow decisions affecting the 
livelihood of millions to be taken by a handful of managers exempt 
from democratic control, and undemocratic to ensure that what is 
planned for the public welfare is actually done, are two questions never 
answered by the champions of capitalist democracy. 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


366 

The need for socialist planning is the need for planning which in- 
cludes provisions to ensure the carrying out of plans, and which 
operates under democratic control. These things are connected. 
Measures to secure the democratisation of economic decisions are at 
the same time measures to ensure that the decisions are well planned 
and are carried out. 

The abstract definition of “socialism” as “public ownership of the 
means of production and exchange” requires completion by defining 
the object of public ownership as bringing the management of social 
production under the control of democratic organisations and planning it 
for the satisfaction of human needs. On the other hand, the fear of socialist 
planning is the fear that if ownership of all major enterprises is taken 
over by the state, the state will dictate a plan to the nation and arbi- 
trarily compel everyone to accept it and work for it, so that there will 
be even less democratic control than is the case under capitalist private 
ownership. 

The spectacle of Soviet people not only bearing up under the rigours 
of socialist planning, but holding discussions to improve its methods and 
doing very well for themselves, has led many who expressed these fears 
to admit it has not turned out so badly as they expected. Some now 
try to account for this by saying there is not after all much difference 
between having production managed by private corporations and 
having it managed by state trusts. Such an assurance is calculated to 
have a calming effect on those who believe we must at all costs hold 
out in a last-ditch struggle against socialist planning, and at the same 
time supplies a new argument against socialists who advocate a struggle 
to advance from capitalism to socialism. For it is argued that if capitalism 
now equals management by large corporations it amounts to very 
much the same thing as socialism, which equals management by large 
state trusts. 

These points were urged strongly by Professor Galbraith in his 
Reith Lectures. He said that the methods adopted by state trusts to 
plan production in the Soviet Union and by corporations to plan 
production in other industrial countries are becoming more and more 
alike. It is not true, however. The methods of planning production in 
the Soviet Union differ from those in capitalist countries in at least 
two important respects. First, the plan is decided upon on the basis of very 
wide consultation amongst democratic organisations , and the managements 
responsible at all levels have to operate within the framework of democratically 
decided objectives . Second, there is democratic control over the carrying out of 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


367 


the plan , to ensure that measures are taken to carry it out. As a result, 
the objective of planning in the Soviet Union is the supply of what 
people need and its delivery to its destination. And what is planned is 
actually achieved. The basis of socialist planning is democratic control 
by popular organisation over the production and distribution of what 
people need, and “public ownership” is the form within which this 
democratic control is effected. 

Socialist planning for social welfare requires the building of a very 
elaborate institutional framework within which the plan is formulated 
and carried out. This is, of course, something entirely unlike Dr. 
Popper’s “brave new world” fantasy of a single “holistic planner” 
issuing orders. There are required institutions of research and teaching, 
institutions of economic science, working out the theory of planning 
as an “exact science” employing mathematical techniques. There are 
required interlocked institutions for the central and regional formula- 
tion of plans, closely tied up with instituted consultation with public 
organisations, trade unions, works managements and so on. And insti- 
tutions are required to supervise and check up on the carrying out of 
plans, tied up with the production institutions (factories, farms, rail- 
ways, local government services, and so on) which carry out the plan. 
When such an institutional framework is built for planning, as it has 
been in the Soviet Union, it becomes evident that the idea that expert 
management is incompatible with democratic control is only one of 
the latest illusions of capitalist ideology. For in this framework are 
combined, on the one hand expertise, the making of economic 
planning into an expert business employing highly trained technicians, 
and on the other hand democratic control. 

These considerations show what has to be done to progress from 
capitalist to socialist institutions in the advanced industrial countries. 
There can be no question of smashing up all the institutions, as Dr. 
Popper imagines would be done by a revolution which transfers 
political power to the working class. There already exists in the insti- 
tutions of research and technology, in the managerial apparatus of the 
great corporations, and in the organisations of nationalised industries 
and municipal and social services the basis of the apparatus of socialist 
planning. The great step that has to be taken is that of the institution oj 
democratic control by popular organisation , which is lacking at present. To 
“raise the proletariat to the position of ruling class” is, exactly as The 
Communist Manifesto said, “to win the battle of democracy”. 


368 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


2. FROM SOCIALISM TO COMMUNISM 

A major part of socialist planning must always be concerned, not 
directly with the production of consumer goods and services, but with 
the production of means of production. And where these are insuffi- 
cient that department of production must take high priority if later on 
a greater part of consumers' needs are to be satisfied. The controlling 
aim is to plan the increase of production so as to meet all individual 
needs from it. This controlling aim implies that all socialist planning is 
planning alomg the road to communism , when such absolute abundance 
will be produced that “to each according to his need” will become the 
maxim governing the social organisation. 

This, of course, is why Marxist parties generally call themselves 
“Communist Parties”. Communism is the controlling aim of all their 
politics. And, incidentally, it demonstrates another big difference, and 
perhaps the biggest difference of all, between socialist democratic 
planning and the planning which already goes on in capitalist countries. 
The latter has certainly no aim of advancing towards communism, 
but presupposes the retention of social relations entirely incompatible 
with it, and is therefore likely to get into the worse confusion the 
higher the level of technological advance. At present the name “Com- 
munist” is not widely understood; but it will have to be made better 
understood if we are to cope with the problems which technology is 
setting. 

Marx described socialism, in the Critique of the Gotha Programme , as 
“the first phase of communist society”. It is this because already, when 
means of production are taken into social ownership and socialist 
planning is instituted, production ceases to be controlled by the profit 
obtainable by private owners from selling the products, and begins to 
be planned instead for the satisfaction of human needs. Communism is 
the organisation of social production to satisfy human needs. In its 
first imperfect or socialist phase production is not yet sufficient to 
satisfy all needs, and a fully communist society emerges only when this 
limitation has been overcome. 

At the same time, socialism can be described as a transition phase 
between capitalism and communism, because when capitalist owner- 
ship and control is first abolished many conditions remain, carried 
over from capitalism, which will also have to be abolished before 
communism is fully instituted. As Marx put it, “what we have to deal 
with here is a communist society, not as if it had developed on a basis 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


369 

of its own , but on the contrary as it emerges from capitalist society , which 
is thus in every respect tainted economically, morally and intellectually 
with the hereditary diseases of the old society from whose womb it is 
emerging . . . these deficiencies are unavoidable in the first phase of 
communist society when it is just emerging after prolonged birthpangs 
from capitalist society.” 

The chief of “these unavoidable deficiencies” is the retention of the 
wages system. People enter into agreements with employing organisa- 
tions (state trusts and the like) to work for so many hours for so much 
pay. What they receive to satisfy their needs depends therefore chiefly 
on their work. So far as the worker is concerned, he gets paid for his 
work, and receives as much as he can earn by enhancing his skills, 
finding jobs and working diligently— just as in capitalist society. The 
retention of the wages system is a social necessity because, so long as 
the social product is not yet sufficient to satisfy all needs as of right, the 
distribution of the social product cannot but be controlled by the socialist 
principle “from each according to his ability, to each according to his 
work”. 

Of course, this principle is never applied with full consistency and 
rigour. That would mean that children, old people and the sick would 
all have to be maintained out of individual earnings and savings; 
wheareas socialist governments always do their best to apply the 
communist principle by doing all that can be done to meet their needs 
out of public funds. And numerous other social services are provided, 
of which the enjoyment does not depend on earnings and the benefits 
supplement earnings. Indeed, a good deal on these lines is already done 
under capitalism, where social necessity reinforced by working-class 
demands already compels the ruling class to concur with the intro- 
duction of these first instalments of communism. Capitalists have, how- 
ever, always been grudging of social services, which they think both cost 
too much and sap the moral fibre of the recipients. They administer 
them so far as possible on a contributory insurance basis and make the 
wage-earners pay as much as possible of the cost. In a socialist society, 
on the other hand, social services are continually expanded and it is not 
thought desirable to run any of them as an insurance business. 

The wages system, reinforced by social services, is, then, and must 
be carried over from capitalism to socialism. With it there are inevitably 
carried over many old habits and ways of thinking — habits of grabbing 
whatever one can for oneself at the expense of others, of caring pri- 
marily for one’s livelihood and letting others look after their own if 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


370 

they can, and ways of thinking which go with these habits. Such 
phenomena of individual consciousness would in any case be likely to 
persist through inertia, since it always takes a long time for new modes 
of consciousness to spread amongst all individuals. But they are en- 
couraged by the retention of the wages system. It is therefore not 
surprising, though disturbing, to find that in a socialist society many of 
the most hateful phenomena of capitalism persist, including ambitious 
people climbing up over the backs of their fellows, people in jobs 
commanding status despising those below them and expecting defer- 
ence from them, and so on. A good Communist cannot lose confidence 
in the advance of humanity towards communism because of this, for 
it is only to be expected. But because it is only to be expected, he will 
not therefore take up an attitude of accepting and concurring in it, 
and still less behave like that himself. 

At the same time, the wages system in socialist society differs 
fundamentally from that under capitalism. The chief difference does not 
show itself on the surface, in the make-up of the wages packet or in the 
procedure of passing it from the wages-clerk to the wage-earner, but 
only in the overall mode of development of social production. It 
consists in the fact that wages are no longer the price paid by the em- 
ployer for the purchase of the worker’s labour-power, but are the 
worker’s entitlement, paid over to him in the form of money from the 
employing organisation, to receive so much in value out of the total 
social product in proportion to the work he has contributed. Labour- 
power is no longer bought and sold. And its value, that is to say, the 
value of the goods and services required to maintain fitness for work, no 
longer enters into the determination of wages. For labour-power is no 
longer a commodity, and wages no longer the price of that commodity. 
Exploitation, in the technical sense of the worker contributing unpaid 
labour-time as surplus value to the employer, has been ended. 

It may be objected that such theoretical considerations are meaning- 
less in human terms, since the worker will feel just as much exploited 
so long as he has to work too hard and gets too little for it. They are far 
from meaningless; for what they mean is that under socialism the 
amount the worker receives is not determined by a bargain with an 
employer who buys his labour-power at so much an hour, but by a 
calculation of how much of the social product is currently available 
to distribute as goods and services for consumption. As the social 
product increases, so must the workers’ welfare improve. The settle- 
ment of wages is no longer an issue of class struggle. Quite literally, 


THE TRANSITION TO COMMUNISM 


371 


the workers are working for themselves, not for the profit af an 
employer. 

It is sometimes objected too that in socialist society exploitation 
continues, just as under capitalism, because the workers by their labour 
contribute to the upkeep of a large “class of officials and bureaucrats”. 
These are described as exploiters who direct the workers* labour and 
appropriate the surplus value just as capitalist exploiters do. While it is 
true that any system of management permits individual peculation 
unless something is done to stop it, it is nevertheless absurd to allege 
that payment of officials, administrators and managers represents a form 
of exploitation of the workers. Of course these people have to be paid, 
because they do necessary work. If some types of work are paid more 
than others, that may or may not be unjust, but it is not exploitation. 
Supporting an apparatus of management out of the values produced 
by productive labour is no more exploitation of labour than it is 
exploitation to reinvest a proportion of the values produced in the 
production of fresh means of production instead of distributing the 
entire product in consumer goods and services. 

Naturally, to keep socialist production going, and to expand it, 
it is necessary that social labour should continually produce a surplus 
over and above what is currently paid out in wages, for investment in 
future production, for costs of management, and for provision of 
social services. This shows, incidentally, that the insistence in current 
Soviet planning methods on enterprises showing “a profit” does not 
represent the reintroduction of capitalism, but is an item in the efficient 
planning of production for welfare, which is heading straight for 
communism. 

That socialist planning is heading for communism means that this 
planning progresses towards planning the full satisfaction of needs . 
Communism grows out of socialism in the course of a period of plan- 
ning, the length of which must depend on the level of social produc- 
tion from which it started. The transition is made by gradually trans- 
ferring supplies from the sphere of goods to be bought out of earnings 
to the sphere of free services. When social production is producing 
sufficient resources for the completion of that process, we have arrived. 
Thereafter there can be no question of paying people for their work, 
but only of the provision of needs as a social service to the benefits of 
which everyone is entitled. The wages system disappears, and with it 
all production of goods as commodities. Naturally, so long as people 
are paid wages they use their wages to buy what they can get for them 


372 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


— so that all the things they need to buy are still produced as commodi- 
ties. If needs are supplied and distributed as a social service, there is no 
more buying and selling and no more commodity production. 

That does not mean, however, that there is no more personal 
property — that no one possess anything of his own but everything is 
shared. Everyone will possess a great deal more personal property than 
most people possess at present. But he acquires it as of right (the human 
right to appropriate the things one needs for personal use and enjoy- 
ment) and does not have to buy it. The effective enjoyment by every- 
one of this right depends on their having co-operated and continuing 
to co-operate in producing the means necessary for its enjoyment. 


6 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 

I. COMMUNISM AND ANTI-COMMUNISM 

From our discussion it seems that progress towards the open society 
must be progress towards communism. 

The way of the open society is the way of democratic control of social 
management. And whether we like it or not, this entails class struggle . 
For the class interests of exploiting classes do not harmonise with 
freedom and security for the rest of society. We cannot move into 
the open society while respecting the rights of exploiting classes, but 
only by infringing on them and finally doing away with them. What 
is necessary is for popular democratic organisations to unite in practical 
policies in opposition to the ruling classes. They must, in the apt 
phrase of the British national anthem, “confound their politics, 
frustrate their knavish tricks”. This is the fight for the open society. 

But this is the very opposite of what Dr. Popper says about the 
open society and its enemies. Believing that capitalism has funda- 
mentally changed recently in such a way that exploitation, classes 
and class struggles are disappearing, he says that capitalism is itself the 
open society. So he says that the friends of the open society, who are 
organising to get rid of capitalism, are its enemies ; and the enemies of 
the open society, who are organising to preserve capitalism, are its 
friends. 

This topsy-turvy way of looking at contemporary issues is justified 
by Dr. Popper in The Open Society and its Enemies by his making out 
that the great fight for the open society against its enemies is a fight 
against certain ideas and teachings. And these ideologies at enmity 
with the open society are, he says, those which regard human insti- 
tutions as other than man-made. They teach that institutions are not 
made by men to suit their purposes but decreed by God or evolved 
through the operations of inexorable necessity. With them go authori- 
tarian or totalitarian views to the effect that both in public affairs and 
in private life everything men do should be directed by authorities 
placed over them, and no one should challenge authority by thinking 
for himself. 

As typical of such ideologies he selects the views of Plato, Hegel and 


374 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


Marx. But whatever may be urged on behalf of Plato and Hegel by 
Platonists and Hegelians (of whom not many survive), our discussion 
of the views of Marx has shown that Dr. Popper is much mistaken in 
selecting Marxism as such an ideology opposed to the open society. 
That beliefs of the kind he describes are indeed incompatible with 
progress is not in doubt. But as well as being mistaken in including 
the scientific ideas of Marxism among them, he is mistaken in sup- 
posing that these sorts of beliefs are the main barrier today to our 
advancing int6 the open society. If they were there would not be much 
to worry about, for they have long since been exploded in the minds 
of most thinking people. 

The real ideological enemy of the open society today is everything that is 
included under the expression “ anti-communism ”. And the fight for the open 
society is the fight against everything being done to enforce and preserve the 
exploitation of man by man under the cover of anti-communism . It is not so 
much a set theory as a passion and a prejudice entering into and 
perverting every expression of theory. Views may be “progressive”, 
adopting a critical attitude towards the establishment, urging de- 
mocracy, equality and freedom, and seeking ways of improving 
conditions for the majority of the human race — but at the same time 
the element of anti-communism turns them into support of the 
capitalist status quo and hostility to practical proposals to get rid of it. 
In that they agree with the most “reactionary” views, which are 
opposed to scientific ways of thinking and uphold traditional dogmas 
and the sanctity of old-established oppressive institutions. Nowadays 
there are few in authority who do not profess themselves convinced 
of the values of democracy and of freedom; but they profess to 
protect these values from the threat of communism, and for this 
purpose use force, tell lies, put people under orders and stamp on 
democratic organisation as vigorously as if they were convinced by 
Plato’s Laws that democracy and freedom were evils to be suppressed. 

In no doubt sincere anti-communist indignation Dr. Popper dedi- 
cated his tirade The Poverty of Historicism “in memory of the countless 
men and women of all creeds or nations or races who fell victims to the 
fascist and communist belief in Inexorable Laws of Historical Destiny”. 
He couples communism with fascism, and the victims of Hitler’s gas- 
chambers with the victims of Stalin’s misrule while socialism was 
building in the Soviet Union. Yet it was the Soviet people, advancing 
to communism, who dealt the death-blow to Hitler and subsequently 
by democratic methods put to rights the abuses of power which 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 


375 


happened under Stalin. We should remember all those who have since 
fallen victims in Vietnam, in Greece, in Spain and Portugal, in many 
parts of Africa, Asia and Latin America to the violence and cruelty of 
imperialist aggression done in the name of anti-communism. 

Dr. Popper denounces “tyranny”. And his principle of political 
science, that “we need only distinguish between two forms of govern- 
ment, democracies and tyrannies”, seems to have been formulated 
less as a guide to sociologists and historians in their study of the forms 
of state (for which purpose it is very inadequate) than as a guide for 
practical politics, to lead us to distinguish between capitalist democ- 
racies and communist tyrannies, and to exhort and entreat the 
guardians of “the free world” to oppose and ward off the latter with 
all their power. This principle is a rallying-cry of the defence of 
imperialism. Dr. Popper can, indeed, justifiably rebut any suggestion 
that his arguments are mere echoes of anti-communist propaganda, 
since The Open Society and its Enemies announced the strategy of the cold 
war even before Churchill’s Fulton Speech. But for working people 
the issue of power is not the issue of democracy versus tyranny, but of 
control of power by us versus control of power by them. To take the 
road of the open society the latter control of power has to be overcome, 
and with it the deceptive use of the ideology of anti-communism. 

Seen in this light, Dr. Popper’s mistakes in The Open Society and its 
Enemies are indeed serious ones. What he has done is to propagate 
systematically and in detail the arguments of anti-communism. 
For this he deserves thanks (and he has in fact received them) from the 
enemies of the open society. But not from its friends. 

2. AGAINST VIOLENCE, FOR JUST LAWS, FOR INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS 

Communism is a tyranny, communism will smash up democratic 
institutions, communism will destroy individual freedom, communism 
will forbid you to think for yourself, it will place you under orders, 
destroy all opportunities for criticism, impose a reinforced dogmatism, 
turn back the advance of science, destroy culture, destroy civilisation, 
return us to the beasts — all this is the theory of anti-communism. 
It is the enemy of the open society, because on the one hand it prevents 
the coming together in mutual respect and understanding, and in 
common action, of those who want to advance out of the closed 
society of exploitation, violence, wasted resources, want and in- 
security; and on the other hand it provides the propaganda and the 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


37<5 

justification for everything done, however tyrannical, however 
violent, to preserve the rule of capital. In accordance with it, Dr. 
Popper rests his main case that communism is the enemy of the open 
society on the assertion that Communists stand for violence, for the 
institution of a lawless tyranny and the destruction of the democratic 
rights of individuals. 

In making these three charges he makes as many mistakes. Let us 
consider first the question of violence. 

Dr. Popper confuses militancy with advocacy of violence. Marxism 
advocates that mass organisations of working people should not be 
prepared meekly to abide by instructions issued by authorities not 
controlled by themselves and victimising working people for the 
benefit of their exploiters. They should be intransigent in their opposi- 
tion to any sort of control of power by the exploiting class. And they 
should be united in their demands for what they immediately want 
done, and prepared to back their leaders and those in whose hands 
they entrust power in getting it done. This attitude of opposition to 
the dictation of an exploiting minority should not be confused with an 
attitude of violence directed against democratic institutions. 

Marxism makes no proposals for the use of violence to destroy 
legally established democratic institutions, where such exist. And 
if anyone does try to use violence to destroy democratic institutions 
(which has often been tried lately, and sometimes succeeded too), the 
Communist Party joins with other democratic organisations in their 
defence. For us, the question of violence can arise only as a question, 
on the one hand, of how to resist violent attacks on democratic 
institutions, on the activities of democratic organisations, and on the 
implementation of the decisions of democratic authorities and, on the 
other hand, of how to overcome violent methods of preventing 
democratic institutions and democratic rights being won. As Marxists 
have said again and again, if the ruling class resorts to violence, either 
to deprive people of existing democratic rights or to prevent their 
winning them, then violence must if necessary be used to defeat this 
violence. But without a doubt, the better organised, the more dis- 
ciplined and the more united the democratic mass movement is, the 
less opportunity is there likely to be for the ruling class to resort to 
violence, and the less violence will be required to repel violence if it 
occurs. 

This matter was touched on by Marx as long ago as December 8, 
1880, in a letter (which Dr. Popper himself quotes) to Henry Hyndman. 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 


377 


In it Marx discussed the likelihood of “a revolution*’ in Britain, in a 
context which makes it clear that by “a revolution” was meant a 
violent uprising. “If the unavoidable evolution turn into a revolution”, 
wrote Marx, “it would not only be the fault of the ruling classes, but 
also of the working class. Every pacific concession of the former has 
been wrung from them by ‘pressure from without’. Their action kept 
pace with that pressure and if the latter has more and more weakened, 
it is only because the English working class know not how to wield 
their power and use their liberties, both of which they possess legally.” 
So Marx told Hyndman that if the class struggle in Britain should ever 
lead to the violence of civil war, that would be the workers’ fault, 
because “they know not how to wield their power and use their 
liberties”. If they learned how to do so, then the “unavoidable evolu- 
tion” to socialism could be completed without revolutionary violence. 
The current programme of the British Communist Party takes up and 
spells out in contemporary political terms these ideas of Marx about 
knowing how to wield the power of democratic organisation and 
make good use of democratic rights. 

Dr. Popper has taken upon himself to argue that Marxists always 
adopt “a violent attitude” because we always declare ourselves pre- 
pared to use violence to put down violence. He freely admits that Marx 
himself refrained from predicting that the socialist revolution would 
inevitably in all circumstances be a violent one. But, he goes on, 
“the social revolution is an attempt by a largely united proletariat to 
conquer complete political power, undertaken with the firm resolution 
not to shrink from violence, should violence be necessary for achieving 
this aim, and to resist any effort of its opponents to regain political 
influence”. And “if a man is determined to use violence in order to 
achieve his aims, then we may say that to all intents and purposes he 
adopts a violent attitude, whether or not violence is actually used in a 
particular case” (2-OS. 150). 

So, according to Dr. Popper, Marxists always adopt “a violent 
attitude” because we always declare ourselves prepared to use violence 
to put down violence. According to him, we are men of violence 
because we not only propose to win and use democratic rights to get a 
socialist government elected, but also declare ourselves ready to use 
violence if anyone tries violently to deprive us of the use of demo- 
cratic rights or to resist the implementation of socialist measures. 
Yet how could democratic rights be preserved, or any democratically 
decided policy be implemented, unless we were prepared to repel 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


378 

those who attempted by violence to prevent rights being used and 
policies being put into effect? Dr. Popper himself agrees that physical 
force is required for such purposes. We propose not to shrink from 
violence if it is required to defend a socialist state and the democratic 
organisations on which it is based, or to prevent a ruling class from 
prohibiting and crushing democratic organisations. We propose to 
disarm those who carry arms against the people, and if necessary to 
carry arms ourselves in order to be able to do so. 

In this we assume far less of “a violent attitude” than some of those 
so-called democratic authorities whom Dr. Popper professes to admire 
so much. If he wants to condemn “a violent attitude” today (1966-67) 
he had better turn his attention first of all to that adopted by the 
President of the United States of America. The fact is that while 
Dr. Popper, along with other would-be friends of the open society, 
expresses horror at the idea that Marxists should advocate violence 
to defend democratic organisations from their opponents, or to get 
them established, he first of all forgets that it is the opponents and not 
those who are trying to win and use their democratic rights who 
necessitate this by taking up a violent attitude, and at the same time 
forgets to condemn the immense, iniquitous and systematic use of 
violence, including violence of the most cruel kind imaginable, in 
military campaigns to defend the rights of capital. Professed advocates 
of the open society often express their horror at the violence and 
cruelties sometimes practised by people who have been long deprived 
of rights and are driven to seek desperate remedies. The violence and 
cruelty of legally instituted authorities is excused even while it may 
be regretted. 

Dr. Popper’s real objection appears to be not against violence as 
such, which he admits is sometimes necessary, but against illegal 
violence. If he thinks violence should be under legal control, and so 
controlled as to be used only to the minimum extent necessary to win 
and protect democratic rights and carry through democratic policies, 
then we entirely agree with him. We have no wish to let loose armed 
bands in the streets and let them hang up on the lamp-posts anyone they 
do not favour. And incidentally, the last time such bands got loose was 
in Hungary, in 1956, when the “freedom fighters” ran amok. But we 
want to put down not only the illegal violence of fascist bands and 
groups of military conspirators directed against legal democratic 
institutions, but also all legalised violence for the purpose of defending 
profit and privilege. 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 


379 


Of all the threats to winning through to an open society the most 
menacing now is the threat of war. It comes from the fact that control 
over vast armed forces is vested in military organisations charged with 
protecting capital and capitalist profits. They are deployed to stop 
the liberation movements in colonial and former colonial territories 
from ousting capitalist control over their governments and their 
economies, and (as was revealed in Greece in 1967) they have plans 
all ready to operate to overthrow democracy at need anywhere. 
The chief thing in the fight for the open society is to get democratic 
control over the military, to combat the hysteria and “totalitarian 
irresponsibility of the individual” on which militarism thrives and, 
where the militarists are already waging war, to force them to stop. 
On the global scale this requires a combination of democratic resist- 
ances, the exercise of their democratic rights by those who possess them 
and, where necessary, the armed resistance of those against whom 
military violence is directed. 

Second, let us consider the question of lawless tyranny. Dr. Popper 
confuses resistance to laws which perpetuate exploitation and unequal 
rights with wishing to settle everything by arbitrary decree un- 
controlled by law. 

One of the achievements of the bourgeois revolution was the 
establishment of “the rule of law”. There is instituted a single system 
of law applying to everyone within the territory of the state, and an 
elected assembly vested with the final authority to make and change 
the laws. This means that the executive officers of the state, and all 
those who command the means of coercion, have to act within the 
law. They are charged to enforce the law and forbidden to break it. 
Their functions are defined by law, and they are liable to punishment 
if they try to use the force at their disposal for their own purposes 
regardless of law. Thus at a decisive stage of ’the bourgeois revolution 
in England, Parliament brought the Monarchy within the law by 
force of arms. Earlier, the bourgeoisie had supported the Tudor 
monarchs because they put a stop to the arbitrary violence of the 
barons and disbanded their private armies. 

The underlying economic reason why the bourgeoisie became 
champions of the rule of law is clear enough. It is because this was an 
indispensable condition for security in the commercial development 
of the home market. Without it, they could never have become as 
prosperous and powerful as they did become. And this necessitated 
laws to protect the right to exploit and curtail the right to oppose it. 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


380 

Marxists are opposed to exploitation, and oppose it even when the 
law steps in to protect it. But that, says Dr. Popper, means we want 
to break the rule of law and carry on without it, whereas without law 
there can only be anarchy or tyranny. 

The law which Marxism opposes is law in so far as it has been 
instituted to protect the rights of exploiting classes. We are not in 
favour of submitting to laws which are designed to protect the 
security and rights of exploiters and hamper the organisation of the 
masses. We propose to nullify such laws. But that is not to oppose 
the reign of law in general. We do not propose that any individuals 
or any organisations should assume powers to set themselves above the 
law, but that through democratic institutions the law should be recast 
to correspond to the work of democratic organisations to recast social 
relations. Indeed, it is evident that the rule of law is a condition for 
effective democratic management. Democracy supposes instituted 
procedures for arriving at decisions and controlling what is done. 
And that supposes enforcement of law and regulation of the whole 
business of management by law. Without law there can be no security, 
no rights and no democracy. Consequently where lawless dictatorships 
exist, trampling on democratic rights for the benefit of a gang of 
exploiters, we propose establishing, or re-establishing, in their place 
the rule of law to protect human rights. 

This may lead us to query a forcible statement written by Lenin 
in 1917, at the beginning of his pamphlet The Proletarian Revolution and 
the Renegade Kautsky: “The revolutionary dictatorship of the pro- 
letariat is power . . . unrestricted by any laws.” Lenin’s subsequent 
arguments made clear what he had in mind. Kautsky (anticipating 
Dr. Popper) had condemned the Soviet regime as a lawless tyranny 
because Russian workers were disregarding the old laws before they 
sat down to draw up new ones. “He expects us to have a constitution 
all complete to the very last word in a few months”, Lenin wrote. 
“. . . When reactionary lawyers have for centuries been drawing up 
rules and regulations to oppress the workers, to bind the poor man 
hand and foot . . . oh, then bourgeois liberals and Mr. Kautsky see no 
tyranny. This is law and order: the ways in which the poor are to be 
kept down have all been thought out and written down . . . But now 
that the toiling and exploited classes have begun to build up a new 
proletarian state ... all the scoundrelly bourgeoisie, the whole gang of 
bloodsuckers with Kautsky echoing them, howl about tyranny.” 

Strong words, no doubt. They express the fact that the task of a 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 


381 

socialist revolution is to establish effective control of power by popular 
organisations and use it to suppress capitalism. In this they will not be 
bound by old laws which circumscribed popular rights, and if neces- 
sary will assert those rights in action before defining them in law. 
But that does not imply that they have not the task of constructing a 
legal system. On the contrary, the task remains of instituting a system 
of procedures of management and of law which will protect the rights 
and personal property of individuals, control and set limits to all 
powers, and embody in institutional procedures the practice of free discussion 
and criticism , of settlement of disputes , of tolerance, of free research and 
expression , and of working together to produce for all the means and oppor- 
tunities of a free life . 

This brings us to the final question about the democratic rights of 
individuals. Dr. Popper confuses resolute action in enforcing decisions 
with stifling democracy in popular organisations. 

No one with any sense of political realities can deny that in con- 
ditions of struggle measures have to be decided and put into operation 
quickly and effectively. For this reason measures cannot always wait 
while committees deliberate and all and sundry voice their objections, 
but a relatively small number of responsible individuals have to be 
given powers of command. The word “dictator” originally denoted 
an officer given temporary command to deal with a situation of 
national emergency in the democratic Roman Republic. And it was 
obviously because he foresaw the need for emergency powers in order 
to effect the transition from capitalism to socialism that Marx (a man 
well-read in the classics) used the phrase “dictatorship of the pro- 
letariat” to describe a workers’ government. Some Marxists nowadays 
try to explain that by “dictatorship” he did not mean what he said; 
but evidently he did. 

Dr. Popper warns us that once individuals are given any dictatorial 
powers they are apt to hang on to them, increase them, and misuse 
them, in defiance of democracy. And indeed the experience of many 
revolutions bears out this warning. It has happened not once but 
several times that revolutions have thrown up dictators, these dictators 
have sought to preserve and increase their power by turning it against 
the popular organisations which gave it to them, others have then 
risen up to overthrow the dictator, and so on. This process is now 
regarded by many as an inviolable law of revolution: “the revolution 
devours its children”. What are we to do about it? Are we for this 
reason to abjure any democratic efforts to force through a fundamental 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


382 

change of the social system? The arguments of Dr. Popper are hardly 
of recent birth, and had Englishmen listened to them three hundred 
years ago we would have continued to enjoy the benefits of the 
divine right of kings— just as had Russians listened to them fifty 
years ago they would now be labouring for the greater profit of 
monopoly capital. 

The problem is a problem of the democratic control of power . For this 
democratic control of power in the socialist revolution there must 
exist popular mass democratic organisations — well organised, imbued 
with a voluntary discipline, well managed, clear about their demands 
and their aims. Such organisations, embracing in their membership 
the majority of the working people, can break the capitalist control of 
power and set up their own power, make it as firm and strong as 
circumstances require, and control it democratically. 

The essential condition is that organisations shall be organised on well- 
established principles of democracy — that is to say, of the orderly conduct 
of discussion of business, of criticism of persons and policies, of carrying 
out decisions, of the election of leaders and officials, and of the re- 
sponsibility of these to the organisations for carrying out the policies 
for which they were elected. Clearly, such democracy of organisation 
must not be merely inscribed in a rule-book but have become a habit, 
embedded in the consciousness of the masses, solidified as a result of 
practical experience, a law of life of all organisations. 

This sort of democracy, which governs not merely the methods of 
appointment and dismissal of officials, but the activity of millions of 
citizens, is no “mere form”. Without it, it is not possible for rulers, 
even though democratically appointed, to be subject to effective and 
continuous democratic control. And incidentally, this explains in what 
sense Marxists do “disparage” the “mere formal” democracy of general 
elections and representative government. Dr. Popper says these 
provide “the only known device by which we can try to protect 
ourselves against the misuse of political power”. Experience shows that 
that is not true, since despite general elections and representative 
government political power is still misused, thanks to its control by 
capitalist organisations. The point is that there must be democratic 
organisation embracing the day-to-day activity of millions; and that 
and only that can provide effective protection against the misuse of 
political power, and at the same time invest in individual office-holders 
all the power necessary to carry through against opposition measures 
on behalf of the people. 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 


383 

Control has to be exercised through a series of links — and the only 
way this can be done is by the organisation of individuals in demo- 
cratic organisations in which the members continually exercise their 
rights of discussion, criticism, hearing reports from officials and voting 
on policies. If the executive is controlled from below by such organ- 
isations, then the organised individuals do, each of them, exercise a 
real and not merely an occasional and nominal control over the 
executive. Rulers are held continually responsible to the organisations 
that entrusted them with power. Each individual then exercises a real 
individual control through the rights he possesses as a member of an 
organisation. 

To sum up. Marxism proposes organised mass opposition to ruling- 
class violence; it proposes opposition to laws which exist to protect 
the privileges of the ruling class and the institution of a system of law 
to protect the rights of the common people ; and it proposes the firm 
control of political power by mass organisations so as to eradicate 
capitalism and advance on the road to communism. These are the 
practical proposals of the fight for an open society. On the other hand, 
policies of using violence — military violence and police violence, 
legalised violence and illegal violence — to enforce the interests of 
exploiting classes; policies to make laws and enforce them to protect 
the exploiting classes; and policies to keep political power out of the 
control of the organised masses — these are the policies of the open 
society's enemies. 

3. THE RATIONALIST BELIEF IN REASON 

But effective action towards the open society is only possible, so Dr. 
Popper repeatedly informs us, on the basis of reason or reasonableness. 
In other words, it has to be decided on as the outcome of argument and 
criticism, of looking for and sifting evidence, of reckoning up con- 
sequences and testing opinions by experience. 

Reasonableness, he continues, brings people together. For it enables 
them to test their premises, draw valid conclusions and concert their 
efforts. Where they disagree it enables them to argue it out, and to 
reach agreement by assisting each other in discovering mistakes. But 
this is exactly what Marxists, with their doctrines of class war, refuse 
to do. They refuse to try to reach agreement with “the class enemy". 
Hence they decline reasonable discussion about differences, resent 
criticism, ignore evidence which conflicts with what they have 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


384 

decided must be true, are reckless of consequences, and believe blindly. 
And this is sheer irrationalism. 

Dr. Popper, like many others, finds himself in a contradiction when 
he reasons about reason and the need for reasonableness. On the one 
hand he is all for reasonableness and says how unreasonable Marxists 
are in proposing to do away with capitalism. But on the other hand, 
he declines to reason about what changes in conditions must be 
brought about before counsels of reasonableness can prevail. He is 
caught in the same dilemma as advocates of reasonableness have 
always been. On the one hand, affairs will never go well until reason- 
ableness prevails over the clamour of competing interests. On the 
other hand reasonableness cannot prevail unless people are reasonable, 
which competing interests prevent. The difficulty was brought out 
long ago by David Hume (that very reasonable philosopher) in his 
studies "of human nature”. Men, he said, are moved by interest and 
passion, not by reason. And so at the same time as he recommended 
what he concluded to be a reasonable attitude in life, he concluded 
from this same reasoning that the majority of men would never adopt 
it. In the same way Dr. Popper exhorts us to be reasonable. But from 
the way things go there is no prospect in sight of building a rational 
society. 

However, the feebleness of the encouragement offered by Dr. 
Popper’s rationalism is compensated by the vigour of his denunciation 
of the irrationalism of Marxists. Rationalism, he tells us, "is an attitude 
of readiness to listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience” 
(2-OS. 225). But Marxism discourages the whole attitude of listening 
and learning. According to "Marx’s historical philosophy” the course 
of social development can be decided only by "the chosen class, the 
instrument of the creation of a classless society, and at the same time, 
the class destined to inherit the earth”. This, says Dr. Popper, is on a 
par with "the historical philosophy of racialism or fascism” according 
to which "the chosen race” is "the instrument of destiny” (i-OS. 9-10). 
Marx, he concedes, was in spirit and intention "a rationalist . . . But 
his doctrine that our opinions are determined by class interests hastened 
the decline of this belief. . . . Marx’s doctrine tended to undermine the 
rationalist belief in reason. Thus threatened both from the right and 
from the left, a rationalist attitude to social and economic questions 
could hardly resist when historicist prophecy and oracular irrationalism 
made a frontal attack on it” (2-OS. 224). 

So, it seems, Marxists join with racialists and fascists "to undermine 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 385 

the rationalist belief in reason”. And they do this by their “doctrine 
that our opinions are determined by class interests”. 

If this “doctrine” is supposed to imply (as Dr. Popper seems to 
think) that class interests and class interests alone determine all the 
opinions of every individual, then obviously the doctrine is false, and 
as obviously it would “tend to undermine the rationalist belief in 
reason”. But Marx never propounded any such doctrine. Indeed, 
he never propounded any “doctrine” whatever about this matter. 
He investigated in concrete cases the influence of class interests in 
processes of opinion-formation, and on the basis of these investigations 
he concluded that in class-divided societies class interest is a constant 
determining factor in opinion-formation. His whole approach to the 
question was scientific. 

The way in which class interest determines opinion is to be traced, 
not in the first place in individual processes of opinion-formation, but 
rather in the aggregate of opinion-forming and opinion-expressing 
interactions of individuals in a society divided into classes. There is 
(as Marx discovered, but he is not alone in remarking on it) a very 
close connection, always observable in the aggregate though often 
not in the case of single individuals, between economic or class interest 
and mental interest. The ambiguity in the word “interest” is significant 
here. Class interests have the effect of making people interested in 
certain themes, certain problems, about which it becomes important, 
from the point of view of class interest, that opinions should be 
formed. Simultaneously they have the effect of creating what may be 
termed blind-spots in opinion-formation: certain ranges of experience 
are ignored, certain questions are simply not asked, and this kind of 
opinion-censorship is sustained by the indignation (or in certain 
instances it may be the indifference) with which any opinions tending 
to trespass on blind-spots are received. Again, class interests lead to 
unquestioned assumptions being made both in factual judgments and 
in value judgments. In general, whatever class is dominant , or specially 
active in furtherance of its interests , its interests will receive reflection in 
major directions of interest and of opinion-formation in society at the time. 

These and many other effects of class interest on aggregate opinion- 
formation cannot but have a very pronounced influence on the 
opinions formed by all individuals in society. The starting point for 
all individual interest (that is to say, mental interest) and opinion is the 
aggregate of interest and opinion which the individual finds current 
in society, towards which he has to orient himself. So his interests will 


386 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


take their direction from class interests (but not necessarily exclusively 
those of the class into which he himself is born), and his opinions will 
tend to be for or against class-determined opinions, and so inescapably 
bear a class as well as an individual character. When individuals of 
exceptional mental ability and originality elaborate opinions, they 
tend to serve the interests of one or another class. When they question 
received opinions, their very questioning tends to aid one class interest 
or another. Or if the individual’s opinions break right away from any 
class interest (in both senses of “interest”), then he becomes an isolated 
eccentric in his society, and he and his opinions suffer accordingly. 
And this is to say nothing of the upbringing and education which 
individuals receive, which cannot but play a determining part in their 
opinions, and in which all manner of class-determined interests, blind 
spots and assumptions are put into their heads. 

Such being roughly the facts, it follows that Dr. Popper assumes 
without reason that no opinions determined by class interest can at 
the same time be reasonable. For there is no reason why class interest 
should always and necessarily preclude “an attitude of readiness to 
listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience”. On the 
contrary, on many topics class interest may demand the formation of 
reasonable opinions — namely, on those topics in which the class 
interest is better served by truth than by illusions. 

So far from Marx’s scientific conclusions about the way class 
interests determine opinions undermining “the rationalist belief 
in reason”, they provide the clue to understanding at long last the 
practical means by which an attitude of reasonableness can be made to prevail 
To promote “a rationalist attitude to social and economic questions” 
does not demand pitting “reason”, as some kind of ideal force free 
from such mundane influences as class interest, against the irrationality 
of class interest. It does not demand that a few rationalists who have 
managed to overcome in their thinking every influence of circum- 
stances should somehow manage to get the ear of the swinish multitude 
and teach them too to think disinterestedly. These are the contradic- 
tions of “rationalism” which have caused so many in the past and 
present to conclude that reasonableness is an ideal incapable of realisa- 
tion. No, to work for reasonableness to prevail is to work for the victory of 
that class interest which is served by reasonableness . 

Recently the French Marxist, Louis Althusser, has presented us with 
a definition of “ideology” which distinguishes it sharply (as class- 
determined opinion) from science. “There is no question here of 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 387 

giving a profound definition of ideology,” he writes. “It suffices to 
say very schematically that an ideology is a system (possessing its own 
logical consistency) of representations (images, myths, ideas or con- 
cepts as the case may be) endowed with an existence and an historical 
role within a given society . . . ideology as a system of representations 
is distinguished from science in that with it the practical-social function 
outweighs the theoretical function (or the function of yielding know- 
ledge)’ ’ ( Pour Marx , Paris 1966, 238) 

Here is a case of a Marxist engaging in that very habit of setting up 
abstract antitheses against which the Marxist dialectic is directed (so 
Althusser is right to call it “very schematic”). Of course, if one con- 
trasts, say, the “system of representations” of the constitution of the 
material world which was current in medieval society with the con- 
ceptions of nature current today, one can contrast the former as 
“feudal ideology” with the latter as science. However, the reason why 
scientific conceptions of nature ousted feudal ideology was that the 
development of capitalism demanded and encouraged a scientific 
approach to the knowledge of nature. Industry could not use images 
or myths, and it could not develop without scientific ideas or concepts. 
So far as nature is concerned, the “representations endowed with an 
existence and an historical role” within bourgeois society are scientific. 
This has been forwarded by the interest (in both senses of the word) of 
the capitalist class. It is not due to the “practical-social function” 
having ceased to outweigh the “theoretical function”, or to demands 
for winning knowledge having contrived to outweigh the demands 
of practice. It is due to circumstances in which the practical-social 
function could only be served by genuine scientific inquiry. So in this 
department bourgeois ideology is scientific — and reasonable. It is a 
great mistake to set up science in abstract antithesis to ideology . Under 
definite circumstances ideology can only be developed to satisfy its practical 
social function by the adoption of the methods of science. And if that were 
not so, it would be a kind of miracle that the methods of science, and 
the attitude of reasonableness in the formation of opinions, should ever 
begin, let alone come out on top. 

So far as class interests are concerned in the circumstances of the 
present day, it is quite clear that the class interests of the capitalist class, 
and the sorts of ideologies which its social dominance promotes, do 
not preclude “an attitude of readiness to listen to critical arguments 
and to learn from experience” in many matters. In these matters they 
favour reasonableness and scientific thinking, as a result of which these 


TOWARDS AN OPEN SOCIETY 


3S8 

good things have made some progress in capitalist societies. This 
applies particularly in the development of science and technology; 
and it also applies, though with rather definite limitations, in what 
Dr. Popper calls ‘‘social engineering” and, in more theoretical matters, 
in the discussion of a number of problems of philosophy, morals, 
aesthetics, and so forth. But when it comes, theoretically to basic 
questions about human relations and the development of society, and 
practically, to the management of social production, the conduct of 
class struggle, the control of state power and the framing of political 
policies — there the attitude of reasonableness, the readiness to follow 
through and act on the conclusions of scientific inquiry, the readiness 
to listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience ceases. 
What takes over is irrational prejudice, preconceived opinion, refusal 
of critical questioning, sophistry, blindness, recklessness of conse- 
quences, refusal to face facts and unreasoning indignation against 
anyone who draws attention to them. 

In all these vital matters it is the working-class interest, and that 
alone, which demands reasonableness and the aid of science. Not to 
preserve the exploitation of man by man, but to fight to end it, and to 
arrive at policies to guide the movement to do this effectively, demands 
nothing in ideology except what can be concluded from a scientific view of 
the human situation tempered and developed by critical argument and the 
tests of experience. 

Hence if today the voice of reason has a better prospect of ampli- 
fication and of making itself heard than “the voice of one crying in 
the wilderness” as of old, this is because it is not, as rationalists have 
imagined, the accuser against even* interest but, on the contrary, the 
true voice of the interest of the working men. Whether recognised by 
them or not, the working classes are interested in the cultivation ot 
reasonableness in all ideas, in all dealings, in all practical policies. 
Anything else injures them. And so reasonableness has the prospect of 
growth out of the soil of class interest. And intellectuals who are 
concerned to arrive at a rational outlook find a common language with 
workers, but can find it with no other class. 

Rationalists have posed the question: how can reasonableness be 
made to prevail in human affairs? To answer it they must themselves 
cultivate a rational and scientific approach to social questions. And tor 
that they must stop trying to refute Marxism, and join with Marxism 
in opposition to the ideas of the exploiting classes. Then the answer 
appears. It is in the struggle of working people against exploitation that 


THE OPEN SOCIETY AND ITS ENEMIES 389 

reasonableness can find support , and out of it reasonableness can in the end 
prevail This is where it grows, so help it grow there. And oppose 
everything that throttles it, whether from outside the movement or 
from inside. 

It follows that reasonableness is not (as Dr. Popper and many others 
appear to suggest) the same thing as universal tolerance, nor as non- 
violence, nor as the reconciliation of all interests. It is not the counsel of 
reason that where incompatible interests exist a way should always be 
sought to reconcile them all On the contrary, where they conflict one 
must always in practice be subordinate to another (as those who in 
capitalist countries counsel reconciliation counsel the subordination of 
the working-class to the capitalist interest), and what is reasonable is to 
subordinate the interest which opposes human progress to that which 
promotes it. It is not the counsel of reason to tolerate the blocking of 
progress by organised vested interests, nor to refuse to use physical 
force to overcome physical force. 

Our century has been called “the century of the common man”. 
This is because of the growth of democratic institutions and demo- 
cratic organisation. The “common man” has no interest in exploiting 
his fellows, and still less in fighting with them over economic issues, 
territorial claims or ideological differences. If contrary to all reason 
exploitation and enmity continue, this is not because of the inherent 
unreasonableness of the common man but because of the interested 
irrationality of administrators, legislators, leaders and rulers. Our 
trouble is not in the irrationality of the common man but in the 
institutions which set men at loggerheads and place over us the rulers 
we have still got. The reasonable ideology w*e must have in order to 
end these conditions is one which subjects them to rational criticism so 
as to show how institutions must be changed by us, and rulers and 
policies brought under control. Its principles are those of science and 
reason, its development comes through critical questioning and learn- 
ing from experience, it unites people in rational opposition to the 
clamours and incitements of divisive ideologies, it relies on the totality 
of scientific ways of thinking and promulgates not “doctrines” but a 
well-tested method of practical thinking. 










INDEX 


Abstraction: 30, 49-51, 70, 72, 74-5, 
77-81, 86, 98, 101-2, 103, 104, 105, 
116-17, 120, 124, 157, 164, 166, 167, 
179, 189, 195, 202, 237, 253 
Acton, Lord: 179 
Althusser, Louis: 386-7 
Anti-Communism: 30, 18 1, 185, 344, 
374-5 

Aristotle: 24, 35, 48, 62, in, 117, 121, 
284 

Attlee, Lord: 216 

Automation: 213, 231, 319, 349-52, 
354 

Bagrit, Sir Leo: 350 
Balzac, Honore de: 254-5 
Berkeley, George: 50, 70 
Bernstein, Edward: 94 
Blake, William: 346 

Capitalism: 21, 22, 27, 76, no, 141, 
144, 145, 148, 149, 155, 158, 159, 
162, 168, 169, 178, 184, 186, 188-214, 
215, 218-19, 225, 227-31, 232, 248, 
250, 255-7, 258, 273-4, 283, 285, 
287-9, 298, 303, 310-n, 322, 331-3, 
339-41, 343, 345, 347-8, 353, 358, 
363-5, 3 <56, 368, 369, 381, 384, 387 
accumulation: 200, 205-14, 229, 
341; crises: 207, 211-12, 227, 
229, 231, 303, 310, 363, 364; 
monopoly: 188-92, 204, 208, 
220, 256, 270, 347, 364-5 
Categories: 80, 105, 116-21 
Caudwell, Christopher: 40 
Causality: 66-7, 116, 148, 313-14 
Charles II (English King): 250 
Choice: 133, 3°7, 309, 3C3. 3H. 315. 

317. 319 . 321. 324. 337. 342 
Churchill, Sir Winston: 216, 375 
Civilisation: 179, 208, 213, 215, 216, 

217, 218, 245, 249, 306, 308, 317, 
320, 334 

Classes: 26, 129, 154, 172, 176, 210, 

218, 219, 241-4, 247, 249, 250, 254, 


Classes — contd . 

260, 272, 276, 281, 285-91, 304, 331, 
340, 37i, 380, 384 
agreements of (compromise): 94, 215, 
227-9, 2 42* 250; ideas , policies: 
174, 176, 242-5, 384-9; ruling: 
177, 217, 218, 226, 227, 229, 
244, 252, 258, 263, 268, 273-4, 
288, 298, 309, 310, 311, 367, 
369, 376-7, 378, 383 ; struggle: 93, 
94, 106, 148, 154, 155, 156, 157, 
177, 178, 179, 182, 183, 186, 
206, 208, 210, 228, 233, 242-5, 
246, 248, 258-9, 261, 264, 
266-71, 289, 301, 322, 323, 
331-2, 335, 345, 353, 370, 373, 
388; working: 150, 155, 156, 
159, 220, 243, 268, 302, 323, 
334, 338, 345, 377, 388-9 
Closed Society: 132, 325-6, 328-30, 
332-6, 340, 342, 343 
Commodity: 74, 79, 189, 192-8, 283, 
287, 332, 335, 354, 363, 372 
Communism (Communist Society) : 
93, 94, 95, 129, 141, 1 50-1, 190, 192, 
335, 343, 344, 345, 352-9, 368-72, 
373, 383 

primitive (see also Tribalism): 129, 
168, 332,333,334,335,340, 362 
Communist Party (Communists, Com- 
munist Movement) : 58, 95, 125, 132, 
138, 142, 150, 179-87, 221, 225-7, 
230, 249, 269, 311, 357, 360, 368, 
370, 375-7 

Darwin, Charles: 27-9, 30, 168 
Democracy: 173, 174, 178, 179, 180, 
181, 186, 218, 249-52, 255, 258-77, 
281-3, 292, 300, 301, 302, 305, 309, 
3I0-II, 326, 335, 339, 344, 345, 358, 
365, 366-7, 368, 373, 374, 377, 379, 
380-3 

d. institutions: 232, 233, 235, 246, 
261-71, 295-9, 375, 376, 378, 
380-2, 389 
Democritus: 69 


Ml Ml 


TEE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


39 - 

Dialectks: 

-•5 spfMOi (mahmi): 33 , 60 - 1 , 67, 
76 — Si, 97 - 5 : crr-oretf analysis: 
32 , “ 3 — Si, 9 >, 239 ; 

34* 62 - 1 , 6 ;-x, 70 - 3 , 75 — Si, 
92 ~i* 93 , 95, ico, 120 , 123 , 124 , 
129 , 202 , 223 , 265, 2 ” 2 , 3 S 7 : 
a^TMkdz^s: 32 , 75 , 75 , 99 , 

100 - 3 . 107 , 109 . I 3 i- 175 ; of 

kmv'bdgf: Si— S ; Lars (rnn- 
35 . 73 * 55 , S9-91, 9S, 
124* in* 1 1 5 * iai, 12:. 129, 
2C2, 223, 266. 272-, 337; 
kfL :: 35 , 76 - 7 . 122 ; muserialisi: 
41 , 6 l, 76 , 93 ; negmirr.: 76 , 77, 
99 * 1 : 2 - 11 , 332 , 335 - 6 ; ciianorf 
z?tdfuz.:ir/: 75,9-5-9* 106 - 7 , Hi, 
120 , 123 ; ariafe ("fen, tx::- 
rteii, rfTZtesis”): 32 , 36 , 64 , 67 , 
" 5 * 1 - 9 . 336 : ssnirj efposi&s: 
6^ 6-5-9- 73 * 75 * 75, S 3 , 95-9- 
I co -9 

Dickers, Chaies: 1 S 9 
Dictatorship of Proletariat: : < 2 , 155 , 
156 , 157 , 175— S:, 155 , :Sx, 223 . 22 S, 
253 , 255 - 9 , 2 - 1 , 2 - 4 --. 32 - 3 S 2 , 3 S 1 
Duhrir.g. Ecger.: 226 


Qecdoas: 251, 259, 263, 264, 272, 2-5, 
2 - 6 , 2 ?:, 2 S 2 . 25x, 255 . 259 , 291 , 
_ c>5--, 335, 339, 3 52 
tarth , Frederick: 25, 2", 33, 34, 36, 
-ii, -iT, 53- 5A 65, 9 :, 52 , 92 , :ox, 
:c-5, ::x- 135, 136, 172, 171, 173, 
: 5 i, ::c. 241. 2x5, 25*. 262, 363 

sidosus 6 c--, - 3 , - 9 , 9 :— ico, 
121 , icc : or iiTtiirvrerz r 
zzr ilzbsn 191 - 2 : on jrf* £: *n : 
I __ 293 , 306 - 9 , 312 , 313 , 

312 - 19 , 3 — : mzxrk&m: ;-S, 
21 , 51 , 69 - 72 , 125 , 123 ; on iSse 
iC-stf; 24 -. 255 - 2 , 556 
pi r^rcii : 69 

-quality: 22-3, 262, 265, 265, 251-9:. 

292-x. 295, 525, 522, 52X, 3 -2 
rascrcialisn : ;c, 15:, 159-61, if.. CiS, 
-53, 297, 29?, 5 C2 


Exploitation: 156, 157, 172, 176, 177, 
175. 179, l5o, 1S6, I *9, 191, 19S, 
202-4, 207, 209 210, 216, 217, 215, 
219, 220, 221, 222, 223, 224, 225, 
229, 241, 242. 244- 145* C4S-9, 250, 
262, 265, 266, 267, 269, 270, 273, 

2?5, 2 *5* C90, 292, 295. 297, 301, 

504, 507, 509, 310, 311, 3*2, 353, 

33-4, 335- 336, 340, 542, 353, 363, 

37C, 371, 373* 374- 375, 379* 35o, 

5S3, 355, ;59 

Fabians: 296 

Fasc^n: 1S4, 1S5* 374, 37?, 5$4 

Fate (Destiny, Fatalism): 131, 133, 145, 
153* 155-9, 170, 175-9. I So, 1S1, 
1S6. 224. 230, 373, 374, 3S4 

Feudalism (Serfdom, Sects): 16S, 169, 
204, 107, 254. 276, 2S3, 1*4, 322, 
35S, 3x6, 563, 35- 

Freedom: 205, 215. 245, 262, 26-, 265, 
251, 292-52X, 526, 525, 344, 345. 
353. 573, 374 

ef ckzix, fr:~: amspearz: 305 - 24 . 
5 : 5 - 19 , 521 , 322 ; irJiinJuil: 
292 , 292 , 299 - 300 , 3 - 4 * 537 -II, 
3I2-I-, 320-24, 335* 337, 342, 
3 - 9 * 355 * 361 . 362 , 351 ; Uriiu 
of 292 - 5 . 299 - 504 , 507 - 5 , 311 . 
3 : 2 - 14 , 517 ; mztsssrf amdcdms 
of: 3 : 2 - 24 ; pdfcual: 294 - 504 , 
3 C 5 

Freud, Smmimd: 19 

Galbraith, Professor R : 565—6 

Galilee Galilei: 24 

Gherghiz Khar. : 262 

Grcerr. Sir W. S.: 502 


Happiness: :Si, 222 . 225 - 6 , 505 
Heath. Edvrard (Ted): 2 "3 
Heseh G. V/. F. : 17 , 51 * 6 i f 65 - 9 , 73 . 
75, 5c, SS, 104 , 135 , IC 9 , no, 117 , 
ri!, in, 122 , 125 , 124 , 125 , 153 , 
512 , 315 , 515 , 5 1 6 , 556 , 573 . 374 
Herachms: iox 


INDEX 


Hiitoricism: 50, 1 2 9—3 o . i>, 155. 
156-9, 16’. 169. 1S1, 1S2. 225, 205. 
29$, 521. 325. 32'. 329, 3S4 
History: 153-6. 15'. 1 >2. 515 

h . fT ' S . nsr .: 12-30, 1 3 '->4. 15'. 

167 

Hider, Adolf: 1S5, 5-4 
Hobbes, Thomas: So, 302 
Holism: 15 1-2, 159. 160-1. 162. 564. 
367 

Hume, David: So, 5S4 

Idealism: 24. 31, 41, 42, 46. 4', 50. 
56-7, 6-5, 9-S, ITS, 119. 121, 12.2. 125. 
153, 529 

Ideology: 243. 553. 367. 575. 574, 575. 
5S6-9 

Imperialism: 1S4, 1S6, 212, 215, 217, 
220, 575 

Individual, the human (see also 
Freedom, individual): 156, 161,105. 
170, 226, 251, 2S1, 525-7. 555, 
336-42, 5S5. 3S5-6 
Induction: 25, 41. 165 
Inevitability: 154, 155. 15', i$i, 221. 
230 

Institutions (see also Democracy, d, 
insdtudons): 135, 172. 215. 221, 222, 
225, 22S, 252— 44, 345 K53. 25S. 273. 
276, 2S1, 2S2, 2S5-5, 395, 501, 302, 
305, 304, 506. 519, 520, 52S-55. 35-, 
339. 34S» 34i. 34^ » 353* 357* 3^7* 
373. 3*i. 3^9 

cr:J class: 233, 255, 242-5, 2SS-91 : 
^viYTr:*T?erj;: 259, 245-5”, 25S— 
395-9: rwfes * f : 2 5 6-5 
Intellectuals: i"4, 220, 3 SS 
Lntendons: 134, 145, 145-S, 170. i”i 
Interests: i”2, 173, 1-4, 179, 1S0, 1S2, 
1S3. 22”, 22S-9. 242, 245. 244. 24-. 
249, 251, 255, 269, 2 ”2, 277. 2$$. 
291, 295. 539-36, 559. 543. 545* 344. 
361. 373* 3*4-9 

Johnson, Lyndon B.: 3”$ 

Kant, Immanuel: 1 1 ”, irS, 121, 2 S 1 
Kautsky, Karl: 3 So 


95 

Knowledge: 26. 45, 4”, 5 1 — 5 . 150, 171, 
295. 5lb. 317. 531. 349.361. 5 5” 

Labour: 55. 19S, 511-4, 545-0, 551 
izi ' isimr . cf 24 1, 24”. 507— 5 , 516, 
522, 525. 531, 554-6 
La bout ,\ i o vem en : (W orkmg-class 
Movement): i”, 125. 145, 174, 176, 
1S5, 1 >5—6, iSS. 200. 20S. 2 co, 221, 
251, 255, 255, 26S. 2 56 , 554, 5^2. 

544. 545* 559 
Laplace. P. S.: 70 

Law (Legislation) : 1 5c, 1S.4, 240, 20S, 
271, 276. 2S2, 2S5. 2S4. 2S5. 25”. 
2>S-oo, 292. 501. 502, 505, 556-7, 

579— 5 1. 555 

Laws : 

rcowoV: 195-4, 301-2, 212. of 
mstyrr: 90, 1 65. 205-6, 25”, 
515-15. 510. 525: of sxiJ 
129, 15”— 5. 159, 

US, lO”-"!. IpO. 205-7, 224, 
25C-1. 255. 254, 521, 541: of 
c&wfftf: 55, 122-5 

Lenin, V. I.: 52. 55, 40, 75, Si, S5. 95, 
ico, 1 19. 122, 124, 149, 151, 152, 
155. 1S0-9C. 202, 2:4, 226. 241, 550 
Liberalism : 5 00, 5 05 . 5 00. 5 co-: 0,516, 
540 

Lincoln. Abraham: 260 
Logic: 52, 55, 52. 76-7, 5”, 09. 102, 
105. ico, no, in, 122. 141. 157, 165 
bri.'isl ryre: 1 12-14, 115-16, 11S; 
rio^\YU7oi: .t: or;, Ira’ of; 32-6, 64 
Louis XV (French King): 140 

Machines: 210, 211, 25”, 519. 54CY-7, 

Mai thus, Rev. T. R. : 25 
Man (Human Nature. Humanity) : 2 5. 
46, 55. 154. 145* 302-5. 515* 515* 
525, 541, 55- 

Management: 1 ”2. 153. 191, 199. 

200—1 . 2II-I2, 24I, 245. 255, 200, 
277, 295. 296, 535-4* 531* 553- 547. 

545, 552, 556, 555, 36I, 362. 564. 
5<X>-7, 571, 550. 551, 355 

Mao Tse-mng: 101 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


394 

Marx, Karl : 

social theory of: 17, 19-31, 34, 36, 
81, 83, 88-9, 90, 91, 129-42, 151, 
152-9, 161-3, 163-71, 181, 182, 

223- 4, 230, 232-3, 235, 240, 
241, 249, 283, 327, 329, 331. 
340,373,385,386 

on capitalism: 33, 178, 189-214, 
307-8, 363 ; on capitalist accumul- 
ation: 204-14; on class struggles: 
232, 243-4, 258-9, 323; on 
dialectics: 33, 36, 76, 78, 80, 
98-9, 335-6; on freedom: 292, 
306, 308-9, 313, 314-15, 3i9, 
324, 328; labour theory of value: 
192-8, 202-4, 207; materialism 
of: 51-4, 69, 118, 119, 125; 
methodology of: 30-1, 239, 266; 
politics of: 149, 172-7, 179, 
229-30, 342, 376-7, 38i; pre- 
dictions by: 22, 146-50, 188, 192, 
204-5, 208, 209, 210, 347, 349; 
on science and technology: 345-8; 
on socialism and communism: no, 

343, 344, 355-6, on the state: 247, 
253, 254-5, 257, 260, 262-3, 
271-4, 302 

Marxism : 

class character of: 175-7; “ dog- 
matism ” of: 17, 129, 137, 205, 
384; “orthodox”: 91-3, 126; 
philosophy of: 40, 43-7, 60, 97-8 ; 
political programme of: 17, 93, 94, 
157, 179, 182-8, 214, 217-22, 

224- 7, 267-71, 274-7, 293-4, 
302-4, 305, 306, 3 1 1, 327, 340, 

344, 359, 380-3; “revisionism”: 
94, 183; scientific development of: 
18, 36-7, 92, 95, 96, 1 12; and 
social sciences: 79-81, 94, 150, 
165, 321; theory of the state: 
80-1, 253-7, 271-4, 298, 331 

Materialism: 31, 42-59, 88, 89, 115, 

118, 153 

dialectical: 37-41, 69, 97, m-12, 
1 15, 1 19, 122, 129, 138 ; historical: 
2 6, 31, 129, 135, 137-40; 
metaphysical: 69-71 


Metaphysics: 19, 38, 41, 60-7, 70, 72, 
74, 75, 76, 98, 101, 106, 119, 120, 
122, 125, 243 

Mill, John Stuart: 300, 301 

Napoleon I (French Emperor) : 145 
Nationalism: 183, 326, 338 
Necessity: 66- 7, 87-8, 99, 100, 102, 
105, 109, hi, 120, 121, 154-7, 170, 
177, 186, 191, 224, 225, 242, 244, 
302, 306, 308-9, 312-17, 324, 327, 
357, 362, 369, 373 
Newton, Sir Isaac: 24, 69, 158 

Open Society: 267, 320, 325-8, 332-6, 
337-40, 342, 343, 344, 356, 359, 373, 
374, 375, 376, 379, 383 
Opportunity: 284, 307, 308, 319-24, 
342, 381 

Organisation: 149-50, 152, 153, 171, 
174, 179, 180, 183, 184, 186, 220, 
226, 228, 243, 253, 256, 268-70, 
274-7, 287-8, 289, 290, 310, 334, 
336, 339, 340, 342, 349, 357, 358, 
366, 367, 373, 377, 38o, 381-3, 389 

Parliament: 216, 263-4, 270, 275-7, 
379 

Paul, Saint: 312 
Peisistratos : 262 
Pericles: 325 

Planning: capitalist: 149, 21 1, 213, 
363-5; socialist: 174, 212, 303, 307, 
323-4, 348, 358, 360-2, 366-8, 371 
Plato: 17, 50, 67-8, 69, 197, 201, 236, 
242, 258, 325, 373, 374 
Plekhanov, G. V. : 100 
Polarity: 108-9 

Politics: 66, 130, 172-4, 178, 182, 224, 
226, 231, 233, 257, 306, 316, 344, 
353, 357, 358, 381, 388 
Political parties: 172-3, 179, 251, 
257, 277, 288: of the working 
class: 149, 173, 174-6, 179-87, 
266-71; and science : 152, 157, 
174-7 

Popper, Professor Sir Karl: 21, 22, 24, 
34, 36, 39, 41, 64, 86, 1 14, 1 19, 152, 


INDEX 


395 


Popper, Professor Sir Karl — contd. 

20 6, 212, 220, 221, 317, 319, 344, 

385, 386, 388, 389 

on capitalism: 1S8, 192, 204, 207-9; 
on communism , evils caused by: 
179, 180-1, 184-5, 215-16, 217, 
223, 275, 276, 290, 313, 343, 
360-2, 367, 375-82; on demo- 
cracy: 249-50, 256-7, 258-71; 
on dialectics: 31-3, 60, 67-8, 
88-92, 100, 108, 1 12; on 

equality: 267, 281-91; on free- 
dom: 292-3, 300-2, 305, 312-13, 
315, 316, 321, 324; on historicism f 
essentialism , holism and utopia- 
nism: 129-33, 136, 137, 153, 
154, 156-63, 167-9, 178, 188, 
223-4, 321, 323, 327, 384; on 
institutions and c/djjej: 219,232-5, 
249, 258-60, 265, 266-71; on 
materialism: 46-7; on Marx’s 
'Capital’: 189-90, 205-10, 230; 
on Open and Closed Society: 320, 
325-42, 373, 383; on political 
power: 178, 179, 233, 245-6, 
252, 262-3, 271-4; on reinforced 
dogmatism: 17, 19, 30, 73, 80, 
91-4, 97, 125; on scientific 

method: 18-21, 29, 77, 79-80, 
84, 111-12, 139-42, 165; on 
social engineering: 222-8, 311, 
364, 384; on social science: 
165-71, 222; on the state: 248, 
294 - 9 , 305 

Possibility: 156, 172, 176, 177, 178, 

224, 231, 316, 349, 357 
Power : 

control of: 178, 179, 190, 228, 229, 
256-7, 258-61, 272-7, 281, 282, 
288, 290-1, 295-6, 298-9, 305, 
306, 309, 310-n, 335, 345, 375, 
381-3, 388, 389; economic: 173, 
186, 256, 271-4, 296; political: 
156, 173, 175, 178-9, 183, 186, 
188, 192, 207, 217, 230, 245-7, 
250-7, 271-4, 296, 310, 327, 
342, 344,367,377,381 
Practice: 39, 48, 51-9, 84-5, 140 


Practice — contd. 

information of: 39, 54-8, 77, 88, 98, 
112, 359 

Prices: 193, 196-7, 201 
Probability: 36, 41, 143-4, 167 
Production, social: 21, 26, 28, 30, 53, 
134-6, 137-9, 144, 148, 150-1, 152, 
154, 155, 158, 161, 166,169,170, 174, 
176, 189-92, 193-8, 211, 212, 214, 
215, 216, 217, 224, 229, 230-1, 239-4, 
247, 248, 291, 293, 302, 306-9, 
316-17, 321-2, 324, 332, 335, 338, 
339-42, 344-59, 362-4, 368 
Profit: 21, 191, 198, 199-200, 209, 213, 
227, 289, 290, 300, 304, 347, 353, 
358, 37i, 379 

Progress: 144,233, 262, 281, 282-3, 289, 
335, 373, 389 

Propaganda: 149, 257, 269, 274, 277, 
286, 288, 298, 304, 306 
Property: 21, 26, 168, 177, 191, 215, 
218, 240-5, 246, 247, 248, 250, 264, 
266, 271, 282, 283, 284, 286, 289, 

290, 299, 301, 302, 303, 304, 306, 

316, 323, 33i, 340, 342, 354, 372, 381 
Psychology: 134, 165-6 

Reason (Rationality, Reasonableness): 
112, 185, 205, 208, 216, 224, 225, 

227, 232, 233, 294, 324, 326, 327, 

329, 333, 338, 339, 341, 345, 359, 

360, 383-9 

Responsibility: 320-1, 325, 327, 
336-42, 344, 346-7, 349, 356, 381, 
383 

Revolution: 215-26, 244, 259 

bourgeois: 218, 254, 275-6, 379; 
Russian: 22, 23, 186; socialist: 
209, 214, 216-22, 230-1, 244-5, 
267, 273, 275, 276, 289-91, 323, 

367, 377, 381, 382 

Ricardo, David: 80 
Richard II (English King): 337 
Rights: 215, 261, 264, 267, 268, 269, 
276, 281-91, 296, 297, 298, 300-4, 
322, 344, 362, 369, 372, 376, 377, 
378, 379-83 

Russell, Bertrand Lord : 65-6, 74 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 


396 

Ryle, Professor Gilbert: 121, 313-14 


Science (see also Social Science) : 

dialectical character of: 65-7, 72, 
77-81; empirical methods of: 19, 
23-4, 27, 36, 37, 47, 82, 84, 85, 
88, 348, 387; exact: 28-9; 
fundamentals of: 22-5, 164, 165, 
166; hypotheses: 22-3, 26, 28, 
141, 164, 348; materialist char- 
acter of: 48; as social force of 
production: 347-9 

Security: 289, 302-3, 304, 310, 327, 
328, 345 , 353 , 373,379 
Shakespeare, William: 173, 242 
Slavery: 144, 168, 204, 207, 284, 322 
Smith, Adam: 80 
Snow, C. P., Lord: 257 
Social Engineering: 21, 222-31, 232, 
234, 238, 239, 245, 246, 249, 294, 

344 . 353 , 357 , 360 , 364,388 

Social Formations: 136, 151, 153, 190, 
217, 340 
Social Science : 

differences from natural science: 
79-81, 152, 164-71, 197; 
economics: 77, 80, 364; funda- 
mentals of: 2 6 , 150, 201; and 
politics , 172-7 

Social Services: 227-9, 254, 256, 277, 
285, 286, 287, 365, 369, 371-2 
Socialism (Socialist Society): 93, 94, 
no, 141, 142, 143, 146, 148, 149, 
150, 169, 178, 180, 184, 190, 192, 
204, 212, 221, 253, 274-7, 283, 303-4, 
309 , 319 , 335 , 343 , 353 , 361, 362, 
366-71, 381 

Scientific socialism: 132, 174-7, 229 
Soviet Union (Union of Socialist 
Soviet Republics): 145, 181, 183-4, 
362,367,371,374,380 
Spinoza, B. de: 156 
Stalin, J. V.: 181, 183, 374-5 


State, the: 80-1, 191, 247-8, 250, 252, 
253-7, 271-4, 292, 294-5, 300, 301, 
303, 306, 316, 325, 331-2, 334, 335, 
366, 367, 375, 379, 

Strachey, John: 260 
Surplus Value: 199-200, 203, 204, 210, 
212, 273, 299, 370, 371 

Technology: 21, 93, 151, 206-7, 239, 
240, 241, 244, 293, 306, 308, 318-19, 
329 , 335 , 343 , 344 , 345-52, 353 , 361, 
388 

t. revolution: 213, 319, 323, 348-52, 
354 , 357 , 358 
Thucydides : 248 
Tolstoy, Leo: 320 

Tribalism: 283, 317, 325-6, 329-36, 
340, 341, 343 

Tyranny (Despots, Dictators, Tyrants, 
Totalitarianism): 179, 181-2, 184, 
185, 246, 247, 249, 251, 258, 259, 

260, 261-2, 263, 264, 265, 266, 267, 

269, 276, 289, 290, 292, 295, 326, 

331, 334 , 336, 337 , 338, 339 , 343, 

344, 36i, 373 , 375 , 376, 379 , 380 

Utopia (Utopianism) : 94, 95, 132, 152, 
159, 160-2, 182, 188,211,212, 223-5, 
244, 249, 343 , 354 , 356 - 7,358 

Violence (Bloodshed): 179, 180, 181, 
184, 185, 215, 217, 218, 223, 225, 

226, 230, 231, 232, 244, 249, 259, 

261, 263, 264, 266, 323, 344, 375-9, 

383, 389 

Wages: 198, 200, 203-4, 3 22 , 369-70, 
37 i 

War: 142, 178, 186, 208, 213, 214, 217, 
218, 225, 229, 231, 269, 299, 302, 
378 , 379 

Wells, H. G.: 260 
Wilson, Harold: 252, 270 
Wittgenstein, Ludwig: 65-6 


WORKS BY MARX, ENGELS AND LENIN, 

CITED IN CORNFORTH, 

THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY , 
AVAILABLE IN INTERNATIONAL PUBLISHERS EDITIONS 

Marx. Capital 1967. Volume 1: “The Process of Capitalist Production*'; 
Volume 2: “The Process of Circulation of Capitar*; Volume 3: “The 
Process of Capitalist Production as a Whole”. 

Critique of the Gotha Programme , 1938. 

The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte , 1963. 

Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations , 1965. 

“Preface to Critique of Political Economy”, in Marx and Engels, Selected 

Works , 1 vol., 1968. 

Theories of Surplus Value: Selections , Eds. G. A. Bonner and Emile Bums, 

1952. 

“Theses on Feuerbach”, in Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach , 1941. 

Wage-Labor and Capital 1933. 

Engels. Anti-Duhring , 1966. 

Dialectics of Nature , 1940. 

Ludwig Feuerbach , 1941. 

The Origin of the Family , Private Property and the State , 1942. 

Socialism: Utopian and Scientific , 1935. 

Marx and Engels. The German Ideology , 1947. 

Selected Correspondence , 1846-1895, 1942. 

Lenin. “Karl Marx”, in Lenin, The Teachings of Karl Marx , 1964. 

“ Left-Wing ” Communism , Infantile Disorder , 1940. 

Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, 1927. 

ILTurt Is to Done 7 1929. 

T/ie Proletarian Revolution and Renegade Kautsky , 1934. 









































































PHILOSOPHY 


THE OPEN PHILOSOPHY AND THE OPEN SOCIETY 
Maurice Cornforth 

Subtitled “A Reply to Dr. Karl Popper’s Refutation of Marxism,” 
this work is certain to draw a good deal of attention from students 
of contemporary philosophy. A trenchant and well-reasoned reply 
to the critics of Marx, the book pays special attention to the polemics 
of Professor Popper in his famous Open Society and Its Enemies. 
The central theme concerns the alleged “historicism” of Marx, and 
in this connection the author deals both with abstract questions of 
logic and the dialectic and with more concrete problems of democ- 
racy, freedom and socialism. The great significance of this work is 
that it pits a major Marxist writer, for the first time in English, 
against Dr. Popper, whose views form the philosophical basis for 
the widely-accepted assault on Marxism by Western social science. 

(A cloth edition of this hook is available at $8.50) 


Other New World Paperbacks 
About Philosophy 


WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY? by Howard Selsam 
DIALECTICS OF NATURE by Frederick Engels 
THE GERMAN IDEOLOGY by K. Marx and F. Engels 
SOCIALISM AND THE INDIVIDUAL by John Lewis 
READER IN MARXIST PHILOSOPHY, 

H. Selsam and H. Martel, eds. 

ANTI-DUHRING by Frederick Engels 
ECONOMIC AND PHILOSOPHIC MANUSCRIPTS OF 1844 
by Karl Marx, D. J. Struik, ed. 

DIDEROT: Interpreter of Nature, J. Kemp, ed. 

ILLUSION AND REALITY by Christopher Caudwell 
CAUSE, PRINCIPLE AND UNITY by Giordano Bruno 
THE LIFE AND TEACHING OF KARL MARX by J. Lewis 
THE MODERN PRINCE by Antonio Gramsci 
KARL MARX: THE EVOLUTION OF HIS THOUGHT 
by Roger Garaudy 


(nw-1) 

1.35 

(nw-5) 

2.25 

(nw-6) 

1.95 

(nw-14) 

1.00 

(nw-18) 

2.65 

(nw-21) 

2.45 

(nw-27) 

1.95 

(nw-37) 

2.25 

(nw-38) 

2.45 

(nw-39) 

1.95 

(nw-53) 

1.95 

(nw-78) 

1.85 

(nw-81) 

1.95 


Write for a complete catalog of New World Paperbacks 

INTERNATIONAL PUBLISHERS 


381 Park Avenue South, New York, N.Y. 10016